A Study of Regret and Rejoicing in Decision-Making and a New MCDM Method - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

About This Presentation
Title:

A Study of Regret and Rejoicing in Decision-Making and a New MCDM Method

Description:

A Study of Regret and Rejoicing in Decision-Making and a New MCDM Method Xiaoting Wang and Evangelos Triantaphyllou College of Engineering and Department of Computer ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:92
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 28
Provided by: xiao94
Learn more at: http://www.csc.lsu.edu
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: A Study of Regret and Rejoicing in Decision-Making and a New MCDM Method


1
A Study of Regret and Rejoicing in
Decision-Making and a New MCDM Method
  • Xiaoting Wang and Evangelos Triantaphyllou
  • College of Engineering and Department of
    Computer Science
  • Louisiana State University
  • Baton Rouge, LA
  • INFORMS Annual Meeting, Seattle, WA
  • Nov. 4 - 7, 2007

2
Outline
  • Introduction and problem description
  • Previous studies on regret and rejoicing
  • Some regret models
  • The limitations of these regret models
  • A new method to assess regret and rejoicing
  • A new MCDM method based on regret and rejoicing
  • Concluding remarks

3
Introduction
  • Multi-criteria decision-making (MCDM)
  • A typical MCDM problem involves the evaluation of
    a finite number of alternatives in terms of a
    finite number of criteria which might be benefit
    or cost criteria.
  • The Decision Matrix
  • aij the performance value of the i-th
    alternative in terms of the j-th criterion
  • wj the weight of the j-th criterion

  • C r i t e r i a
  • C1 C2 ... Cn
  • (w1 w2 ... wn)
  • Alts. ------------------------------------
  • A1 a11 a12 ... a1n
  • A2 a21 a22 ... a2n
  • . . .
  • . . .
  • Am am1 am2 ... amn
  • Figure 1. A typical
    decision matrix

4
Problem description
  • The main factors in an MCDM problem
  • The performance values of the alternatives under
    the decision criteria.
  • The weights of the criteria.
  • Also emotional factors, like feeling of regret
    and rejoicing.
  • Why emotional factors matter?
  • It comes from the fact that humans often base
    their choices on comparisons across the
    alternatives under consideration and relative to
    what might have been under another choice
    Plous, 1993 Hastie and Dawes, 2001.
  • Example
  • Given two alternatives A1 and A2 and some
    decision criteria
  • Assume overall A1 gt A2 but a1k is worse than a2k
    for some criterion Ck.
  • Then the decision maker (DM) who chooses A1 and
    forgoes A2 may experience a certain level of
    regret because a1k lt a2k.
  • Sometimes, the regret feeling could be very
    strong and as result the DM may regret to have
    chosen A1 instead of A2.

5
Problem description
  • In order to avoid the above situation
  • the DM would want to anticipate the regret
    feeling and consider it in the decision-making
    process by making some tradeoffs for a more
    balanced alternative. He/she can predict the
    emotional consequences of different decision
    outcomes in advance, and opt for the choices that
    minimize the possibility of negative emotions.
  • The favorable feeling of rejoicing
  • can be considered as the inverse of regret and
    analyzed in an analogous manner as regret.
  • Note because of time constraint, only regret is
    discussed in the next sections. Rejoicing can be
    analyzed in an analogous manner.

6
Previous studies on regret and rejoicing
  • Multi-attribute utility analysis (MAUA)
  • One of the systematic MCDM method Kirkwood,
    1997.
  • The performance value of an alternative under
    each decision criterion is transferred into a
    utility value according to some utility
    functions.
  • The utility (a value between 0, 1) represents
    the preferability of the alternatives under each
    decision criterion.
  • Usually, the total utility of each alternative
    can be computed as a weighted sum such as

  • (1)
  • One key assumption for the utility model
  • DMs are rational Individuals which devoid of
    psychological influences or emotions Luce,
    1992.
  • Thus, DMs will always want to make choices that
    can maximize the utilities of the chosen
    alternatives.

