Title: Individual Choice
1Individual Choice
- Anomalies and Preference Functionals
2- Judgment
- Allais paradox
- Violations of independence?
- Preference reversals
- Cognitive production and capital
- Decision theories
3Readings
- Kagel and Roth, chapter 8 by Camerer
- Starmer, Chris, Developments in Non-Expected
Utility Theory Developments in Non-Expected
Utility Theory The Hunt for a Descriptive Theory
of Choice under Risk, Journal of Economic
Literature, XXXVIII, June 2000, 332382. - Ballinger, T. Parker, and Wilcox, Nathaniel T.,
Decisions, Error and Heterogeneity, Economic
Journal, 107, July 1997, 1090-1105. - Conlisk, John, Three Variants on the Allais
Example, American Economic Review, 79(3), June
1989, 392-407. - Cox, James C., and Epstein, Seth, Preference
Reversals Without the Independence Axiom,
American Economic Review, 79(3), June 1989,
408-426. - Cubitt, Robin P. Starmer, Chris, and Sugden,
Robert, Dynamic Choice and the Common Ratio
Effect An Experimental Investigation, Economic
Journal, 108, September 1998, 1362-1380. - Harrison, Glenn W. Johnson, Eric McInnes,
Melayne M., and Rutström, E. Elisabet,
Individual Choice and Risk Aversion in the
Laboratory A Reconsideration, Working Paper
3-18, Department of Economics, College of
Business Administration, University of Central
Florida, 2003. - Grether, David M., and Plott, Charles R.,
Economic Theory of Choice and the Preference
Reversal Phenomenon, American Economic Review,
69(4), September 1979, 623-648. - Hey, John D., Experimental Investigations of
Errors in Decision Making Under Risk, European
Economic Review, 39, 1995, 633-640. - Holt, Charles A., Preference Reversals and the
Independence Axiom, American Economic Review,
76, 1986, 508-515. - Loomes, Graham Starmer, Chris, and Sugden,
Robert, Observing Violations of Transitivity by
Experimental Methods, Econometrica, 59(2), March
1991, 425-439. - Loomes, Graham, and Sugden, Robert,
Incorporating a Stochastic Element Into Decision
Theories, European Economic Review, 39, 1995,
641-648. - Hey, John D., and Orme, Chris, Investigating
Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using
Experimental Data, Econometrica, 62(6), November
1994, 1291-1326. - Harless, David W., and Camerer, Colin F., The
Predictive Utility of Generalized Expected
Utility Theories, Econometrica, 62(6), November
1994, 1251-1289. - Decision Making Costs and Problem Solving
Performance, (with Tanga M. McDaniel),
Experimental Economics, 4, 2001, 145-161. - Characterizing Cognitive Production Frontiers,
(with Glenn W. Harrison and Richard Hofler),
February 2006.
4Judgment
- Probability judgments
- Many subjects are poorly calibrated
- They do not predict frequencies or probabilities
well - Overstate probabilities
- Overconfident in the stated probabilities
(underestimate variation) - Some, but not all, experts are well calibrated
- Most studies have not used an elicitation
instrument that is incentive compatible like the
scoring rule - Critique these studies may suffer from sample
selection bias in the tasks studied
5Proper Scoring Rule
- An example of a popular incentive compatible
belief elicitation mechanism - You will be paid (2p-p2) if event happens
- You will be paid (1-p2) if event does not
happen - Show how truth telling (reporting the p you
believe is the true one) maximizes payoffs
6Bayesian Updating
- A cab was involved in a hit and run accident at
night. Two cab companies, the Green and the Blue,
operate in the city. You are given the following
data - A) 85 of the cabs in the city are Green and 15
are Blue - B) a witness identified the cab as Blue
- The court tested reliability of the witness under
the same circumstances that existed on the night
of the accident and concluded that the witness
correctly identified each one of the two colors
80 of the time and failed 20 of the time. - What is the probability that the cab involved in
the accident was Blue rather than Green?
7Bayesian Updating
- P(XM) (P(MX)P(X)) / P(M)
- X is cab is blue
- M is observation is cab is blue
- P(X) P(is blue)0.15
- P(MX)P(report blue is blue) 0.80
- P(M)P(MX)P(X) P(MnX)P(nX)P(report blue)
0.29 - P(XM)0.12/0.29 0.41
- Base rate neglect due to representativeness
heuristic
8- Linda is 31 years old, single, outspoken and very
bright. She majored in philosophy. As a student,
she was deeply concerned with issues of
discrimination and social justice, and also
participated in anti-nuclear demonstrations. - Rank the following statements about Linda by
their probability - Linda is a teacher in elementary school
- Linda works in a bookstore and takes Yoga classes
- Linda is active in the feminist movement
- Linda is a psychiatric social worker
- Linda is a member of the League of Women Voters
- Linda is a bank teller
- Linda is an insurance salesperson
- Linda is a bank teller and is active in the
feminist movement.
