The Custom in the Shadow of the Formal Law: An Economic Analysis - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

About This Presentation
Title:

The Custom in the Shadow of the Formal Law: An Economic Analysis

Description:

The Custom in the Shadow of the Formal Law: An Economic Analysis Gani Aldashev, Imane Chaara, Jean-Philippe Platteau, and Zaki Wahhaj Centre for Research in ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:229
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 125
Provided by: imane
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: The Custom in the Shadow of the Formal Law: An Economic Analysis


1
The Custom in the Shadow of the Formal Law An
Economic Analysis
  • Gani Aldashev, Imane Chaara, Jean-Philippe
    Platteau, and Zaki Wahhaj
  • Centre for Research in Development Economics
    (CRED)
  • University of Namur

2
Outline of the presentation
  • Introduction/motivations
  • Description of the model
  • Results
  • A dynamic framework
  • Illustrations

3
Introduction
  • Legal Pluralism several law systems coexist

4
Introduction
  • Legal Pluralism several law systems coexist
  • ? legal system or formal law (formal
    institutions)

5
Introduction
  • Legal Pluralism several law systems coexist
  • ? legal system or formal law (formal
    institutions)
  • ? customary principles or informal rules
    (informal institutions)

6
Introduction
  • Legal Pluralism several law systems coexist
  • ? legal system or formal law (formal
    institutions)
  • ? customary principles or informal rules
    (informal institutions)

The formal law is intended for either replacing
1 or complementing 2 the informal rule.
7
Introduction
  • Legal Pluralism several law systems coexist
  • ? legal system or formal law (formal
    institutions)
  • ? customary principles or informal rules
    (informal institutions)

The formal law is intended for either replacing
1 or complementing 2 the informal rule. 1
legal pluralism is conceived of as a temporary
outcome
8
Introduction
  • Legal Pluralism several law systems coexist
  • ? legal system or formal law (formal
    institutions)
  • ? customary principles or informal rules
    (informal institutions)

The formal law is intended for either replacing
1 or complementing 2 the informal rule. 1
legal pluralism is conceived of as a temporary
outcome 2 legal pluralism is seen as a
permanent situation (different laws deal with
different matters)
9
Introduction
  • In the case in which legal pluralism is seen as a
    temporary outcome, substituting the formal for
    the informal law may obey two distinct
    rationales.

10
Introduction
  • In the case in which legal pluralism is seen as a
    temporary outcome, substituting the formal for
    the informal law may obey two distinct
    rationales.
  • formal law uniformizes, codifies and simplifies
    the customary rules and practices
  • ? informal rules appear to be  the foundations
    on which formal rules are built  (Knight 1992,
    North 1990)

11
Introduction
  • (2) formal law aims at bringing a change that
    the custom inhibits
  • ? formal and informal laws are seen as
    conflicting with each other

12
Introduction
  • Two different problems can arise when legal
    pluralism is intended to be temporary

13
Introduction
  • Two different problems can arise when legal
    pluralism is intended to be temporary
  • (1) There may be an uncertainty about whether
    the formal law or the custom actually applies.
  • ? Aoki 2001, Greif 2006
  • ? Knight 1992
  • ? Basu 2000

14
Introduction
  • (2) There may be manipulation of the state of
    legal
  • pluralism by the privileged group in societies
    strongly
  • differentieted in terms of power and social
    status.
  • Example laws providing for formal land rights or
    titles (Doornbos 1975, Glazier 1985, Barrows
    and Roth 1989, Berry 1993, Platteau 2000,
    Jacoby and Minten)

15
Introduction
  • Conventional view in literature
  • Except in cases where the statutory law is
    grounded in customary rules which it attends to
    formalize and simplify, legal pluralism tends to
    produce neutral or negative effects.

16
Introduction
  • In our research project
  • a more general approach of legal pluralism

17
Introduction
  • In our research project
  • a more general approach of legal pluralism
  • in reality, customary rules are continuously
    evolving.
  • the transformation of customs may partly occur as
    a result of the existence of statutory laws which
    have the effect of conferring a stronger
    bargaining position on some particular section(s)
    of the population.

