VOTING POWER - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 38
About This Presentation
Title:

VOTING POWER

Description:

VOTING POWER IN THE ELECTORAL COLLEGE Weighted Voting Games The Electoral College is an example of a weighted voting game. Instead of each voter casting a single vote ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:93
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 39
Provided by: umbc
Category:
Tags: power | voting | voting

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: VOTING POWER


1
VOTING POWER
  • IN THE ELECTORAL COLLEGE

2
Weighted Voting Games
  • The Electoral College is an example of a weighted
    voting game.
  • Instead of each voter casting a single vote, each
    voter casts a block of votes, with some voters
    casting larger blocks and others casting smaller
    blocks.
  • Other examples
  • voting by disciplined party groups in multi-party
    parliaments (probably elected on the basis of
    proportional representa-tion)
  • balloting in old-style U.S. party nominating
    conventions under the unit rule
  • voting in the EU Council of Ministers, IMF
    council, etc.
  • voting by stockholders (holding varying amounts
    of stock).

3
Weighted Voting Games (cont.)
  • Weighted voting can be analyzed using the theory
    of simple games.
  • A simple game is a (voting or similar) situation
    in which every potential coalition (set of
    players/votes) can be deemed to be either winning
    or losing.
  • With respect to lawmaking power of the United
    States, the winning coalitions are
  • All coalitions including 218 House members, 51
    Senators, and the President, and also
  • All coalitions including 290 House members and 67
    Senators.
  • Including the Vice President, or 60 Senators
    excluding the Vice President in so far as
    filibustering is an option.

4
Weighted Voting Games (cont.)
  • With respect to weighted voting games, the most
    basic finding is that voting power is not the
    same as (and is not proportional to) voting
    weight in particular
  • voters with very similar (but not identical)
    weights may have very different voting power and
  • voters with quite different voting weights may
    have identical voting power.
  • In general, it is impossible to apportion voting
    power (as opposed to voting weights) in a
    refined fashion, especially within small
    groups.

5
Weighted Voting Example
  • Consider a country that uses proportional
    representation to elect members of parliament.
  • Duvergers law implies that the country will have
    a multi-party system.
  • Hotelling-Downs implies that the parties will be
    spread over the ideological spectrum and may
    receive rather similar vote shares.

6
Weighted Voting Example
  • Suppose that four parties receive these vote
    shares Party A, 27 Party B, 25 Party C, 24
    Party 24.
  • Seats are apportioned in a 100-seat parliament
    according some apportionment formula. In this
    case, the apportionment of seats is
    straight-forward
  • Party A 27 seats Party C 24 seats
  • Party B 25 seats Party D 24 seats
  • Seats (voting weights) have been apportioned in a
    way that is precisely proportional to vote
    support, but voting power has not been so
    apportioned (and cannot be).

7
Weighted Voting Example (cont.)
  • Since no party controls a majority of 51 seats, a
    governing coalition of two or more parties must
    be formed.
  • A partys voting power is based on its
    oppor-tunities to help create (or destroy)
    winning (governing) coalitions.
  • But, with a small number of parties, coalition
    possibilities -- and therefore differences in
    voting power -- are highly limited.

8
Weighted Voting Example (cont.)
  • A 27 seats B 25 seats C 24 seats D 24
    seats
  • Once the parties start negotiating, they will
    find that Party A has voting power that greatly
    exceeds its slight advantage in seats. This is
    because
  • Party A can form a winning coalition with any one
    of the other parties and
  • the only way to exclude Party A from a winning
    coalition is for Parties B, C, and D to form a
    three-party coalition.
  • The seat allocation (totaling 100 seats) is
    strategically equivalent to this much simpler
    allocation (totaling 5 seats)
  • Party A 2 seats
  • Parties B, C, and D 1 seat each
  • Total of 5 seats, so a winning coalition requires
    3 seats.
  • So the original seat allocation is strategically
    equivalent to one in which Party A has twice the
    weight of each of the other parties (which is not
    at all proportional to their vote shares).

9
Weighted Voting Example (cont.)
  • Suppose at the next election the vote and seat
    shares change a bit
  • Before Now
  • Party A 27 Party A 30
  • Party B 25 Party B 29
  • Party C 24 Party C 22
  • Party D 24 Party D 19
  • While the seats shares have only slightly
    changed, the strategic situation has changed
    fundamentally.
  • Party A can no longer form a winning coalition
    with Party D.
  • Parties B and C can now form a winning coalition
    by themselves.
  • The seat allocation is equivalent to this much
    simpler allocation
  • Parties A, B, and D 1 seat each
  • Party D 0 seats
  • Total of 3 seats, so a winning coalition requires
    2 seats.
  • Party A has lost voting power, despite gaining
    seats.
  • Party C has gained voting power, despite losing
    seats.
  • Party D has become powerless (a so-called dummy),
    despite retaining a substantial number of seats.