9Conjunction Fallacy
- F Linda is active in the feminist movement
- T Linda is a bank teller
- FT Linda is a bank teller and is active in the
feminist movement - Also an example of representativeness heuristic
10Wason problem
- Four cards are marked E K 4 7
- Each card has a letter on one side and a number
on the other - Rule If a card has a vowel on one side it has an
even number on the other - Which card(s) should be turned over to test the
rule? - Confirmation bias
11- Judgment
- Allais paradox
- Violations of independence?
- Preference reversals
- Cognitive production and capital
- Decision theories
12Expected Utility anomalies
- Preference axioms
- Completeness
- Transitivity
- Continuity
- Monotonicity
- Substitution/Independence
- Reduction
13Allais paradox
- A1 (0.10), (0.66 2400) (0.33 2500)
- EV(A1) 2409
- Var(A1)2786
- B1 (1.0 2400)
- EV(B1)2400
- Var(B1)0
- Majority of people choose B1
- A2 (0.33 0) (0.34 2400) (0.33 2500)
- B2 (0.32 0) (0.68 2400)
- Majority of people choose A2
14What is the paradox?
- Both A1 and A2 can be rewritten to show that they
both contain the following lottery (assuming
Reduction Axiom is fulfilled) - A3 (1/66 0) (16/33 2400) (1/2 2500)
- A1 0.66A3 0.34B1
- A2 0.68A3 0.320
- Now compare these to B1 and B2
- A1 0.66A3 0.34B1
- B1 0.66B1 0.34B1
- Preference depends only on A3 and B1
(Independence Axiom) - A2 0.68A3 0.320
- B2 0.68B1 0.320
- Preference depends only on A3 and B1
(Independence Axiom) - Observed behavior (B1 A1 but A2 B2) is a
violation of the independence axiom
15Methodological issues in this literature
- Hypothetical choices
- Between vs within subject
- Within gives more statistical power
- May induce consistency
- Indifference
- Random error in expression
- Tests based on reliability
- Making the same choice twice observe proportion
of switches - Is violation rate significantly above such a
switch rate?
16HJMR
- Harrison, Glenn W. Johnson, Eric McInnes,
Melayne M., and Rutström, E. Elisabet,
Individual Choice and Risk Aversion in the
Laboratory A Reconsideration, Working Paper
3-18, Department of Economics, College of
Business Administration, University of Central
Florida, 2003 - Choice inconsistencies in lottery applications
- Common ratio and preference reversal lotteries
- Risk attitudes and recognition of indifference
- Can no longer reject EUT based on such choice
inconsistencies
17Experimental design
- Elicit risk attitudes of all subjects
- Observe choices for lotteries where, given the
risk attitude, the subject should not be
indifferent - Imprecision in measures of risk attitudes
- A wider range of risk coefficients is consistent
with indifference - Lottery A .8U(30).2U(0) or Lottery B
U(20) - Lottery A 0.75(.8U(30).2U(0))
0.25U(0) - Lottery B 0.75U(20)0.25U(0)
18Expected Value and Expected Utility
- Independent of risk attitude choice over A/B and
A/B should be consistent - Except if one allows decision errors that depend
on relative valuations - Assume U(x)x(1-r)/(1-r), where r0 is risk
aversion, and r - Certainty equivalents of the four lotteries as a
function of r
19(No Transcript)
20Indifference
- Around r0.5 all subjects are indifferent A/B and
A/B - As r is increasing the difference in CEs between
A and B become very small - r0.5, pennies
21(No Transcript)
22How did we elicit risk attitudes?