18
Introduction
  • In our research project
  • a more general approach of legal pluralism
  • in reality, customary rules are continuously
    evolving.
  • the transformation of customs may partly occur as
    a result of the existence of statutory laws which
    have the effect of conferring a stronger
    bargaining position on some particular section(s)
    of the population.
  • ?  local landholding systems are not the
    expression of an unchanging traditional law,
    but the fruit of a process of social change,
    which incorporates the effect of national
    legislation  (Lavigne Delville 2000)

19
Introduction
  • Punchline of the paper
  • Even if the formal law is not resorted to in an
    explicit manner the simple fact that it exists
    and that people whose interests concur in its
    prescriptions can threaten to use it, might
    create a situation in which its objectives are
    partly met.

20
Introduction
  • Punchline of the paper
  • Even if the formal law is not resorted to in an
    explicit manner, the simple fact that it exists
    and that people whose interests concur in its
    prescriptions can threaten to use it, might
    create a situation in which its objectives are
    partly met.

In this case - we may observe a permanent
coexistence of the two types of law even when the
intent of the legislator is to substitute the
formal law for the custom.
21
Introduction
  • Punchline of the paper
  • Even if the formal law is not resorted to in an
    explicit manner, the simple fact that it exists
    and that people whose interests concur in its
    prescriptions can threaten to use it, might
    create a situation in which its objectives are
    partly met.

In this case - we may observe a permanent
coexistence of the two types of law even when the
intent of the legislator is to substitute the
formal law for the custom. - legal pluralism may
obtain as a self-perpetuating equilibrium outcome
of strategic interactions between arbiters and
claimants.
22
Introduction
  • Our approach differs from the literature on the
    economic analysis of law in three respects
  • the study of customary judges behavior
  • the study of the mechanism through which the
    customary law evolves as the formal law gets
    introduced or changed
  • the role of inequality is adressed

23
Introduction
  • Our approach differs from the literature on the
    economic analysis of law in three respects
  • the study of customary judges behavior
  • the study of the mechanism through which the
    customary law evolves as the formal law gets
    introduced or changed
  • the role of inequality is adressed
  • BUT we remain in the tradition of the economic
    analysis of law by
  • modelling the customary judge as a rational
    agent maximizing his uility
  • assuming that this utility arises from prestige
    motives and from the desire to write a decision
    that is close to the customary judge's
    preferences

24
Introduction
  • Alternative dispute resolution (ADR)
  • use of arbitration or mediation
  • The reality of developing countries severely
    limits the applicability of the existing analysis
    of ADR
  • developped and developing countries differ in
    terms of legal integration
  • competition mechanism cannot be easily
    translated into developing countries' setting

25
Description of the model
  • 3 agents R, P and M

26
Description of the model
  • 3 agents R, P and M
  • Possible verdicts ? 0,1
  • 0 being the most favourable verdict for R
  • 1 being the most favourable verdict for P

27
Description of the model
  • 3 agents R, P and M
  • Possible verdicts ? 0,1
  • 0 being the most favourable verdict for R
  • 1 being the most favourable verdict for P
  • The mediator M he has a preferred verdict I
    the communitys dominant custom at the present
    time.

28
Description of the model
  • 3 agents R, P and M
  • Possible verdicts ? 0,1
  • 0 being the most favourable verdict for R
  • 1 being the most favourable verdict for P
  • The mediator M he has a preferred verdict I
    the communitys dominant custom at the present
    time.
  • The mediator chooses a verdict vM ? 0,1.
    Therefore, the interval is his strategy set.

29
Description of the model
  • The formal judge

30
Description of the model
  • The formal judge
  • Reasons of the unpredictability of the formal
    judges verdict vF
  • asymetries of information
  • existence of several bodies of law available to
    the formal judge
  • the subjectivity of the judge

31
Description of the model
  • The formal judge
  • Reasons of the unpredictability of the formal
    judges verdict vF
  • asymetries of information
  • existence of several bodies of law available to
    the formal judge
  • the subjectivity of the judge
  • cR and cP capture the administrative cost of
    going to a formal court.

