Aristotle: Nichomachean Ethics - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 44
About This Presentation
Title:

Aristotle: Nichomachean Ethics

Description:

Aristotle: Nichomachean Ethics Clark Wolf Director of Bioethics Iowa State University jwcwolf_at_iastate.edu Weakness of Will? Aristotle's View: Incontinents make the ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:244
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 45
Provided by: CARD
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: Aristotle: Nichomachean Ethics


1
Aristotle Nichomachean Ethics
Clark Wolf Director of Bioethics Iowa State
University jwcwolf_at_iastate.edu
2
Argument for Analysis
  • People believe that theyll be made happy by
    gaining money or power. But they usually find,
    if they achieve these things, that having them
    doesnt make them happy! As a result, they are
    unhappy and their projects become pointless.
    They only keep themselves going with the hope
    that getting even more money or more power will
    do the trick. The reason for this is not just
    that people are mistaken about what will make
    them happy, they are also mistaken about what
    happiness is. In order to achieve a happy and
    successful life, we need to discover what
    happiness is, and what we need to do to achieve
    it.

3
Argument for Analysis
  • It doesnt make sense to care about something if
    you cant do anything about it. But the only
    things we can really control are our own
    attitudes and internal states. So we should only
    care about our internal states. Life, death,
    war, other peoples welfare, none of these are
    internal states. So we shouldnt care about any
    of these things.
  • (After Epictetus)

4
Argument for Analysis
  • 1) It doesnt make sense to care about something
    if you cant do anything about it.
  • 2) But the only things we can really control are
    our own attitudes and internal states.
  • 3) Conclusion So we should only care about our
    internal states.
  • 4) Life, death, war, other peoples welfare,
    none of these are internal states.
  • 5) Conclusion So we shouldnt care about any of
    these things.
  • (After Epictetus)

5
Argument for Analysis
  • We will either pull our troops out of
    Afghanistan, or we will keep our troops in
    Afghanistan. If we pull troops out of
    Afghanistan, the insurgents will take control and
    the nation will become an enemy to the United
    States. If we dont pull the troops out of
    Afghanistan, we will continue to spend US lives
    and money on an unwinnable war, and will earn the
    enmity of the Afghani people. If we earn the
    enmity of the Afghani people, the nation of
    Afgnahistan will become an enemy to the United
    States, and the insurgents will eventually gain
    control. So we can predict that Afghanistan is
    destined to become an enemy of the United States,
    and the insurgents will gain control.

6
  • Form of the Argument
  • 1) a or Not-a.
  • 2) If a then (b and the c)
  • 3) If Not-a then d and e.
  • 4) If e then (c and b)
  • 5) Therefore c and b.
  • Valid argument form.

7
Argument for Analysis
  • The human function must be associated with what
    is highest and best in human beings, and with the
    characteristics that distinguish human beings
    from non-human animals and other things. But it
    is our capacity for intelligent reasoning that
    distinguishes human beings it is our highest,
    best, and most important faculty, which
    distinguishes us from everything else. So
    whatever the human function is, it must
    essentially involve the exercise of our reasoning
    capacity.

8
Argument for Analysis
  • A person will be a good and happy person when he
    or she is doing well what people are
    characteristically supposed to do.

9
Argument for Analysis
  • A good knife is a knife that cuts well that is,
    it is sharp. This is because cutting is what
    knives are for its their function. And
    sharpness is the quality that good knives have
    to fulfill this function well.
  • In the same way, a good person will be a person
    who fulfills the function of a person in an ideal
    way. So to find out what a good person is, we
    need to discover the function of a person the
    essential human function and we need to discover
    what qualities or virtues a person must possess
    in order to fulfill this function well.

10
PLATO ON JUSTICE
  • Connection to Happiness and Well-Being A person
    whose "soul" is out of harmony will be
    internally divided (see 351a-c This passage, and
    the analogy between individual and social
    divisions becomes clear now.) subject to
    inappropriate and unpleasant emotions motivated
    to do what she should not.