- Holt and Laury (2002)
- Multiple Price List
23So if we want to test EUT
- With these subjects we need a different set of
lotteries - That generate larger CE differences
- We find these lotteries in Grether and Plott
(1979) Preference Reversal paper - We do not compare subjects choice between binary
choice and pricing - We simply predict their choices for each lottery,
given their risk attitude, and compare to their
actual to their predicted choice
24(No Transcript)
25(No Transcript)
26- Judgment
- Allais paradox
- Preference reversals
- Cognitive production and capital
- Decision theories
27Preference Reversal
- Choice over lotteries vs. pricing of lotteries
- P-bet .99 win 4, .01 lose 1 EV3.95
VAR0.0895 - -bet .33 win 16, .67 lose 2 EV3.94
VAR50.518 - P-bet chosen over -bet 50 of the time
- -bets are priced higher than P-bets when selling
the bets
28Intransitivity interpretation
- Asymmetric reversal
- P bets preferred to bets 50 of the time
- bets selling prices are higher than selling
prices for P bets - Set WTAi to a value between those stated for
and P bets - bet WTAi (based on pricing task)
- WTAi P bet (based on pricing task)
- But P bet bet
29Independence interpretation
- Since elicitation done using compound lotteries
- Pricing gambles using BDM
- Random lottery procedures
- These reversals can be explained by violation of
independence rendering these elicited preferences
invalid
30Independence violation
- Independence axiom
- If X Y
- Then pX (1-p)Z pY (1p)Z
- In RLS p is the probability that this task is
selected - In BDM p is the probability that the randomly
drawn value is the stated WTA
31Initial findings
- Lichtenstein and Slovic (1971, 1973)
- Hypothetical
- Procedural invariance
- Intransitive preferences
- Grether and Plott (1979)
- Incentives
- BDM procedure
- Verified reversal pattern
32Preference Reversal
- Holt (1986) and Karni and Safra (1987)
- PR can be explained by violations of the
independence axiom because Random Lottery
Selection was used - Even in absence of RLS, Becker-deGroot-Marshak
use for pricing task assumes independence - Violation of transitivity is a more serious
violation than that of independence - Segal (1988)
- PR can be explained by violations of the
reduction principle
33Reduction violations
- Compound form lottery
- 0.750 .253000
- .750 .25(.84000 .20)
- Reduced form lottery
- .750 .253000
- .800 .204000
- Isolate and ignore the common part
- Independence has been less of a problem when
reduction is violated in this way - Thus, if reduction is violated in BDM perhaps the
mechanism works well because independence is not
violated
34Notes on Starmer and Sugden 1991
- They show that the reduction axiom is violated
- Thus Holts proof that Random Lottery Procedures
are not demand revealing does not apply - Thus the criticism of using BDM in PR experiments
does not apply - Starmer and Sugdens results show that reduction
axiom is violated and thus EUT - Valid preferences could still be based on
combination of substitution, monotonicity and
transitivity axioms - Observations consistent with PR in non-BDM and
non-RLS environments show that it is not only
reduction axiom that is violated perhaps
substitution?
35Counter arguments to the blaming of BDM
- BDM is proven to fail only if independence is
violated but reduction is obeyed - BDM may work well if reduction is violated
- Same reversals are also observed when using other
elicitation methods - Safra, Segal, and Spivak (1990a, 1990b)
- Two testable implications of BDM failure have
been rejected - Same proportion of reversals observed for
subjects who do not fan out as for those who do
(McDonald, Huth, and Taube (1991)) - Selling Price and Certainty Equivalent do not
always lie on same side of EV (Keller, Segal, and
Wang (1993))
36Conclusion
- So it seems reduction is violated by isolation
- Thus perhaps BDM (and Random Lottery Procedure)
is demand revealing after all - No final answer here yet
37The literature and where it was published
- Lichtenstein and Slovic (1971)
- Journal of Experimental Psychology
- Lichtenstein and Slovic (1973) Las Vegas
experiments - Journal of Experimental Psychology
- Grether and Plott (1979) AER
- Schneider and Zweifel (1982) AER
- Reilly (1982) AER
- Berg, Daley, Dickhaut and OBrien (1985)Research
in Experimental Economics vol 3 - Loomes and Sugden (1983) regret theory and
preference reversals - Economic Journal
- Holt (1986)
- AER
- Karni and Safra (1987)
- hEconometrica
38Recent evidence
- Wedell and Bockenholt (1992)
- Reversals disappear when choosing over portfolios
of gambles played repeatedly (?) - Irwin et al. (1993)
- Journal of Risk and Uncertainty
- Opposite pattern of reversals observed in gambles
over real losses - McDonald, Huth, and Taube (1991) JEBO
- Casey (1991) Organizational Behavior and Human
Decision Processes - Casey (1994) Management Science
- Cox and Epstein (1989) AER
- Avoided BDM, value and P bets, then compare
ranking of valuations with pairwise choices
39- Tversky, Slovic, and Kahneman (1990) AER
- Procedure invariance over-pricing of -bet
organizes data better than intransitivity - Using a Dichotomous Choice DC design
- Cox and Grether (1991)
- Economic Theory
- Replicates this
- Loomes, Starmer, and Sugden (1989, 1991)
- Economic Journal, Econometrica
- Dispute these results more evidence of
intransitivities using similar DC design - Loomes and Taylor (1992) Economic Journal
- More evidence of procedural invariance rather
than intransitivities - Bostic, Herrnstein, and Luce (1990) JEBO
- Loomes (1991c) Oxford Economic Papers
- Process evidence
- Schkade and Johnson (1989) traced information
search, Organizational Behavior and Human
Decision Processes - Johnson, Payne, and Bettman (1988) made
calculating probabilities harder, Organizational
Behavior and Human Decision Processes
40Summary of recent evidence
- Support for Slovic and Lichtenstein
- Weight attached to a dimension (consequence or
probability) increases when dimension is
psychologically compatible with the response mode - Choice probability
- Price consequence
41New approaches
- What does it take to make subjects stop
displaying reversals?
