PHIL 151 History of Modern Philosophy - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 34
About This Presentation
Title:

PHIL 151 History of Modern Philosophy

Description:

George Berkeley (1685-1753) came after Locke and ... Idealism is not solipsism. Solipsism is the view that I am the universe that all that exists is me and my ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:1035
Avg rating:5.0/5.0
Slides: 35
Provided by: Philoso7
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: PHIL 151 History of Modern Philosophy


1
PHIL 151 History of Modern Philosophy
  • Dr. Martin Godwyn
  • Fall 2008
  • WEEK 6 Berkeleys Idealism

2
George Berkeleys Idealism
  • George Berkeley (1685-1753) came after Locke and
    slightly before Hume. He developed a radical
    empiricist solution to the veil of perception
    problems and the mind-body problem
  • Rather than postulate an external world of
    matter that (somehow!) causes our perceptions,
    Berkeley argued that to say that something exists
    at all is always to say nothing more than that
    there is an idea in a mind.

3
Idealism
  • This view is called idealism more specifically,
    subjective idealism.
  • As Berkeley famously put it
  • Esse est percipi to be is to be perceived.
  • The word idealism gets used in other ways today
    but here it simply refers to a theory based on
    the claim that ideas (plus the minds that have
    them) are the fundamental stuff out of which
    the universe is made.

4
Idealism is not skepticism
  • The intent of idealism is to turn the tables on
    the veil of perception problem facing
    empiricists. We cannot know an external world
    outside our minds because the very idea of an
    external world beyond our minds is absurd.
  • Idealism is not skepticism the central point of
    Berkeleyan idealism is to argue that it is silly
    to suppose that there is anything more to be
    known than ones ideas. Hence Berkeley is
    anti-skeptical. We can know the world perfectly
    well inasmuch as we can know our ideas.

5
Idealism is not anti-realist
  • A common misconception is that idealism denies
    the reality of chairs, planets, etc. Not so
    what it denies is the existence of a
    mind-independent reality.
  • Berkeley argues that chairs, planets, etc. really
    do exist. They are as real as real can be. His
    central point is that all that it is for such
    things to exist is for them to be an idea in a
    mind, and there really are such ideas in minds.

6
Idealism is not solipsism
  • Solipsism is the view that I am the universe
    that all that exists is me and my ideas.
    Everything else is just an idea in my mind.
  • Berkeley is not a solipsist. He thinks that there
    are many minds (including the mind of God that
    sees all) and that we can all have ideas of the
    same object.

7
Idealism vs. Materialism
  • Idealism is standardly contrasted with
    materialism.
  • As with idealism, the word gets used rather
    differently today. Materialism in philosophical
    contexts does not mean the desire for material
    wealth etc., it means a theory based on the
    claim that matter is the fundamental stuff out
    of which the universe is made.

8
Dualisms
  • Berkeley represents a radical break from the view
    of Descartes. Descartes was a Dualist he
    argued that the universe had two basic and
    completely different kinds of stuff
  • Matter extended in space and non-thinking
  • Mind (ideas) unextended in space and thinking
  • Since nothing could be both extended and
    unextended, mind and matter had to be
    fundamentally different stuff, argued Descartes.

9
Mind-Body interaction
  • One of the lasting problems arising from
    Descartes dualist position was how something
    extended (matter) could possibly have any causal
    interaction whatsoever with stuff that had no
    extension (mind).
  • Since (most would agree) their clearly is
    interaction between the two, Descartes suggested
    that it took place in the pineal gland (in the
    brain), but ultimately admitted he didnt have
    much of a clue how.
  • Locke, avoided being drawn on such metaphysical
    speculations, and took the view that how the
    mental and the material interacted was something
    we cant know.

10
Problems solved?
  • Berkeleys theory, in one swoop, dissolves two
    major philosophical problems
  • 1. The Veil of Perception.
  • There is no veil at all since ideas in minds are
    what is real and are all that is real. Ideas in
    our minds are not representations of a
    mind-independent world.
  • 2. The Mind-Body problem.
  • There is no interaction between the mental and
    the physical, since all that exists are the
    contents of minds.