11
  • And justice was in truth, it appears, something
    like this. It does not lie in a mans external
    actions, but in the way he acts within himself,
    really concerned with himself and his inner
    parts. He does not allow each part of himself to
    perform the work of another, or the sections of
    his soul to meddle with one another. He orders
    well what are in the true sense of the word his
    own affairs he is master of himself, puts things
    in order, is his own friend, harmonizes the three
    parts like the limiting notes of a musical scale,
    the high, the low, the middls, and any others
    there may be in between. He binds them all
    together, and himself from a plurality becomes a
    unity. Being thus moderate and harmonious, he
    now performs some public actions or private
    contract. In all these fields he thinks the just
    and beautiful action, which he names as such, to
    be that which preserves this inner harmony, and
    indeed helps to achieve it, wisdom to be the
    knowledge which oversees this action, an unjust
    action to be that which always destroys it, and
    ignorance the belief which oversees that.
  • -Republic, Book IV, 443d

12
PLATO ON JUSTICE
  • Platonic Vices and Virtues
  • Courage- reason supports spiritCowardice-
    desire (to escape harm) and foresight (to see it
    coming) take too much precedence over
    spirit.Vainglory- spirit overcomes
    wisdomTemperance- desire is mediated by
    wisdomGluttony- desire takes overInsensibility-
    insufficient (desire and spirit) to care properly
    for virtue

13
(No Transcript)
14
Aristotle NE, Book I Chapter 1
  • Every craft and every line of inquiry, and
    likewise every action and decision, seems to seek
    some good that is why some people were right to
    describe the good as what everything seeks. But
    the ends that are sought appear to differ some
    are activities, and others are products apart
    from the activities. Wherever there are ends
    apart from the actions, the products are by
    nature better than the activities.

15
Book I Chapter 1
  • Since there are many actions, crafts, and
    sciences, the ends turn out to be many as well
    for health is the end of medicine, a boat of boat
    building, victory of generalship, and wealth of
    household management. But some of these pursuits
    are subordinate to some one capacity for
    instance, bridle making and every other science
    producing equipment for horses are subordinate to
    horsemanship, while this and every action of
    warfare are in turn subordinate to generalship,
    and in the same way other pursuits are
    subordinate to further ones. In all such cases,
    then, the ends of the ruling science are more
    choiceworthy than all the ends subordinate to
    them, since the lower ends are also pursued for
    the sake of the higher. Here it does not matter
    whether the ends of the actions are the
    activities themselves, or something apart from
    them , as in the sciences we have named.

16
Book I Chapter 1
  • Suppose, then, that the things achievable by
    action have some end that we wish for because of
    itself and because of which we wish for the other
    things and that we do not choose everything
    because of something else, for if we do it will
    go on without limit, so that desire will prove
    empty and futile. Clearly this end will be the
    good, that is to say, the best good.
  • NE 1094a

17
Aristotle on What Matters
  • NE I.1 Heirarchy of Goods
  • NE I.2 Existence of a Master Good
  • NE I.3 How to judge an ethical theory
  • NE I.4 Method discover what most people think
    about happiness, then improve it.
  • NE I.5 Three conceptions of happiness
  • NE I.6 Against Platos Forms
  • NE I.7 Characteristics of the Good Complete,
    self-sufficient, final end. Souls activity
    expressing virtue.
  • NE I.8

18
What Matters?
  • Money
  • Security
  • Happiness
  • Fun
  • Love
  • Pleasure
  • Power
  • Achievement
  • Knowledge
  • Wisdom

19
Aristotelian Teleology
  • Telos- end or goal.
  • To find out what something is, find out where
    its going,
  • A things characteristic function is the
    function that makes it the kind of thing it is.
    (Ex Acorns function is to become an oak.)
  • A good thing is a thing that fulfills its
    function well.

20
Aristotle on the Master Good
  • The master good Aristotle is looking for is a
    complete description of the human function.
  • It will include within it all the things we want
    non-instrumentally, and its achievement will
    constitute our complete happiness.

21
  • Properties of Aristotle's Master Good
  • 1) Complete
  • 2) Self-Sufficient3) Final4) Attainable

22
Contrast with Plato
  • Aristotle recommends an Attainable good (proper
    to us).
  • Platonic Good is beyond us, beyond our
    understanding or comprehension. We can only
    grope toward it.

23
  • Test for Completeness of a good For any good G,
    we ask "Is there some other good F that we could
    add to G to make G even better? If so, then G is
    not complete, and cannot be the "master good."

24
Aristotle on What Matters
  • Test for Completeness Consider something that
    might be the master good.
  • Ask If I possessed that good, is there something
    I could have that would make things even better?
  • If so, then the original good is not complete.
  • No good that is incomplete can be the master
    good.
  • Is there any such thing?

25
The Function Argument
  • 1) If something has a function, then its good
    will involve the exercise of that function.
  • 2) A things function will be associated with
    whatever is highest and best in things of that
    type.
  • 3) To find a things function, find out what its
    highest and best capacities are.