10
Weighted Voting Example (cont.)
  • In fact, the only possible strong simple games
    with 4 players are these two with simplified
    weights of (2,1,1,1) and (1,1,1,0),
  • plus the inessential game (1,0,0,0), in which
    one party holds a majority of seats (making all
    other parties dummies, so no coalition need be
    formed.
  • Expanding the number of players to five produces
    these additional possibilities (3,2,2,1,1),
    (3,1,1,1,1), (2,2,1,1), (1,1,1,1,1).
  • With 6 or more players coalition possibilities
    become much more numerous and complex.

11
Weighted Voting Example (cont.)
  • Returning to the four-party example, voting power
    would change further if the parliamentary
    decision rule were to change from simple majority
    to (say) 2/3 majority (like the old nominating
    rule in Democratic National Conven-tions).
  • Both before and after the election, all
    three-party coalitions, and no smaller
    coalitions, are winning coalitions (so all four
    parties are equally powerful).
  • In particular, under 2/3 majority rule, Party D
    is no longer a dummy after the election.
  • Thus, changing the decision rule reallocates
    voting power, even as voting weights (seats)
    remain the same.
  • Generally making the decision rule more demanding
    tends to equalize voting power.
  • In the limit, weighted voting is impossible under
    unanimity rule.

12
Weighted Voting Example (cont.)
  • A simple weighted majority voting game (with no
    ties) is a strong simple game, i.e.,
  • Given any complementary pair of coalitions, one
    is winning and the other is losing.
  • A (for example) 2/3 weighted majority voting game
    is no longer strong, i.e.,
  • Given some complementary pairs of coalitions,
    neither may be winning (both are blocking).

13
Power Indices
  • Several power indices have been pro-posed to
    quantify the share of power held by each player
    in simple games.
  • These particularly include
  • the Shapley-Shubik power index and
  • the Banzhaf power index.
  • Such power indices provide precise formulas for
    ascertaining the voting power of players in
    weighted voting games.

14
The Shapley-Shubik Index
  • The Shapley-Shubik power index works as follows.
    Consider every possible ordering of the players
    A, B, C, D (e.g., every possible order in which
    they might line up to support a proposal put
    before a voting body). Given 4 voters, there are
    4! 4 x 3 x 2 x 1 24 possible orderings

15
The Shapley-Shubik Index (cont.)
  • Suppose coalition formation starts at the top of
    each ordering, moving downward to form coalitions
    of increasing size.
  • At some point a winning coalition formed.
  • The grand coalition A,B,C,D is certainly
    winning.
  • For each ordering, identify the pivotal player
    who, when added to the players already in the
    coalition, converts a losing coalition into a
    winning coalition.
  • Given the seat shares of parties A, B, C, and D
    before the election, the pivotal player in each
    ordering is identified by the arrow (lt).

16
The Shapley-Shubik Index (cont.)
  • Voter is Shapley-Shubik power index value SS(i)
    is simply
  • Number of orderings in which the voter i is
    pivotal
  • Total number of orderings
  • Clearly such power index values of all voters add
    up to 1.
  • Counting up, we see that A is pivotal in 12
    orderings and each of B, C, and D is pivotal in 4
    orderings. Thus
  • Voter SS Power
  • A 1/2 .500
  • B 1/6 .167
  • C 1/6 .167
  • D 1/6 .167
  • So according to the Shapley-Shubik index, Party A
    has 3 times the voting power of each other party.
  • Lloyd Shapley and Martin Shubik, American
    Political Science Review, 1955.

17
The Banzhaf Index
  • The Banzhaf power index works as follows
  • A player i is critical to a winning coalition if
  • i belongs to the coalition, and
  • the coalition would no longer be winning if i
    defected from it.
  • Voter is absolute Banzhaf power Bz(i) is
  • Number of winning coalitions for which i is
    critical
  • Total number of coalitions to which i belongs.
  • Bz(i) is equivalent to voter is a priori
    probability of casting a decisive vote, e.g.,
    breaking what otherwise would be a tie.
  • In this context, a priori probability means, in
    effect, given that all other voters vote randomly
    (i.e., by flipping coins).