7
Previous studies on regret and rejoicing
  • However, behavioral scientists have proved that
    it is not always appropriate to relate decision
    rationality to utility maximization Allais,
    1988 Ellsberg, 1961.
  • To broad the assumptions, some research has been
    made to incorporate behavioral issues into the
    decision making process, for example, regret and
    rejoicing.
  • Regret is defined as the painful sensation of
    recognizing that what is compares unfavorably
    with what might have been. Sugden, 1985.
    The converse experience of a favorable comparison
    between the two has been called rejoicing.
  • Next, some of the main regret models in the
    literature will be introduced.

8
Some regret models in the literature
  • The minimax regret model Savage, 1951

  • (2)
  • The Regret Theory of Bell and Loomes and Sugden
    (RT-B/LS) Loomes and Sugden, 1982 Bell, 1982
    and 1985

  • (3)
  • The Reference-Dependent Regret Model (RDRM)
    Kujawski, 2005

  • (4)
  • G(.), the regret-building function.

9
Limitations of these regret models
  • The minimax model
  • decides the selection of alternatives totally
    based on their regret values, it may lead to
    irrational choices.
  • The RT/B-LS and the RDRM model
  • They are based on the concept of utility
  • It is not always convenient for DMs to find a
    proper utility function that can appropriately
    transform performance values with different units
    into unit-less and additive utility values.
  • They quantify regret by using continuous
    functions.
  • How to determine the customizing parameters as
    the R and D in the regret function?
  • For different criteria, the DM may need to
    determine different values for the parameters.
  • Regret does not always change as a continuous
    variable. Usually people feel a certain level of
    regret when the difference between two compared
    items is beyond a threshold value or when one of
    the compared performance values is below an
    echelon value.
  • Example consider three students taking an exam.
  • Scores
    79, 70, 69.
  • Grades C, C, F.
  • Then we may have R(69, 70) gt R(70, 79)

10
Limitations of using continuous regret functions
  • Furthermore, decision criteria may be
    quantitative or qualitative. As emotional
    factors, regret and rejoicing are definitely
    qualitative aspects in decision problems.
  • It would be more appropriate to assess peoples
    anticipated regret/rejoicing feelings by using
    some proper linguistic terms rather than
    continuous numbers.
  • For qualitative aspects, the pairwise comparison
    approach proposed by Saaty (as part of the AHP
    method) Saaty, 1994 has received widespread
    attention.
  • In this approach, the DM is asked to select a
    linguistic statement from 9 statements that best
    describes his/her assessment for the comparison
    of two compared items (alternatives or criteria).
  • Next, some consistency tests are performed as it
    is possible to have estimated values from DMs
    with high levels of inconsistency.
  • Why choose 9 as the upper limit? Psychological
    experiments have shown that most individuals
    cannot simultaneously compare more than seven
    objects (plus or minus two) Miller, 1956.

11
A new method to assess regret and rejoicing
  • Here a similar pairwise approach is proposed
  • First, a scale similar to the Saaty scale is
    built as in Table 1 (on the next slide).
  • It has a finite set of linguistic choices with
    corresponding numerical values.
  • the DM can use this scale to assess his/her
    anticipated regret value for choosing one
    alternative over another under a specific
    decision criterion.
  • Example
  • Two alternatives Ai and Aj having aik and ajk
    in terms of a benefit criterion Ck.
  • R(aik, ajk) the true (more accurate) anticipated
    regret value for choosing aik and forgoing ajk.
  • r(aik, ajk) the estimated regret value chosen by
    the DM from Table 1.
  • R(aik, ajk) eijk r(aik, ajk), for any i, j
    1,2,3,,n. (5)
  • eijk is the error coefficient which is expected
    to be close to 0 assuming the DM is consistent
    and reasonable.
  • If aik,gt ajk, r(aik, ajk) 0. Otherwise, a
    linguistic expression need to be selected and the
    corresponding numerical value will be assigned to
    r(aik, ajk).

