Critical Thinking about Morality and Introduction to Moral Theory - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 29
About This Presentation
Title:

Critical Thinking about Morality and Introduction to Moral Theory

Description:

We will consider this question, taking into account what Regan and ... like appealing to Makoto on what clothes, cosmetics, hair styles etc. are fashionable) ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:491
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 30
Provided by: coh4
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: Critical Thinking about Morality and Introduction to Moral Theory


1
Critical Thinking about Morality and Introduction
to Moral Theory
  • 2006 Makoto Suzuki

2
Aims of Day 2
  • In this philosophy class, we will examine various
    moral positions to know whether they are correct.
  • However, you might wonder how to do this.
  • We will consider this question, taking into
    account what Regan and Timmons say.

3
Tom Regan on Ways Not to Answer Moral Qs 1.
Irrelevance of Personal Preferences
  • Practice Concise Summary of the Premises
    (Reasons)
  • Regan (on p.5) argues that moral right and wrong
    cannot be determined just by finding out about
    someones personal preferences because moral
    judgments are not just expressions of personal
    preference. What are the two reasons for this?
  • While different persons expressions of personal
    preferences cannot deny each other, different
    persons moral judgments can deny each other.
    (See Jack-Jill exchange on liking of Grateful
    Dead justness of war)
  • While it is not appropriate to press people for
    justifying their personal preferences, it is
    always appropriate to press people for justifying
    their moral judgments.

4
2. Irrelevance of What a Person Think
  • Regan (on p.6) argues that a persons thinking
    something right or wrong does not make it so
    because his moral claims are not reports of what
    he thinks. Why?
  • One persons report of what he thinks cannot
    contradict another persons report of what she
    thinks. For they describe different things. In
    contrast, one persons moral claim can contradict
    another persons moral claim.
  • Regan illustrates this point with the
    Bonnie-Clyde exchange.

5
3. Irrelevance of Statistics
  • On pp.6-7, Regan argues that what all or most
    people think does not settle moral issues. Why?
  • It is odd to think that the rightness or
    wrongness of actions changes as peoples view
    changes.
  • Regan asks you, for example, As peoples view on
    capital punishment changes, does it get right (or
    wrong)?
  • In general, even what all people think cannot
    make it so everyone can be mistaken. (E.g.,
    everyone was mistaken about the shape of the
    earth.) Why do you think morality is any
    different?

6
Arguments from Consensus
  • Regan thus points out that arguments from
    consensus is often fallacious.
  • Arguments from consensus take the following
    general form
  • When most people agree on a claim about a subject
    matter S, the claim is often true.
  • p is a claim most people make about S.
  • ??????????????
  • p is true.

7
4. Problems about Appeal to Authority
  • Appeal to authority is often indispensable to
    know truths. For example, we novices generally
    accept what physics or chemistry texts say,
    depending on the authority of the authors as
    scientists. Example of Appeal to Authority
  • World-renowned physicist Stephen Hawking says
    that the condition of the universe at the instant
    of the Big Bang was more highly ordered than it
    is today. In view of Hawkings stature in the
    scientific community, we should conclude that
    this description of the universe is correct.

8
Conditions on ProperAppeals to Authority
  • The argument appeals to an expert or experts in
    the area of knowledge under consideration (it is
    not like appealing to Makoto on what clothes,
    cosmetics, hair styles etc. are fashionable)
  • 2. There is agreement among the experts in the
    area of knowledge under consideration
  • 3. There is no good reason to suspect that the
    expert appealed to is biased on the particular
    issue in question.
  • Does appeal to moral authority satisfy these
    three conditions?

9
Appeal to the Authority of the Authors/Interpreter
s of Religious Texts
  • In moral contexts, the appealed authority tends
    to be religious.
  • If we can use religious authorities as moral
    authorities to settle moral disputes, that is
    convenient.
  • However, as Regan points out (on p.7), there are
    several problems haunting this appeal to
    authority.
  • Lets consider these problems in connection to
    homosexuality.
  • This glance at homosexuality is an illustration,
    and it is not meant to settle whether homosexual
    acts are permissible.

10
Problems Haunting the Use of Religious Texts
  • There are many religions and their sects.
    Therefore, if their texts give us different
    ethical teachings, we have to show which
    religious sect, if any, is true. And in many
    cases, these texts actually differ in their
    ethical teachings.
  • Ex. The texts of Judeo-Christian-Islamic
    religions seem to condemn homosexuality, but many
    non-theistic religions, such as ancient Greek or
    Roman religions and many sects of Buddhism, do
    not seem to condemn homosexuality.