32
Description of the model
  • Once the dispute is resolved, the players
    participate in a social exchange game

33
Description of the model
  • Once the dispute is resolved, the players
    participate in a social exchange game
  • the agent who appeals to the formal law is
    excluded

34
Description of the model
  • Once the dispute is resolved, the players
    participate in a social exchange game
  • the agent who appeals to the formal law is
    excluded
  • all non-excluded agents participate in the
    production of a public good

35
Description of the model
  • Once the dispute is resolved, the players
    participate in a social exchange game
  • the agent who appeals to the formal law is
    excluded
  • all non-excluded agents participate in the
    production of a public good
  • Q(Z) is the benefit of the public good (Z A, AR
    , AP)

36
Description of the model
  • Once the dispute is resolved, the players
    participate in a social exchange game
  • the agent who appeals to the formal law is
    excluded
  • all non-excluded agents participate in the
    production of a public good
  • Q(Z) is the benefit of the public good (Z A, AR
    , AP)
  • Cost-sharing rule each non excluded agent K
    contributes CK(Z) to the public good (K R, P or
    M)

37
Description of the model
  • Once the dispute is resolved, the players
    participate in a social exchange game
  • the agent who appeals to the formal law is
    excluded
  • all non-excluded agents participate in the
    production of a public good
  • Q(Z) is the benefit of the public good (Z A, AR
    , AP)
  • Cost-sharing rule each non excluded agent K
    contributes CK(Z) to the public good (K R, P or
    M)
  • We assume Q(Z) CK(Z) gt 0, for any Z and K.

38
Description of the model
  • Ms utility is
  • Where X is the prestige in utility terms that the
    mediator acquires from having his verdict
    unchallenged

39
Description of the model
  • Rs utility is

40
Description of the model
  • Ps utility is

41
Timing of the game
  • One-shot sequential game
  • 3 players the mediator, the rich agent, the
    poor agent

42
Timing of the game
  • One-shot sequential game
  • 3 players the mediator, the rich agent, the
    poor agent
  • TIMING
  • The institutions of the formal court are set.

43
Timing of the game
  • One-shot sequential game
  • 3 players the mediator, the rich agent, the
    poor agent
  • TIMING
  • The institutions of the formal court are set.
  • M chooses verdict vM

44
Timing of the game
  • One-shot sequential game
  • 3 players the mediator, the rich agent, the
    poor agent
  • TIMING
  • The institutions of the formal court are set.
  • M chooses verdict vM
  • P decides whether to appeal to the formal court
    (F) if she chooses F, the community excludes
    her, the social game without P is played, and the
    payoffs of all parties are determined.

45
Timing of the game
  • One-shot sequential game
  • 3 players the mediator, the rich agent, the
    poor agent
  • TIMING
  • The institutions of the formal court are set.
  • M chooses verdict vM
  • P decides whether to appeal to the formal court
    (F) if she chooses F, the community excludes
    her, the social game without P is played, and the
    payoffs of all parties are determined.
  • Otherwise, R decides whether to bring the case to
    the formal court (F) if she chooses F, the
    community excludes her, the social game without R
    is played, and the payoffs of all parties are
    determined.

46
Timing of the game
  • One-shot sequential game
  • 3 players the mediator, the rich agent, the
    poor agent
  • TIMING
  • The institutions of the formal court are set.
  • M chooses verdict vM
  • P decides whether to appeal to the formal court
    (F) if she chooses F, the community excludes
    her, the social game without P is played, and the
    payoffs of all parties are determined.
  • Otherwise, R decides whether to bring the case to
    the formal court (F) if she chooses F, the
    community excludes her, the social game without R
    is played, and the payoffs of all parties are
    determined.
  • Otherwise, both parties accept the verdict vM,
    the social game without exclusion is played and
    the payoffs of all parties are determined.