18
The Banzhaf Index (cont.)
  • Given the seat shares before the election, and
    looking first at all the coalitions to which A
    belongs, we identify
  • A,A,B,A,C, A,D, A,B,C, A,B,D,
    A,C,D, (A,B,C,D.
  • Checking further we see that A is critical to all
    but two of these coalitions, namely
  • A (because it is not winning) and
  • A,B,C,D (because B,C,D can win without A).
  • Thus Bz(A) 6/8 .75

19
The Banzhaf Index (cont.)
  • Looking at the coalitions to which B belongs, we
    identify
  • B,A,B, B,C, B,D, A,B,C, A,B,D,
    B,C,D, (A,B,C,D.
  • Checking further we see that B is critical to
    only two of these coalitions
  • B, B,C, B,D are not winning and
  • A,B,C, A,B,D, and A,B,C,D are winning even
    if B defects.
  • The positions of C and D are equivalent to that
    of B.
  • Thus Bz(B) Bz(C) Bz(D) 2/8 .25

20
The Banzhaf Index (cont.)
  • The "total absolute Banzhaf power" of all four
    voters
  • .75 .25 .25 .25 1.5 .
  • Voter i's Banzhaf index power values BP(i) is his
    share of the "total power," so
  • BP(A) .75/1.5 1/2 and
  • BP(B) BP(C) BP(D) .25/1.5 1/6.
  • John F. Banzhaf, Weighted Voting Doesnt Work,
    Rutgers Law Review, Winter, 1965, and One Man,
    3.312 Votes A Mathematical Analysis of the
    Electoral College, Villanova Law Review, Winter
    1968.

21
Shapley-Shubik vs. Banzhaf
  • In this simple 4-voter case, the two indices
    evaluate power in the same way.
  • This is often true in simple examples, but it is
    not true more generally.
  • In particular kinds of situations the indices
    evaluate the power of players in radically
    different ways.
  • For example, if there is single large stockholder
    while along other holding are highly dispersed.
  • It is even possible that the two indices may rank
    players with respect to power in different ways
    (but not in weighted voting games).
  • It is now generally believed that the Banzhaf is
    more appropriate to apply to the analysis of
    voting institutions, including the Electoral
    College.

22
Do Constitution Makers Understand Voting Power?
  • Luther Martin (delegate to the Constitutional
    Convention but an opponent of its proposal)
  • " ...even if the States who had most inhabitants
    ought to have a greater number of delegates, yet
    the number of delegates ought not to be in exact
    proportion to the number of inhabitants, because
    the influence and power of those States whose
    delegates are numerous, will be greater when
    compared to the influence and power of the other
    States, than the proportion which the numbers of
    delegates bear to each other.
  • Application to House of Representatives vs.
    Electoral College.

23
Do Constitution Makers Understand Voting Power?
(cont.)
  • The allocation of voting power in the original
    (six-member) European Common Market Council of
    Ministers made the smallest member (Luxembourg) a
    dummy.
  • The recent Nice Treaty expanding and reallocating
    voting power in the EU had effects on voting
    power that almost certainly were not intended.
  • Dan S Felsenthal and Moshé Machover, The Treaty
    of Nice and Qualified Majority Voting, Social
    Choice and Welfare, 2001.

24
Evaluating Voting Power in the Electoral College
  • Lets first review the apportionment of voting
    weights (electoral votes) in the Electoral
    College, in relation to states share of the U.S.
    population.
  • We know that
  • there is a small-state bias in this
    apportionment and
  • there is the problem of apportionment into whole
    numbers that is most significant among small
    states.
  • The following chart shows the relationship
    between electoral vote and population shares
    following the 2000 Census.

25
(No Transcript)
26
Voting Power in the Electoral College (cont.)
  • When the Shapley-Shubik index was first developed
    in the early 1950s, it seemed apparent that that
  • the voting power of the weightiest players is
    typically greater than their weights, while
  • the voting power of less weighty players is
    typically less than their weights.
  • This seemed consistent with intuition (going back
    to Luther Martin and the move to the general
    ticket system) that large states are
    substantially advantaged in the Electoral
    College, even though the small are favored by the
    apportionment of voting weights.
  • However, when the first (Shapley-Shubik
    approxima-tions, using Monte Carlo methods)
    evaluations of voting power in the Electoral
    College were done, this tendency manifested
    itself only very weakly.

27
Voting Power in the Electoral College (cont.)
  • Clearly we cannot apply the formulas sketched
    above for calculating power index values in the
    Electoral College (let alone larger weighted
    voting bodies)
  • There are 51! 1.55 x 1066 ways 51 voters might
    line up to vote.
  • Indeed, such calculations are well beyond the
    practical computing power even of
    super-computers.
  • Fortunately quite accurate indirect methods of
    calculation exist
  • There are websites that can make power index
    calculations.
  • The best is http//www.warwick.ac.uk/ecaae/
  • Also see http//www.lse.ac.uk/collections/VPP/
  • Note that Electoral College Voting Game is not
    quite strong, i.e., a 269-269 tie is possible.