12
Table 1

Linguistic Expression Numerical Value
There is no distinguishable feeling of regret when choosing alternative Ai over alternative Aj. 0
The feeling of regret when choosing alternative Ai over alternative Aj is noticeable. 2
The feeling of regret when choosing alternative Ai over alternative Aj is high. 4
The feeling of regret when choosing alternative Ai over alternative Aj is very high. 6
The feeling of regret when choosing alternative Ai over alternative Aj is as high as it can be. 8
The numerical values of 1, 3, 5, and 7 are used when the decision maker cannot choose between two successive linguistic expressions from the above list of choices. 1, 3, 5, 7
13
Regret matrix
  • Given a decision problem with n alternatives and
    m criteria, the DM compares each alternative with
    all the others under each single criterion to
    build a regret matrix in terms of each criterion.
  • A regret matrix in terms of criterion Ck is
    defined as follows
  • Alts.
  • (A1 A2 ... Am)
  • Alts. ------------------------------------
  • A1 0 r12 ... r1m
  • A2 r21 0 ... r2m
  • . . . . .
  • Am rm1 rm2 ... 0
  • Figure 2. A
    regret matrix
  • Some relations about the entries of a regret
    matrix.
  • r(aik, aik) 0, for any i 1, 2, 3, , n.
  • If aik,gt ajk, then r(aik, ajk) 0, for any i, j
    1,2,3, ,n.

14
The additive transitivity property
  • The additive transitivity property
  • Suppose the performance values of three
    alternatives Ai, Aj, and Am under a benefit
    criterion Ck, are aik , ajk, and am, assuming
    aik gt ajk gt amk.
  • It is required that the anticipated regret values
    produced when compared them two at a time should
    satisfy an additive transitivity property defined
    as follows


  • (6)
  • Since R(.) r(.) e(.), then


  • (7)
  • where

15
The additive transitivity property
  • In terms of a specific criterion, if the DM is
    rational and consistent, then the error
    coefficients should be small.
  • The objective is to minimize the sum of squares
    of the error coefficients under the additive
    transitivity constraints.
  • Then, we have an optimization problem as follows

  • (8)
  • subject to
    (7)
  • where

16
A new method to assess regret and rejoicing
  • Solving the optimization problem to get
  • the error coefficients which produce the minimum
    value ,
  • the adjusted regret values R(.) which are also
    regarded as the more accurate regret values.
  • can also be used as a consistency
    criterion. The more consistent the estimated
    regret values are, the smaller this value will
    be. An acceptable value should be decided for the
    specific application at hand.
  • We can also check some other statistic values
    about the error coefficients, such as their
    average, the maximum, and the standard deviation
    etc., to determine if there is any significant
    inconsistency within the estimated values.
  • If the inconsistency between the estimated regret
    values is beyond a certain acceptable level, then
    the DM would be required to review his/her
    estimated regret values.

17
A new method to assess regret and rejoicing
  • Next, the overall regret value of alternative Ai
    in terms of the k-th criterion is defined as the
    average of the regret values produced when
    alternative Ai is compared with each of the other
    alternatives under the same criterion.
  • (9)
  • The overall regret value of alternative Ai in
    terms of all the criteria is defined as
  • (10)
  • Then, how to aggregate the regret and rejoicing
    values and the performance values of the
    alternatives together to get the final priority
    for each alternative?

18
A new MCDM method based on regret and rejoicing
  • Some previous studies had reported that some
    types of rank reversals may occur with some MCDM
    methods which use additive formulas to compute
    the final priorities of the alternatives, such as
    the AHP method and the revised AHP method Dyer
    and Wendell, 1985 Triantaphyllou, 2001.
  • (11)
  • A method known as the multiplicative AHP
    Lootsma, 1999 is immune to those ranking
    problems.
  • (12) (13)
  • By using the multiplicative formula, no matter
    how the decision matrix is normalized, the ratios
    of the alternatives performance values will be
    kept the same because the normalization factor is
    cancelled off in the multiplicative formula.