47
Equilibrium
  • We solve by backward induction

48
Equilibrium
  • We solve by backward induction

0
49
Equilibrium
  • We solve by backward induction

50
Equilibrium
  • We solve by backward induction
  • The case will go unappealed iff vM ? (I , I)

51
Equilibrium
  • We solve by backward induction
  • The case will go unappealed iff vM ? (I , I)

52
Equilibrium
  • We solve by backward induction
  • The case will go unappealed iff vM ? (I , I)

Where R is indifferent
Where P is indifferent
53
Equilibrium
  • We solve by backward induction
  • The case will go unappealed iff vM ? (I , I)

54
Equilibrium
  • We solve by backward induction
  • The case will go unappealed iff vM ? (I , I)

55
Equilibrium
  • (a) I lt I
  • A critical verdict value at which the judges
    payoff from letting go equals that of keeping the
    case  in  is given by the following equation
  • If lt I, M lets the case go to the formal
    court

56
Equilibrium
  • (a) I lt I
  • A critical verdict value at which the judges
    payoff from letting go equals that of keeping the
    case  in  is given by the following equation
  • If lt I, M lets the case go to the formal
    court

57
Equilibrium
  • (a) I lt I
  • A critical verdict value at which the judges
    payoff from letting go equals that of keeping the
    case  in  is given by the following equation
  • If lt I, M lets the case go to the formal
    court

? equilibrium vF
58
Equilibrium
  • (a) I lt I
  • A critical verdict value at which the judges
    payoff from letting go equals that of keeping the
    case  in  is given by the following equation
  • If gt I, M chooses I and thus keeps the case
    in.

59
Equilibrium
  • (a) I lt I
  • A critical verdict value at which the judges
    payoff from letting go equals that of keeping the
    case  in  is given by the following equation
  • If gt I, M chooses I and thus keeps the case
    in.

? equilibrium I
60
Equilibrium
  • (b) I gt I
  • A critical verdict value at which the judges
    payoff from letting go equals that of keeping the
    case  in  is given bythe following equation
  • If I lt v , M lets the case go to the formal
    court.

I
I
0
1
I
61
Equilibrium
  • (b) I gt I
  • A critical verdict value at which the judges
    payoff from letting go equals that of keeping the
    case  in  is given bythe following equation
  • If I lt v , M lets the case go to the formal
    court.

62
Equilibrium
  • (b) I gt I
  • A critical verdict value at which the judges
    payoff from letting go equals that of keeping the
    case  in  is given bythe following equation
  • If I lt v , M lets the case go to the formal
    court.

63
Equilibrium
  • (b) I gt I
  • A critical verdict value at which the judges
    payoff from letting go equals that of keeping the
    case  in  is given by the following equation
  • If I gt v , M chooses I and thus keeps the case
    in.

v
64
Equilibrium
  • (b) I gt I
  • A critical verdict value at which the judges
    payoff from letting go equals that of keeping the
    case  in  is given by the following equation
  • If I gt v , M chooses I and thus keeps the case
    in.

65
Equilibrium
  • The equilibrium is

66
Equilibrium
67
Comparative statics
  • Proposition 1
  • An increase in f, the mean verdict of the formal
    judge, raises both I and I, the respective
    thresholds at which the poor agent and the
    rich agent are indifferent between an informal
    resolution of the conflict and an appeal to the
    formal court.

68
Comparative statics
  • Proposition 1
  • An increase in f, the mean verdict of the formal
    judge, raises both I and I, the respective
    thresholds at which the poor agent and the
    rich agent are indifferent between an informal
    resolution of the conflict and an appeal to the
    formal court.

69
Comparative statics
  • Proposition 1
  • An increase in f, the mean verdict of the formal
    judge, raises both I and I, the respective
    thresholds at which the poor agent and the
    rich agent are indifferent between an informal
    resolution of the conflict and an appeal to the
    formal court.
  • An increase in f, which corresponds to a
    decrease in the variance of the formal verdict,
    raises I and decreases I.

70
Comparative statics
  • Proposition 1
  • An increase in f, the mean verdict of the formal
    judge, raises both I and I, the respective
    thresholds at which the poor agent and the
    rich agent are indifferent between an informal
    resolution of the conflict and an appeal to the
    formal court.
  • An increase in f, which corresponds to a
    decrease in the variance of the formal verdict,
    raises I and decreases I.