11
Problems Haunting the Use of Religious Texts
  • 2. It is often difficult to determine which
    interpretation of the text in question is
    correct.
  • Religious texts are often mysteriously vague.
  • Even if we agree what the text says, we might
    disagree on what their ethical implications are.
  • If there are more than one authoritative texts in
    a religious sect, sometimes they seem to
    contradict each other.
  • As for homosexuality and the Bible the Old
    Testament seems to condemn it. (We will see this
    later.) In the New testament, though Jesus
    himself does not condemn homosexuality, Paul
    (alone) appears to do so. (1 Corinthians 69 1
    Timothy 110). But some interpreters in the 20th
    century question this orthodox interpretation.

12
Problems Haunting the Use of Religious Texts
  • 3. Religious texts, esp. old ones, often give us
    more than we bargain for.
  • Let me exemplify this point in relation to the
    Bible and homosexuality.
  • Leviticus 1822 says You may not lie with a man
    as with a woman it is an abomination.

13
E.g. Leviticus
  • However, Leviticus also gives lengthy
    instructions for diet, hygiene, treating leprosy,
    detailed requirements concerning burnt offerings,
    an elaborate routine for dealing with
    menstruating women.
  • There are a number of rules about the daughters
    of priests, including the notation that if they
    play the whore, they shall be burned alive
    (219).
  • Leviticus forbids eating fat (723), letting a
    woman into church until 42 days after giving
    birth (124-5), and seeing your uncle naked,
    which is also called an abomination (1814, 26).
  • It says that a beard must have square corners
    (1927) and that we may purchase slaves from
    neighborhood states (2544).

14
Problems Haunting the Use of Religious Texts
  • If someone condemns homosexuality based on the
    authority of the text, he has to either (1)
    accept these other teachings or (2) show the
    reasons why we do not have to obey them while we
    should obey the text on homosexuality.
  • Such a dilemma is not limited to homosexuality or
    the Bible. It also occurs in relation to other
    issues and other religious texts.
  • Caution (2) is unavailable if one takes the text
    to be
  • the exact words given by the God or by the
    religious authority that he or she believes in
    and,
  • applied in entirety by the God or the authority
    to our situation and,
  • not retracted even in part by the God or the
    authority.

15
Continued
  • Taking (2) means explaining why the particular
    passages one accepts the passage on
    homosexuality in this case are authoritative
    (in relation to our situation) while the passages
    he discards are not.
  • For example, suppose he claims that the
    problematic passages on eating fat, slavery
    etc. in Leviticus do not correctly represent
    Gods dictate while the passage on homosexuality
    does. Then, he needs to provide the reason why he
    can say so.
  • If the reason is a moral reason independent of
    religious texts, he ultimately bases his ethical
    view not on the authority of the texts but on the
    moral reason.

16
How Can We Know Correct Moral Views?
  • On pp.8-11, Regan lists six positive proposals
    about how to approach moral issues.
  • Make relevant concepts clear
  • Take into account all relevant information
  • Be logically consistent
  • Give the same judgment when there is no relevant
    difference Formal Justice
  • Be cool (Well, I would rather say, Cool head,
    warm heart.)
  • Seek for valid moral principles
  • The first three are conditions for study of any
    subject whatsoever the last three are probably
    specific to moral inquiry.

17
1. Make the question and the view clear!
  • Suppose that unbeknownst to him, Mike is a
    sleepwalker, and while he is sleeping, he drives
    his car and parks the car in the area where one
    is legally prohibited from parking.
  • Is Mike responsible?
  • Well, the correct answer depends on what this
    question means. For example, depending on what
    responsible here means, the correct answer will
    be different.
  • If responsible means having the legal duty (to
    pay the bill for the illegal parking), the
    correct answer is probably Yes, he is
    responsible.
  • If responsible means morally blameworthy,
    probably the correct answer is No, he is not
    responsible.
  • If responsible means trustworthy, we cannot
    tell yes or no from the example.

18
Continued
  • Without knowing what questions or moral views
    mean, you cannot properly evaluate them.
  • Therefore, before trying to examine a moral
    question or a moral view, you need to make it
    clear.
  • In the above example, we should ask the
    questioner to define what he means by
    responsible.