26
The Function Argument
  • Aristotle on the Soul (I,13)
  • Non-rational Part (1102b) 1) Nutrition and
    Growth (In common with plants) 2) Appetites
    (including desires and passions)
  • (Possessed in common with animals)
  • Rational Part Two Aspects 1) Regulative
    -control appetite 2) Good for its own sake
    -philosophical contemplation.

27
  • ARISTOTLE The Function Argument
  • 1) If anything has a function, its happiness (or
    good) will lie in performing that function well.
    2) If a human being has a function, its
    happiness (or good) will lie in performing that
    function well. 3) To determine what happiness is
    for a human being, we need to discover the human
    function. (look to the capacities of the human
    soul).

28
  • ARISTOTLE The Function Argument
  • 4) Three Possible Functions Humans Might Have
  • a) Nutritional and reproductive- these functions
    are common to all living things. Plants are said
    to be 'living' because they maintain themselves
    through nutrition and growth.
  • b) Appetitive and perceptual function (use of
    perception and desire, or the animal soul).
    Animals have this function and are said to be
    'living' in that they perceive and act on desire.
    This part of the 'soul' includes the nonrational
    appetites, emotions, pleasure, pain, sense
    perception, imagination, and the power of
    movement.
  • c) Rational Function- Humans and God have this
    function. Human beings, unlike plants and
    animals, have projects and plans. We make
    choices, deliberate, we can calculate and even
    select a way of life for ourselves.

29
  • ARISTOTLE The Function Argument
  • 5) Aristotle argues that (c)rationality is what
    is peculiar to human life. We have a life in the
    sense that we have reason, so our function lies
    in reason.
  • 6) Happiness therefore lies in using our
    reasoning capacity well.
  • 7) Since the virtues are what enable a thing to
    perform its function well, the human virtues are
    what enable us to reason well. Happiness is a
    life of activities governed by reason rational
    activities that are performed well (that is,
    virtuously or excellently). Aristotle's theory of
    the virtues shows how they are qualities that
    enable us to live a life according to reason, and
    to do it well.

30
Aristotelian Virtues The Human Function
  • VIRTUES OF CHARACTER
  • DF A (1) state involving decision, (2) lying in
    a mean, (3) a mean that is relative to us, (4) a
    mean defined by reason, and (5) by the reason by
    which the wise person would define it.
    (1106b36-1107a2)
  • VIRTUES OF THOUGHT (For another time)

31
  • (1) a. Virtue is a state (hexis) not simply a
    capacity or feeling, though it involves both
    capacities and feelings. Possession of a virtue
    requires more than behavior-- it also reqires
    appropriate motivation and disposition for both
    behavior and motivation.
  • b. Value of virtue is more than just a means to
    virtuous action. (Compare to Kant's "action in
    accordance with and for the sake of law...)
    Virtuous activity is not virtuous unless it is
    done for its own sake.
  • c. State "involving decision (prohairesis)
    Certain pattern of desire and deliberation is
    characteristic of the virtuous person. Virtuous
    action is not just thoughtless "reflex," it
    involves intelligent decision making.
  • (2-3) "Mean" does not merely mean 'moderation' in
    action or feeling. For example, achievement of
    'the mean relative to anger' does not mean that
    we will never be more than moderately angry. On
    the contrary, a virtuous person will be EXTREMELY
    angry on occasions when extreme anger is called
    for (Irwin). When Aristotle says that the mean is
    "relative to us," he does not mean to defend a
    narrow relativism. The "mean" is the middle place
    between vices of excess and vices of defficiency.
  • (4-5) Mean (4) defined by reason and (5)
    determined by the wise (phronimos) person--
    refers to the intellectual virtue that is
    responsible for good deliberation. This connects
    the moral virtues with the intellectual virtues.

32
Weakness of Will?
  • Socratic Paradox1) All voluntary action aims
    at the achievement of some goal that the actor
    perceives, in some sense, as good or desirable.
    2) To say that an end is 'wicked' or 'bad' is to
    say that it is neither properly desirable nor
    good. 3) Actions that spring from ignorance are
    involuntary. 4) When actors would not pursue
    some end but for their false belief that the end
    in question is desirable or good, then their
    actions spring from ignorance. 5) When actions
    are aimed at bad or wicked ends, the actor must
    perceive or believe these ends to be good or
    desirable. 6) Such actors would not pursue these
    ends but for their false beliefs. 7) So such
    actions spring from ignorance. 8) So such
    actions are involuntary. 9) So all actions that
    aim at bad or wicked ends are involuntary.