19
A new MCDM method based on regret and rejoicing
  • Thus, in the new MCDM method, the multiplicative
    formula is used to compute the final priority for
    each decision alternative.
  • Then, for decision making problems, when the set
    of alternatives is changed, all variation left is
    due to the regret and rejoicing effects and that
    could be justifiable as it would not be due to
    any mathematical artifacts.
  • Based on the above points, assume only
    considering the anticipated regret for a given
    MCDM problem which has m alternatives and n
    benefit decision criteria. The formula for
    computing the final overall priority for each
    alternative by using the multiplicative formula
    and the benefit to cost approach to deal with
    conflicting criteria will be as follows
  • (14)

20
A new MCDM method based on regret and rejoicing
  • For a more complex decision problem
  • m alternatives and n decision criteria with n1
    benefit criteria and (n-n1) cost criteria
  • Consider both the anticipated regret and
    rejoicing
  • The equation to compute the overall priority for
    each alternative is as follows
  • (15)
  • is the overall regret for choosing Ai under
    the benefit criteria
  • is the overall rejoicing for choosing Ai
    under the benefit criteria
  • is the overall performance value of Ai
    under the benefit criteria
  • and have the similar meaning
    as the above ones but now in terms of the cost
    criteria.

21
Why to satisfy the additive transitivity property?
  • Given is a symmetric decision problem where
    xgtygtz.
  • Table 3. A symmetric decision problem
  • Because of the symmetry of this decision problem,
    it is expected that the three alternatives should
    be ranked equivalently by a valid MCDM method
    when two of them are ranked at a time.
  • However, some regret model like the RT-B/LS model
    ranks these three alternatives in a cyclic way
    Kujawski, 2005. That is, A2gt A1, A3 gt A2, and
    A1gt A3.
  • The new method should not allow cyclic
    preferences to happen.

Criteria Criteria Criteria
Alternatives C1 C2 C3
A1 A2 A3 z x y y z x x y z
Weights 1/3 1/3 1/3
22
Why to satisfy the additive transitivity property?
  • Consider the task of ranking A1 and A2
  • The overall regret values for A1 and A2 are
  • (16)
  • (17)
  • The aggregated performance
  • The overall performance value for A1 and A2 are
  • (18) (19)
  • Only if
    then
  • That is, the additive transitivity property
    should be satisfied.

23
A summary of the new method
  • Step 1. Set up the scale and the linguistic terms
    for esimating the regret and rejoicing.
  • Step 2. Ask the DM to choose the best linguistic
    term that can assess his/her anticipated regret
    and rejoicing feeling independently and then to
    fill the entries for the regret and rejoicing
    matrixes.
  • Step 3. Build the objective function and the
    constraints which require the adjusted
    regret/rejoicing values to satisfy the additive
    transitivity property.
  • Step 4. Solve the optimization problem and get
    the error coefficients and the adjusted regret
    and rejoicing values.
  • Step 5. Check the value of Z and the error
    coefficients to see if there is any significant
    inconsistency within the estimated regret and
    rejoicing values. If the answer is yes, go to
    Step 6, else go to Step 7.
  • Step 6. Ask the DM to review the estimated regret
    and rejoicing values and repeat step 3-5 until
    there are no significant inconsistent estimated
    values.
  • Step 7. Use the adjusted regret and rejoicing
    values to compute the final overall priority for
    each alternative and rank them.

23
24
Concluding remarks
  • The properties of the new MCDM method are
  • Besides the usual benefit and cost criteria, this
    method is able to incorporate the effects of
    regret and rejoicing for DMs who value these
    emotional factors in MCDM situations.
  • The determination of regret and rejoicing effects
    is more reasonable and consistent with usual
    human behavior.
  • For the new method, rank reversals may occur only
    as result of readjusting the effects of regret
    and/or rejoicing when the set of the alternatives
    is altered.
  • The new method is able to deal with qualitative
    and quantitative criteria expressed in different
    units of measurement.
  • The new method does not allow cyclic preference
    to happen to a symmetric decision problem.
  • By using the new method, decision makers will
    have the flexibility to decide their own
    regret/rejoicing levels and the importance of
    these emotional factors in their decision-making
    process.