19
Defining a Complex Concept Conceptual Analysis
(Regan, section 2, pp. 3-4)
  • As for a complex concept, you can make it clear
    by analyzing the concept into the elements that
    constitute the concept, i.e., setting out the
    conditions for the application of the concept.
  • For example, the complex concept of bachelor is
    probably analyzed as follows
  • Something is a bachelor if and only if (1) it is
    a person, (2) it is male, (3) it is not married,
    and (4) it is an adult.
  • According to this analysis, the concept of
    bachelor is constituted by four elements or
    conditions.
  • For obvious reasons, philosophers call this
    activity conceptual analysis.

20
Conditions Necessary v. Sufficient,
  • In the sentence One is a bachelor if and only if
    , if and only if means that is a necessary and
    sufficient condition for being a bachelor.
  • X is a necessary condition for Y just in case X
    must occur in order for Y to occur.
  • That is, you cannot have Y without X.
  • In other words, Y only if X.
  • Being male is a necessary condition for being a
    bachelor. One is a bachelor only if he is male.
  • X is a sufficient condition for Y just in case Y
    must occur if X occurs.
  • That is, you cannot have X without Y.
  • In other words, Y if X (or, if X then Y).
  • Being a bachelor is a sufficient condition for
    being male. One is male if he is a bachelor.

21
Necessary and Sufficient Condition
  • X is a necessary and sufficient condition for Y
    just in case X is both a necessary condition and
    a sufficient condition for Y.
  • That is, just in case both X must occur in order
    for Y to occur, and Y must occur in order for X
    to occur.
  • In other words, X if and only if Y.
  • Being a person, male, unmarried and an adult is
    jointly a necessary and sufficient condition for
    being a bachelor.
  • Conceptual analysis strives to state a necessary
    and sufficient condition for a given concept.

22
Test yourself Necessary v. Sufficient Conditions
  • The presence of water is a condition for it to
    rain.
  • Being a plane closed figure is a condition for
    being a triangle.
  • An object being red is a condition for the
    object being colored.
  • An object being a BMW is a condition for the
    object being a car.

necessary
necessary
sufficient
sufficient
23
2. Take into all the relevant considerations (a)
Consider both reasons for and against the moral
view
  • Suppose that Makoto considers whether death
    penalty is permissible.
  • In order to determine whether it is permissible,
    Makoto needs to take into account all the
    relevant considerations.
  • He needs to consider the reasons for this view,
    such as Death penalty deters crimes, Only
    death penalty gives some criminals what they
    deserve etc.
  • He also needs to consider the reasons against
    this view, such as Death penalty violates the
    dignity of the punished or Death penalty
    sometimes kills an innocent person, and this harm
    cannot be compensated etc.

24
(b) Consider possible objections to arguments for
your positions.
  • Not all arguments are good. Considering possible
    replies, we can evaluate whether they are good.
  • Suppose Makoto gives a following argument
  • Death penalty deters crimes more than any other
    punishment.
  • Therefore, death penalty is permissible.
  • What are the possible replies to this argument?
  • You can either (1) argue that the premise is
    incorrect (e.g., Statistics show that life
    imprisonment deters crimes more than death
    penalty), or (2) argue that the conclusion does
    not follow from the premise (e.g., Even if death
    penalty deters, it does not satisfy other
    necessary conditions for the permissibility of
    punishment, such as rehabilitating criminals, not
    being cruel etc.).

25
3. Be Consistent
  • Suppose that Makoto has the two general views
  • Killing any person whoever is wrong.
  • Death penalty is permissible.
  • Is there any problem?
  • These views are inconsistent. And inconsistent
    views cannot be all correct. Therefore, Makoto
    should either abandon or modify one of his views.
  • One way is to abandon the view that death penalty
    is permissible.
  • Another way is to modify the first view to this
    Killing any innocent person (knowingly) is
    wrong.
  • In general, consider whether your views can be
    consistently applied in combination with each
    other.

26
Mind consistency between general views and views
on particular cases
  • Suppose Makoto holds the view that killing
    oneself is always wrong.
  • However, watching a military movie, Makoto finds
    out that on reflection he thinks it is morally
    permissible or even recommendable that a person
    sacrifices his life in order to save others (say,
    by covering up a bomb with his body and armor,
    which otherwise would kill his defense-less
    comrades though he would survive due to the
    armor).
  • What does consistency require?
  • Consistency requires that Makoto should either
    drop the considered view about the case, or
    should modify the view that killing oneself is
    always wrong.