33
  • Socratic/Platonic View Plato, The Laws.
    Athenian all wicked men are, in all respects,
    unwillingly wicked.This being so, my next
    argument necessarily follows. Cleinias What
    argument? Athenian That the unjust man is
    doubtless wicked but that the wicked man is in
    that state only against his will. However, to
    suppose that a voluntary act is performed
    involuntarily makes no sense. Therefore, in the
    eyes of someone who holds the view that injustice
    is involuntary, a man who acts unjustly would
    seem to be doing so against his will. Here and
    now, that is the position I have to accept I
    allow that no one acts unjustly except against
    his will. ...Well then, how am I to make my own
    arguments consistent? 860
  • Aristotle's Response NE VII.ii, 1145b29. The
    Socratic view contradicts appearances. We need to
    look to the causes of faulty action.
  • Plato, LawsSources of "faults" and wrong
    choices Our first kind is a painful one, and we
    call it anger and fear. ... The second kind
    consists in pleasures and desires. The third,
    which is a distinct category, consists of hopes
    and opinion- a mere shot at the truth about the
    supreme good. If we divide this category twice
    according to the various kinds of ignorance
    discussed earlier in the section we get three
    types and that makes, according to our present
    argument, a total of five in all. We must enact
    different laws for the five kinds...864

34
Weakness of Will?
  • Aristotle's View Incontinents make the right
    decision (1152a17) and then act against this
    decision (1148a13-17, 1151a5-7) Their failure to
    stick to their decision is the result of strong
    appetites. Aristotle's Example We recognize that
    we should avoid eating this sweet thing, but our
    recognition that it is sweet triggers our
    appetite for sweet things, which causes us to eat
    it after all.
  • Proviso Aristotle agrees with Socrates, against
    common sense, in believing that an appeal to
    ignorance is an important part of the explanation
    of incontinence. Though he admits that
    incontinents have the right decision and act
    against it because of appetite, he believes that
    it is impossible to act against a correct
    decision that they fully accept at the very
    moment of their incontinent action. (1147b15-17)
  • Explanation Incontinent people's appetite causes
    them to loose part of the reasoning that formed
    their correct decision. They retain the right
    general principles but fail to see (at the time
    of action) just how these principles apply in
    their present situation. So even though they say
    that they know that they are wrong to do what
    they are doing, they are just saying the words,
    without really meaning them (1147b9-12).
  • To this extent, Aristotle thinks that Socrates is
    right to appeal to ignorance-- though he
    disagrees with Socrates about the kind of
    ignorance that is relevant.

35
Aristotle and the Happy Life NE X6-8
  • In the last book of the NE, Aristotle describes
    the best life as a life of study. Such a life,
    he argues, fulfills all the criteria of a best
    life, since the happiness involved is complete,
    final, and uniquely associated with the exercise
    of our highest function in its most
    characteristic employment. But

36
  • Worries about NE X.6-8
  • Worry Is the view Aristotle defends in NE X.6-8
    over intellectualized? Is it a Platonic view,
    inconsistent with his earlier insistence that the
    human good must be achievable within the scope of
    a human life?

37
The Evidence
  • X.7
  • The activity of philosophy seems to be presented
    as the final good!
  • Thought is represented as superior to the human
    level (1177b25). (Is this Platonism??)

38
  • Terence Irwin
  • "Though the evidence suggesting that Aristotle
    holds this purely contemplative conception of
    happiness is strong, it is not conclusive. He
    does not clearly claim that contemplation fully
    satisfies the criteriafor happiness, and
    therefore he does not infer that by itself it is
    sufficient for happiness. (1) If we were pure
    intellects with no other desires and no bodies,
    contemplation would be the whole of our Good (as
    it is for an immortal soul, as Plato conceives it
    in the Phaedo). Still, we are not in fact merely
    intellects (1178b3-7) and Aristotle recognizes
    that the good must be the good of the whole human
    being. In his considered view, contemplation is
    the highest and best part of our good, but not
    the whole of it. (2) Though contemplation is the
    single most self-sufficient activity, in so far
    as it is the single activity that comes closest
    to being self-sufficient, this degree of
    self-sufficiency does not justify the
    identification of contemplation with happiness.
    For Aristotle has argued that happiness must be
    complete, and for this reason he argues that
    neither virtue nor pleasure alone can be
    happiness. He should not, then, agree that
    contemplation is happiness just because it is
    invulnerable and self-contained. For
    contemplation is not the complete good we can
    think of other goods (e.g. virtue and honor) that
    could be added to it to make a better good than
    contemplation alone." "Aristotle," in Becker,
    ed. Encyclopedia of Ethics p59-60.