71
Comparative statics
  • Proposition 1
  • (ii) An increase in cP, the cost of access to the
    formal court for the poor agent, decreases his
    threshold verdict I. Similarly, an increase in
    cR, the cost of access to the formal court for
    the rich agent, increases his threshold verdict
    I.

72
Comparative statics
  • Proposition 1
  • (ii) An increase in cP, the cost of access to the
    formal court for the poor agent, decreases his
    threshold verdict I. Similarly, an increase in
    cR, the cost of access to the formal court for
    the rich agent, increases his threshold verdict
    I.

73
Comparative statics
  • Proposition 1
  • (ii) An increase in cP, the cost of access to the
    formal court for the poor agent, decreases his
    threshold verdict I. Similarly, an increase in
    cR, the cost of access to the formal court for
    the rich agent, increases his threshold verdict
    I.

74
Comparative statics
  • Proposition 1
  • (iii) An increase in the net benefit from the
    social game, expands the interval (I , I) in
    which both parties are satisfied with the verdict
    of the mediator.

75
Comparative statics
  • Proposition 1
  • (iii) An increase in the net benefit from the
    social game, expands the interval (I , I) in
    which both parties are satisfied with the verdict
    of the mediator.

I
I
76
Comparative statics
  • Proposition 2
  • An increase in X, the prestige associated with
    mediating a case, raises , the upper
    threshold above which the mediator lets the case
    go to the formal court and lowers , the
    corresponding lower threshold.

1
0
I
77
Comparative statics
  • Proposition 2
  • An increase in X, the prestige associated with
    mediating a case, raises , the upper
    threshold above which the mediator lets the case
    go to the formal court and lowers , the
    corresponding lower threshold.

1
0
I
78
Comparative statics
  • Proposition 2
  • An increase in X, the prestige associated with
    mediating a case, raises , the upper
    threshold above which the mediator lets the case
    go to the formal court and lowers , the
    corresponding lower threshold.

1
0
I
I
I
79
Comparative statics
  • Proposition 2
  • An increase in X, the prestige associated with
    mediating a case, raises , the upper
    threshold above which the mediator lets the case
    go to the formal court and lowers , the
    corresponding lower threshold.

1
0
I
I
I
80
Comparative statics
  • Proposition 2
  • An increase in X, the prestige associated with
    mediating a case, raises , the upper
    threshold above which the mediator lets the case
    go to the formal court and lowers , the
    corresponding lower threshold.

1
0
I
I
I
81
Comparative statics
  • Proposition 2
  • An increase in X, the prestige associated with
    mediating a case, raises , the upper
    threshold above which the mediator lets the case
    go to the formal court and lowers , the
    corresponding lower threshold.

82
Comparative statics
  • Proposition 2
  • An increase in X, the prestige associated with
    mediating a case, raises , the upper
    threshold above which the mediator lets the case
    go to the formal court and lowers , the
    corresponding lower threshold.

83
Comparative statics
  • Proposition 2
  • An increase in X, the prestige associated with
    mediating a case, raises , the upper
    threshold above which the mediator lets the case
    go to the formal court and lowers , the
    corresponding lower threshold.

1
84
Comparative statics
  • Proposition 2
  • An increase in X, the prestige associated with
    mediating a case, raises , the upper
    threshold above which the mediator lets the case
    go to the formal court and lowers , the
    corresponding lower threshold.

85
Comparative statics
  • Proposition 2
  • An increase in X, the prestige associated with
    mediating a case, raises , the upper
    threshold above which the mediator lets the case
    go to the formal court and lowers , the
    corresponding lower threshold.

86
Comparative statics
  • Proposition 2
  • (ii) An increase in the net gain to the mediator
    from the participation of the rich agent in the
    social game lowers Correspondingly, an
    increase in the net gain to the mediator from the
    participation of the poor agent in the social
    game, increases .

87
Comparative statics
  • Proposition 2
  • (ii) An increase in the net gain to the mediator
    from the participation of the rich agent in the
    social game lowers Correspondingly, an
    increase in the net gain to the mediator from the
    participation of the poor agent in the social
    game, increases .