27
4. Give the Same Judgment When There Is No
Relevant Difference
  • Suppose that two students get the same grade in
    every exam.
  • Suppose that the instructor gives one of them a B
    (as his total grade) while he gives another a C
    (as her total grade).
  • The instructor might be morally criticized in
    that he gives different judgments when there is
    no morally relevant difference.
  • He can refute this challenge only by pointing to
    a morally relevant difference, such as a
    difference in the grade in some assignment or a
    difference in the contribution to the class
    discussion.
  • He needs to point to a relevant difference. For
    example, the difference in sex is not a relevant
    difference in this context.

28
An Application
  • Consider Thomsons Violinist case. (the text,
    p.221)
  • You wake up and find yourself back to back in bed
    with a famous unconscious violinist. He has been
    found to have a fatal kidney ailment. The Society
    of Music Lovers has found that you alone have the
    right blood type to help. They have therefore
    kidnapped you, and the violinists circulatory
    system was plugged into yours, so that your
    kidneys can be used to extract poisons from his
    blood. The doctor in the hospital tells you that
    to unplug you would be to kill him. In nine
    months he will recover from his ailment, and can
    safely be unplugged.
  • Is it permissible for you to unplug yourself?
  • If you says yes and are a pro-life person, here
    comes a challenge. Is there any relevant
    difference between unplugging the unconscious
    violinist and aborting a fetus? If no, even if a
    fetus is a person, it is permissible to abort him
    or her.

29
6. Seek for valid moral principles Introduction
to Moral Theory
  • As Timmons points out (pp.5-6), valid moral
    principles will both
  • explain why certain actions are right (or wrong),
    and
  • help us to arrive at justified moral verdicts
    about actions and rationally settle moral
    disputes. (See the inference on p.5)
  • As Timmons points out (pp.1-4), because these two
    are the practical and theoretical aims of moral
    theory, so moral theorists seek for valid moral
    principles.

30
Consider Whether A Valid Moral Principle Can
Explain Your Moral View
  • Suppose some people hold the view that because of
    racial differences, it is permissible for them to
    enslave other people.
  • One legitimate way to challenge this view is to
    demand the explanation of why racial differences
    matter.
  • It seems no plausible moral principle can explain
    the relevance of racial differences.
  • Now suppose Makoto holds the view that because
    of differences in academic achievement, it is
    permissible for him to grade students
    differently.
  • One legitimate way to challenge this is, again,
    to demand the explanation of why academic
    differences matter.
  • Makoto may well explain this by appealing to the
    moral principle of desert the principle of
    desert recommend that the instructor grade
    students according to their academic achievement.

31
Continued
  • If some plausible moral idea or principle can
    explain the moral view, the moral view is
    plausible to some extent.
  • If no plausible moral idea or principle can
    explain the moral view, the moral view is
    suspicious to some extent.

32
Deontic Categories v. Value Categories (Timmons,
7-10)
  • Concepts like right, wrong, obligatory,
    merely permissible/optional etc. are used to
    evaluate the morality of actions, i.e., what one
    can intentionally do. They are called deontic
    concepts.
  • For the basic deontic categories of actions, see
    Figure 1.1 on Timmons, p.9.
  • Concepts like good, bad and
    value-neutral/indifferent are primarily used to
    evaluate objects, feelings, character traits,
    consequences etc. They are called value concepts.
  • That is, other things than actions, e.g., a
    picture, a computer, suffering, can be good or
    bad, but only actions can be right or wrong.

33
The Structure of Moral Theory (Timmons, pp. 10-12)
  • Moral Theory has two parts theory of right
    conduct, and theory of value.
  • Theory of right conduct seeks for principles of
    right or wrong actions.
  • Theory of value seeks for principles of good or
    bad things.
  • See the components of moral theory on p.11.
  • In stating principles, moral theory tells how
    right or wrong actions relate to good or bad
    things.
  • For example, one type of theories of right
    conduct (called consequentialism) holds that
    actions are right if and only if the upshot would
    be the best if the action were taken.

34
Reading for Tuesday
  • Read
  • Hugo Adam Bedau, Capital Punishment, Chapter 5
    (pp.160-194) of the text
  • You do not have to read section 30 Equal justice
    and Capital Punishment, pp.188-190 because we
    will discuss this part on the next Thursday.
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com