11
Some Berkeleyan Arguments
  • So why does Berkeley think that all that exists
    are ideas?
  • His critical arguments against the materialist
    hypothesis boil down to two claims that the
    hypothesis of a material world is
  • 1) superfluous and
  • 2) incoherent

12
Superfluity of the material
  • Berkeley suggests that the hypothesis of an
    external material world adds absolutely nothing
    to our understanding of the universe.
  • Try to think of what difference there would be
    between a world where there was matter causing
    our ideas, and a world where there was only the
    ideas.
  • Can you think of a empirical difference? If so,
    what?

13
Superfluity of the material
  • In a sense, Berkeley tries to turn the table on
    the skeptical Evil Demon argument (or
    Matrix-style situation).
  • Such skeptical arguments hinge on the supposition
    that it is logically possible for our experience
    to be precisely the same regardless of whether
    there was an external world or not.
  • Since all we have to go on is experience, a
    hypothesis that makes no difference whatsoever to
    our experience cannot explain anything.

14
Superfluity of the material
  • But, the critic might still respond Even if we
    grant that it is logically possible for there not
    to be an external material world, surely the
    existence of such a world, running according to
    natural laws, helps to explain our experiences
    (Locke their law-like regularity, our inability
    to will away certain experiences such as pain) in
    a way that idealism cannot.

15
Imagination and perception
  • Berkeley grants that some experiences we can
    control. The former we call imagination, and the
    latter, perception. This difference needs
    explanation.
  • But Berkeley argues that the materialist
    explanation loses out to the idealist explanation
    on two counts.
  • Firstly (as well see) he thinks the materialist
    hypothesis is incoherent.

16
Mental causation
  • Secondly, Berkeley argues that we have not the
    slightest sliver of direct evidence that our
    perceptual ideas are, or even can be, caused by
    material bodies beyond our minds. But, by
    contrast, we do have direct evidence that ideas
    can be caused by minds we know that we can
    cause images in our imagination just by willing
    it.
  • The simplest and most reasonably explanation,
    therefore, is that our perceptual ideas are also
    caused by a mind willing them, but since we
    cannot control those ideas, the mind cannot be
    our own.

17
The incoherence argument
  • Berkeley lays most argumentative weight for his
    idealism on what he sometimes calls his Master
    argument the incoherence argument.
  • The first element of this argument is we can
    never have an idea (an experience) of the cause
    of our ideas.
  • We hear a sound (never its cause) we see a
    colour (never its cause), etc. Causes themselves
    that is things beyond our sensations that are
    not themselves ideas cannot, by definition, be
    sensed or experienced.

18
The incoherence argument
  • The second element of his argument is his
    likeness principle. Namely nothing can
    resemble an idea except another idea.
  • If the likeness principle is correct, then it
    becomes incoherent to speak of an idea of a
    mind-independent material world.

19
The incoherence argument
  • Just try to imagine something that is
    mind-independent. What is it like?
  • Berkeley argues that when we take ourselves to be
    thinking about something existing without being
    perceived, we tacitly forget that we are (in our
    imagination, in this case) perceiving it.

20
The incoherence argument
  • Thus, Berkeley argues, whenever you try to say or
    think something coherent about anything at all (a
    chair say) that statement or thought will
    ultimately be about nothing more than a set of
    ideas in your mind.
  • When you talk about the chair or Venus, you
    are actually talking about your ideas that is
    the only significance you can attach to you
    words.
  • What would Descartes say?

21
Locke and Berkeley
  • Locke argues that the mind represents the
    external world, a world we know only indirectly
    through our ideas.
  • Locke admits that there is no good reason to
    suppose that the secondary qualities resemble
    anything in the object itself. There is a quality
    of yellowness in the banana, but that is just a
    power in the banana to cause yellow ideas in us
    that quality does not resemble the idea of
    yellowness in our minds.

22
Locke and Berkeley
  • Locke, however, takes a different view of primary
    qualities (bulk, extension, figure, number, and
    motion). These ideas, Locke suggests, resemble a
    quality in the object itself.
  • Berkeley thinks what goes for so called secondary
    qualities goes for primary qualities as well.

23
Berkeley on primary qualities
  • Berkeley argues that all the so-called primary
    qualities vary relative to the experiencer and
    hence are equally mind-dependent.
  • Size (extension) is relative what is large to a
    mite is small to us.
  • Shape (figure) smooth shapes to the naked eye
    look irregular through a microscope.