88
Comparative statics
  • Proposition 2
  • (ii) An increase in the net gain to the mediator
    from the participation of the rich agent in the
    social game lowers Correspondingly, an
    increase in the net gain to the mediator from the
    participation of the poor agent in the social
    game, increases .

v
0
I
1
89
Comparative statics
  • Proposition 2
  • (ii) An increase in the net gain to the mediator
    from the participation of the rich agent in the
    social game lowers Correspondingly, an
    increase in the net gain to the mediator from the
    participation of the poor agent in the social
    game, increases .

v
0
I
1
90
Dynamic framework
  • Community size matters
  • Y (n) increasing and concave
  • X (n) increasing and concave

91
Dynamic framework
  • Community size matters
  • Y (n) increasing and concave
  • X (n) increasing and concave
  • The community consists of N individuals either
    rich or poor.

92
Dynamic framework
  • Community size matters
  • Y (n) increasing and concave
  • X (n) increasing and concave
  • The community consists of N individuals either
    rich or poor.
  • The population is heterogenous. The agents differ
    in terms of their outside option.
  • F(?) is the fraction of the population whith a
    per period outside option below ?.

93
Dynamic framework
  • Community size matters
  • Y (n) increasing and concave
  • X (n) increasing and concave
  • The community consists of N individuals either
    rich or poor.
  • The population is heterogenous. The agents differ
    in terms of their outside option.
  • F(?) is the fraction of the population whith a
    per period outside option below ?.
  • In any period, a fraction d of the population is
    engaged in disputes.

94
Dynamic framework
  • Community size matters
  • Y (n) increasing and concave
  • X (n) increasing and concave
  • The community consists of N individuals either
    rich or poor.
  • The population is heterogenous. The agents differ
    in terms of their outside option.
  • F(?) is the fraction of the population whith a
    per period outside option below ?.
  • In any period, a fraction d of the population is
    engaged in disputes.
  • The informal judge chooses a unique within
    any period t.

95
Dynamic framework
  • Given , a threshold value for which the
    poor agent is indifferent between choosing the
    informal and the formal court is given by

96
Dynamic framework
  • Let

H(n,v)
n, community size
97
Dynamic framework the steady state
  • And

98
Dynamic framework the steady state
  • And
  • If , a process of exclusion will
    make the population shrink until the size .

99
Dynamic framework the steady state
  • And
  • If , a process of exclusion will
    make the population shrink until the size .
  • If , the exclusion process will
    never begin.

100
Dynamic framework the steady state
  • A change in any of the parameters
    affects for each n and v and gives rise
    to a new steady state.

101
Dynamic framework the steady state
  • A change in any of the parameters
    affects for each n and v and gives rise
    to a new steady state.

102
Dynamic framework the steady state
  • A change in any of the parameters
    affects for each n and v and gives rise
    to a new steady state.

103
Dynamic framework
  • The choice of is endogenous to the strategy
    of the informal judge. The custom that maximises
    the steady-state level of utility for the
    informal judge is given by

104
Dynamic framework comparative statics
  • Proposition 4

105
Dynamic framework
  • If it is too costly for the informal judge to
    adapt the custom, he will choose ,
    which will lead to the exodus of all the poor
    people of the community. In this case, we have

106
Dynamic framework the effect of inequality
  • The optimal choice of law for the informal judge
    depends on the distribution of outside options in
    the poor section of the community.
  • Lets take 2 different distributions

107
Dynamic framework the effect of inequality
  • The two effects of an increase in inequality are
    described in the following graphs

108
Dynamic framework the effect of inequality
  • Proposition 5
  • The impact of increasing inequality on the custom
    can be decomposed into two effects.
  • First, the pivoting of the distribution of
    outside options tends to make the custom less
    favorable to the poor.
  • Second, the shift in the distribution makes the
    custom more or less pro-poor, depending on
    whether the outside option of the individual who
    is indifferent between the two legal systems in
    the initial steady-state gains or loses in the
    redistribution.