28
Voting Power in the Electoral College
29
(No Transcript)
30
(No Transcript)
31
The Electoral College as a Two-Stage Voting Game
  • With respect to the Electoral College as a
    (one-stage) weighted voting game, the conjecture
    that large states are greatly advantaged by the
    winner-take-all practice is not supported.
  • But the one-stage Electoral College voting game
    is a chimera
  • each state is a mere agent of the popular voting
    majority within the state.
  • We should expand the application of the Banzhaf
    index to include individual voters with each
    state.
  • Within each state, we have an (unweighted)
    majority voting game that determines how that
    state's bloc of electoral votes is to be cast in
    the weighted majority EC game.

32
The Electoral College as a Two-Stage Voting Game
(cont.)
  • If there are nk voters in state k, clearly (on
    the basis of common sense and either power index)
    each voter has 1/nk of the voting power within
    the state.
  • Since (as we have seen in the prior chart) each
    nk is approximately proportional to the state's
    voting power Bz(k) in the Electoral College, it
    appears that the voting power (in the full
    100,000,000-person Presidential election game) of
    all voters throughout the country is just about
    the same.
  • This appears to follow because the ratio Bx(k) /
    nk state voting power to population is
    approximately constant over all states.

33
The Electoral College as a Two-Stage Voting Game
(cont.)
  • But closer analysis of the properties of the
    Banzhaf index shows that this apparent uniformity
    of individual voting power across the states does
    not hold after all.
  • While all voters in the same state have equal
    voting power in determining the allocation of
    their states electoral votes, voters in
    different states clearly do not have the same
    voting power in determining the allocation of
    their respective states electoral voters.

34
The Electoral College as a Two-Stage Voting Game
(cont.)
  • Recall that Banzhaf power is equivalent to a
    voters a priori probability of casting a
    decisive vote, e.g., breaking what otherwise
    would be a tie (when other voters vote randomly.
  • Compare the voting power of a voter in Wyoming
    and a voter in California.
  • One the one hand, the Wyoming voter has the
    greater chance of casting a decisive vote in the
    first stage of the voting game, simply because
    there are fewer other voters in Wyoming and the
    voter has a larger (though still very small) of
    breaking what would otherwise be a tie in the
    Wyoming popular vote.
  • On the other hand, while the voter in California
    has a smaller chance of casting a decisive vote,
    if that voter does cast a decisive vote, it is
    much more likely to determine the outcome of the
    Presidential election, because it will tip 55
    (rather than 3) electoral votes into one
    candidates column or the others.

35
The Electoral College as a Two-Stage Voting Game
(cont.)
  • Put informally, voters in small states have a
    bigger chance of determining the winner of a
    smaller prize, while voters in large states have
    a smaller chance of determining the winner of a
    bigger prize.
  • The question is how these relative advantages and
    disadvantages balance out.
  • We have seen the value (Banzhaf power) of the
    prizes are approximately proportional to
    weights (number of electoral votes).

36
The Electoral College as a Two-Stage Voting Game
(cont.)
  • However, statistical theory tells us that, while
    the probability of casting a decisive vote is
    inversely related to the number of voters, it is
    inversely proportional -- not to the number of
    voters -- but to the square root of this number.
  • This is an approximation that becomes very good
    once the number of voters reaches a few dozen.
  • Now we can put the probabilities for the two
    stages together.

37
The Electoral College as a Two-Stage Voting Game
(cont.)
  • California has about 68 times the population of
    Wyoming.
  • Therefore a voter in Wyoming has a greater
    probability of casting a decisive vote.
  • But the Wyoming voter does not have 68 times the
    probability -- but rather about v68 8.25 times
    the probability.
  • Meanwhile, California has 18.33 times more
    electoral votes than Wyoming and about 21 times
    the probability of being decisive in the
    Electoral College.
  • Suppose the Wyoming voters probability of
    casting a decisive vote is p then the California
    voters probability is about 21p/8.33 2.5p.
  • In sum, the California voter has a considerably
    larger probability of casting a decisive vote in
    the two-stage Presidential election voting game
    than the Wyoming voter.
  • Banzhafs reference to One Man, 3.312 Votes
    compares DC with NY in the 1960s.
  • DC actually had a larger population than some
    states with 4 electoral votes.
  • See language of the 23rd Amendment.

38
The Electoral College as a Two-Stage Voting Game
(cont.)
  • Bear in mind that all these probabilities are a
    priori, on the assumption of random voting.
  • That is, they factor out any empirical data or
    assumptions about actual voting patterns.
  • Some political scientists have critiqued this
    conclusion as the Banzhaf fallacy.
  • Probably what they mean is not really that the
    Banzhaf analysis is fallacious but that it is not
    especially relevant in practice.
  • Certainly the status of states as actual or
    potential battlegrounds is likely to be more
    relevant to the amount of attention that voters
    in different states get in Presidential elections
    than is their Banzhaf power.
  • Howard Margolis, The Banzhaf Fallacy, American
    Jounal of Political Science, 1983 Andrew
    Gellman, Jonathan Katz, and Gary King, various
    recent papers and articles.
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com