24
25
References
  • 1.Allais, M., (1988), The general theory of
    random choices in relation to the invariant
    cardinal utility function and the specific
    probability function, Risk, Decision and
    Rationality, in Munier, editor, pp. 231-291,
    Dordrecht, The Netherlands.
  • 2. Bell, D.E., (1982), Regret in Decision Making
    under Uncertainty, Operations Research, Vol.30,
    pp. 961-981
  • 3. Bell, D.E., (1985), Disappointment in
    decision making under uncertainty, Operations
    Research, Vol. 33, pp.1-27.
  • 4. Dyer, J.S., and R.E. Wendell, (1985), A
    Critique of the Analytic Hierarchy Process,
    Technical Report 84/85-4-24, Department of
    Management, the University of Texas at Austin,
    Austin, TX, U.S.A.
  • 5. Ellsberg, D. (1961), Risk, ambiguity and the
    Savage axioms, Quarterly Journal of Economics,
    Vol. 75, pp. 643-649.
  • 6. Hastie, R., and R.M. Dawes, (2001), Rational
    choice in an uncertain world, Sage Publications,
    Thousand Oaks, CA, USA.
  • 7. Kirkwood, C.W., (1997), Strategic Decision
    Making, Duxbury Press, Wadsworth Publishing
    Company, Belmont, Calif., USA.
  • 8. Kujawski, E., (2005), A reference-dependent
    regret model for deterministic tradeoff studies,
    Systems Engineering, Vol. 8, pp. 119-137.
  • 9. Loomes, G., and R. Sugden, (1982), Regret
    Theory an Alternative Theory of Rational Choice
    Under Uncertainty, The Economic Journal, Vol.
    92, pp.805-824.

26
References (Contd)
  • 10. Lootsma, F.A., (1999), "Multi-Criteria
    Decision Analysis via Ratio and Difference
    Judgment." Kluwer Academic Publishers, Applied
    Optimization Series, Vol. 29, Dordrecht, The
    Netherlands.
  • 11. Plous, S., (1993), The psychology of judgment
    and decision making, McGraw-Hill, New York, NY,
    U.S.A.
  • 12. Saaty, T.L., (1980), The Analytic Hierarchy
    Process, McGraw-Hill, New York, NY, U.S.A.
  • 13. Saaty, T.L., (1994), Fundamentals of Decision
    Making and Priority Theory with the AHP, RWS
    Publications, Pittsburgh, PA, U.S.A.
  • 14. Savage, L.J., (1951), The theory of
    statistical decision, Journal of American
    Statistical Association, Vol. 46, pp.55-67.
  • 15. Stam, A., and A.P.D. Silva, (1997),
    Stochastic Judgments in the AHP the measurement
    of rank reversal probabilities, Decision
    Sciences, Vol.28, pp.655-688.
  • 16. Triantaphyllou, E., (2000), Multi-Criteria
    Decision Making Methods A Comparative Study,
    Kluwer Academic Publishers, Boston, MA, USA.
  • 17. Triantaphyllou, E., (2001), Two New Cases of
    Rank Reversals when the AHP and Some of its
    Additive Variants are Used that do not Occur with
    the Multiplicative AHP, Multi-Criteria Decision
    Analysis, (May 2001 issue) Vol. 10, pp. 11-25.
  • 18. Luce, R.D., (1992), Where does subjective
    expected utility fail descriptively? Journal of
    Risk and Uncertainty, Vol. 5, pp. 5-27
  • 19. Mellers, B.A., (2000), Choice and the
    relative pleasure of consequences, Psychological
    bulletin, Vol. 126, pp. 910924.
  • 20. Miller, C.A., (1956), The magic number seven
    plus or minus two some limits on our capacity
    for processing information, Psychological
    Review, Vol. 13, pp. 81-97.

27
Thanks!
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com