24
Berkeley on primary qualities
  • Motion Also, motion is clearly relative to the
    perceiver. (In his Three Dialogues, he also
    suggests that some minds may experience time at
    different rates. Since motion is spatial movement
    divided by time, motion would be faster to the
    slower mind.)
  • Solidity Some things will appear hard to one
    animal but soft to another (much stronger animal).

25
Berkeley on primary qualities
  • Number That number is not something in the
    object is clear from the fact that it varies
    according to how one considers the object.
  • A pack of cards, for example, is one in number
    only so long as we consider it in our minds as a
    pack of cards. It is also 4 in number considered
    as suits, 52 in number if we consider it as
    cards, etc.

26
Mind-dependence and relativity
  • Berkeleys arguments for the mind-dependence of
    primary qualities draws on the perceiver-relativit
    y of perception. Primary qualities are just as
    much relational properties dependent on the
    perceiver as secondary qualities are.
  • Hence, primary qualities are likewise not
    intrinsic to objects and no idea of primary
    qualities can be said to resemble anything in the
    object itself, as Locke mistakenly supposes.

27
Abstract ideas
  • Berkeley is also famous for arguing that we can
    never form abstract ideas. For Berkeley, unlike
    Locke, every idea is particular.
  • For example, just try to frame an idea of a
    triangle that does not have any particular
    internal angles. Can you do it? Berkeley thinks
    this is impossible.
  • Similarly, try to frame an idea of a triangle
    that lacks any particular colour. Can you do
    that? Berkeley thinks you cant.

28
General ideas
  • Berkeley is not denying that we can have general
    ideas, such as a general idea of a triangle.
  • But what this amounts to, he argues, is taking a
    particular idea and simply ignoring any
    particular features that are not relevant to it
    being a triangle. What is called an abstract
    idea is just an arbitrary particular idea with
    some particular properties ignored.

29
Some criticisms
  • One of the most prominent criticisms of Berkeley
    concerns the existence of things when they are
    not perceived. Such as when no one is in the
    room, before anyone perceived some object, or
    after everyone ceases to perceive some object.
  • Surely, it is suggested, it is plainly absurd to
    suggest that the tables and chairs stop existing
    when we leave the room or even whilst we blink!
    Surely the Earth existed before life emerged to
    perceive it!

30
Berkeley and God
  • Berkeley agrees that its absurd. But he has two
    rejoinders.
  • 1. Something ceases to exist only if it is not
    perceived by any mind. The reality of a chair,
    say, is entirely objective in the sense that it
    does not depend on any particular individual
    perceiving it.
  • 2. An all-knowing God perceives everything, and
    hence even without our presence, objects continue
    to exist. (Berkeleys central reason for thinking
    there is a God is as explanation for our lack of
    control over our perception.)

31
Two accounts
  • Berkeley actually offers a couple of explanations
    for the existence of tables when not observed by
    us
  • The table I write on, I say, exists, that is, I
    see and feel it and if I were out of my study I
    should say it existed, meaning thereby that if I
    was in my study I might perceive it, or that some
    other spirit actually does perceive it. (269
    emphasis added)

32
The counterfactual account
  • Thus, in addition to the God hypothesis, he also
    offers what might be called the counterfactual
    account of the existence of objects not currently
    observed to say that something exists means
    that if one were in the right circumstances (in
    the room), then one would have perceptions of the
    object.

33
Illusion vs. reality
  • A similar point addresses another common
    criticism if Berkeley were right, there would
    be no difference between illusions or
    hallucinations on the one hand, and reality on
    the other, since they are all ideas in minds.
  • Berkeley argues that Illusion is essentially a
    word we apply to perceptions that are experienced
    entirely privately and which are not shared by
    other minds. Reality is objective in the sense
    that it is, in principle, publicly accessible to
    others.
  • Is this response adequate? Can there be
    collective hallucinations?

34
Ideas of the same object?
  • Berkeley supposes that we can all have ideas of
    the same object. But no two persons ideas are
    the same in their particulars.
  • For instance, the same table looks different
    from different positions. What unites such ideas
    into ideas of the same publicly perceivable
    object if not that they are ideas of a single
    mind-independent object?
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com