109
Welfare analysis
  • The aggregate social welfare of the poor
    individuals in the population is given by

110
Welfare analysis
  • The aggregate social welfare of the poor
    individuals in the population is given by
  • The marginal effect on social welfare of a
    pro-poor legal reform is

111
Welfare analysis
  • The aggregate social welfare of the poor
    individuals in the population is given by
  • The marginal effect on social welfare of a
    pro-poor legal reform is
  • ? A legal reform that makes the formal law more
    favourable to the poor has three distinct effects
    on the welfare of the poor.

112
Welfare analysis
  • Under what conditions a moderate pro-poor reform
    can be superior to a radical reform?
  • Proposition 6
  • If the elasticity of the marginal benefit of the
    scial game with respect to the size of the
    community is below 1 and utility is linear in the
    outcome of a dispute, then either abiding by the
    custom or carrying out a radical reform dominates
    a moderate reform in the formal law in terms of
    the social welfare of the poor.

113
Welfare analysis
  • If the net benefit from the social exchange game
    is sufficiently sensitive to the size of the
    community and if the utility function is
    sufficiently concave, the social welfare function
    is concave, implying that the implementation of a
    moderate law is the optimal reform.

114
Illustrations
  • The case of womens inheritance rights in the
    Senegal river valley

115
Illustrations
  • The case of womens inheritance rights in the
    Senegal river valley
  • Muslim population
  • Quranic prescription vs. customary principle

116
Illustrations
  • The case of womens inheritance rights in the
    Senegal river valley
  • Muslim population
  • Quranic prescription vs. customary principle
  • Important benefits from the social game for women

117
Illustrations
  • The case of womens inheritance rights in the
    Senegal river valley
  • Muslim population
  • Quranic prescription vs. customary principle
  • Important benefits from the social game for women
  • Over the last decade, the cost of being excluded
    from the social game has fallen

118
Illustrations
  • The case of womens inheritance rights in the
    Senegal river valley
  • Muslim population
  • Quranic prescription vs. customary principle
  • Important benefits from the social game for women
  • Over the last decade, the cost of being excluded
    from the social game has fallen
  • Educational and employment opportunities enable
    the more progressively-minded women to reveal
    preferences and to manifest opposition against
    customary practices.

119
Illustrations
  • The case of womens inheritance rights in the
  • Senegal river valley
  • Muslim population
  • Quranic prescription vs. customary principle
  • Important benefits from the social game for women
  • Over the last decade, the cost of being excluded
    from the social game has fallen
  • Educational and employment opportunities enable
  • the more progressively-minded women to reveal
    preferences and to manifest opposition against
    customary practices.
  • Recently, we observe an evolving practice of
    transfers to compensate women from their
    exclusion from inheritance.

120
  • In urban areas, when womens organisations are
    active, the fall in cost of access to court makes
    a recourse to it more attractive, potentially so
    much more attractive that the custom does not
    evolve at all.

121
  • In urban areas, when womens organisations are
    active, the fall in cost of access to court makes
    a recourse to it more attractive, potentially so
    much more attractive that the custom does not
    evolve at all.
  • In India (Jharkand), the Santal Pargana Tenancy
    Act (1949) recognises womens inheritance rights
    through marriage to a resident son-in-law but
    only if there is no male heir in the womans
    family. It had an effect because this law does
    not represent too radical a departure from
    custom.

122
  • In urban areas, when womens organisations are
    active, the fall in cost of access to court makes
    a recourse to it more attractive, potentially so
    much more attractive that the custom does not
    evolve at all.
  • In India (Jharkand), the Santal Pargana Tenancy
    Act (1949) recognises womens inheritance rights
    through marriage to a resident son-in-law but
    only if there is no male heir in the womans
    family. It had an effect because this law does
    not represent too radical a departure from
    custom.
  • Same conclusion in the case of Law N 98-750
    (1998) in the Côte dIvoire, which grants
    long-term leasehold rights to immigrant farmers.

123
  • When land becomes quite scarce, the custom
    evolves regressively (the preferred judgement of
    customary authority, I, moves closer to zero),
    with the result that women have more incentive to
    appeal to the modern court.

124
Conclusion
  • There may little gain from a strong state bent on
    imposing radical reforms even in the name of
    equity.
  • It may be more effective for the state to exert
    its influence in an indirect manner that does not
    overlook the custom.
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com