39
  • Martha Nussbaum Aristotle's other works show
    that "ethical Platonism of some sort exercised a
    hold over Aristotle's imagination in one or more
    periods of his career. We should, then, view the
    fragment x.6-8 as a serious working-out of
    elements of a position to which Aristotle is in
    some ways deeply attracted, though he rejects it
    in the bulk of his mature ethical and political
    writing. Surely this is not disappointing.
    Frequently Aristotle is rather quick and
    dismissive of Platonic positions. It seems far
    more worthy of him, and of his method, that he
    should seriously feel the force of this position
    and try to articulate the arguments for it.
    Perhaps we can say that, like anyone who has been
    seriously devoted to the scholarly or
    contemplative life, Aristotle wonders whether,
    thoroughly and properly followed, its demands are
    not such as to eclipse all other pursuits. (...)
    So he articulates the Platonist view, not
    attempting to harmonize it with the other view,
    but setting it side by side with that one, as the
    Symposium stands side by side with the Phaedrus.
    In a sense there is a decision for the mixed
    view but the other view remains, not fully
    dismissed, exerting its claim as a possibility.
    This seems to me to be a worthy way for a great
    philosopher to think about these hard questions
    and therefore worthy of Aristotle." The
    Fragility of Goodness, p. 377

40
Upshot
  • NE X.6-8 occur within a larger work that focuses
    on virtues of action and character, which cannot
    be exercised in a purely contemplative life.
  • The argument of NE X.6-8 is not entirely
    consistent (?) with the view expressed in the
    rest of the book.
  • The achievement of a complete good requires the
    exercise of all the virtues, not only the virtues
    of thought.
  • This would have fit Aristotles experience of
    life, since Athenian citizens mostly did not have
    the option to retreat from public life.

41
Non Aristotelian Conceptions of the Human Good
  • 1) Hedonists and Cyrenaics Epicurus, Aristippus
    (Came after Aristotle)Argued that pleasure is
    the human good.
  • Aristippus Instant Gratification View
  • Epicurus Take the long view.
  • Aristotle argues that a life of pleasure must be
    incomplete, since it allows no essential role to
    rational activity. Mere pleasure without rational
    activity is not the good for a rational agent.
    (1174a1-4). So A life of pleasure can be
    Improved upon.

42
Non Aristotelian Conceptions of the Human Good
  • 2) Socratic View Virtue is sufficient for
    happiness.
  • Later accepted by the Stoics. Epictetus, Seneca
    Good for human beings is not happiness or
    pleasure, but discipline of the will by the use
    of reason. If we constrain our desires so that we
    want nothing that isn't entirely internal and
    within the control of our will, we will always be
    completely happy regardless of external
    circumstances. The virtuous stoic can be
    completely happy even while being tortured on the
    rack.
  • Aristotle notes that external misfortunes may
    impede rational activity (1100b29-30) and take
    away happiness (1100a5-6). Virtue is insufficient
    for happiness-- one also needs "goods of
    fortune." While virtue may help to achieve these,
    it won't always work.

43
Non Aristotelian Conceptions of the Human Good
  • 3) Egoist view (Thrasymachus, Aristippus,
    Hobbes) We ltalways do/always shouldgt act in our
    own self interest.
  • Aristotle believes that our "end" is not
    "protection of life and gaining power." This
    follows from the fact that a life that was secure
    and powerful might still be lacking in some
    important ways. Thrasymachian view places too
    little weight on reason and understanding, and so
    misses that portion of the good that is most
    important for beings like ourselves.
  • BUT1) While virtue is insufficient for
    happiness, it is nonetheless its dominant
    component. That is, no matter what we have to
    lose as a result of being virtuous, we still have
    better reason to choose virtue than to choose any
    other combination of other goods that are
    incompatible with it. (1100b30-1101a8)
  • 2) From the general conception of happiness,
    Aristotle infers the general features of a virtue
    of character (ˆthikˆ aretˆ moral virtue). Like
    Plato, he argues that the excellent and virtuous
    condition of the soul will be the one in which
    the non-rational elements are guided by reason.

44
Non Aristotelian Conceptions of the Human Good
  • On to Epicurus (Epicureanism) and Epictetus
    (Stoicism)
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com