42Arbitrage
- Chu and Chu (1990) AER
- money pump
- Going through the steps of switches and trades to
make subject end with same bet but having lost
money - Stated preferences P-bet over -bet in choice but
c() c(P) - Sell - bet to subjects for c() their stated
valuation - Allow them to switch to P-bet according to stated
choice preferences - Buy the P-bet for c(P)
- Subject ends up holding neither P- nor -bet as
before but has given up c() c(P) and is worse
off - Berg, Daley, Dickhaut and O-Brien (1985)
- Research in Experimental Economics
43Incentives
- Bohm (1994)
- Empirical Economics
- cars
- Harrison (1994)
- Empirical Economics
- Increased expected value difference
- Berg, Dickhaut and Rietz (2003)
- Journal of Risk and Uncertainty
- Error-rate model testing
- Different errors in choice expression and pricing
allowed
44Markets
- Knez and Smith (1987)
- Between period trading of the bets
- Cox and Grether (1991)
- BDM, Vickrey, English
- Asymmetric reversals disappeared in English
- Bids are correlated with last market price
45Summary
- Increased incentives
- Lower error rates but do not always remove
reversals - Arbitrage
- Reduces magnitude but not frequency of reversals
- Trading bets
- Reduce reversals
- Procedural invariance violations
- Should we model preferences as varying with
procedures? - What happens to our ability to do comparative
statics if we allow preferences to be procedure
contingent? - State contingent preferences
- Alternative perception of opportunities may be
varying with procedures
46- Judgment
- Allais paradox
- Preference reversals
- Cognitive production and capital
- Decision theories
47Cognitive Production and Capital
- Camerer and Hogarth (1999), The effects of
financial incentives in experiments A review and
capital-labor-production framework, Journal of
Risk and Uncertainty - Feldman Barrett, Tugade, and Engle (2004),
Individual Differences in Working Memory Capacity
and Dual-Process Theories of Mind, Psychological
Bulletin - Harrison, Hofler, and Rutstrom, Characterizing
Cognitive Production Frontiers (ongoing research
project) - McDaniel and Rutstrom (2001), Decision Making
Costs and Problem Solving Performance,
Experimental Economics.
48Financial Incentives and Cognitive Capital
- Camerer and Hogarth (1999)
- Procedural knowledge as cognitive capital
- Not just effort (labor) in cognitive production
- Incentived improve mean performance
- Incentives hurt mean performance
- Incentives do not hurt mean behavior
- Incentives do not hurt mean performance
- Incentives affect behavior, but no performance
standard - Incentive effects are confounded with effects of
other treatments
49Cognitive capital
- Experience with task in the lab
- Contextual labeling of actions or consequences
- Triggers use of field heuristics
- Cognitive capital generated in the lab is often
task specific and does not transfer to other
tasks
50Relationship between cognitive capital and
incentives
- Experience and incentives are often substitutable
- Feedback and incentives like wise
- Instruction on optimal responses as well
51Incentive effects
- Strongest in moderately easy tasks that are
effort responsive - Judgment, prediction, problem solving, recall,
clerical - If tasks are very easy performance will not be
affected by incentives - Variance is often reduced in
- Auctions, games, risky choices
- These tasks may be too difficult to generally
generate performance improvement from incentives
52Working memory capacity and dual-process theories
of Mind
- Two types of cognitive processes
- Automatic
- Attention based
- If automatic processes lead to conflicting
evaluations - Need for attention is triggered
- The ability to trigger and control attention may
be related to working memory capacity
53Working Memory Capacity task
- Read and recall lists of words
- While working on arithmetic task
- 6/3 14 -12? curve
- 49/7 10 19? file
- 28/7 8 -5? dance
- 27/3 11 2? dust
- 15/3 14 -9? guy
54Recall the 5 words
55Cognitive Reflection Test
56- A bat and a ball cost 1.10. The bat cost 1 more
than the ball. How much does the ball cost?
57- If it takes 5 machines 5 minutes to make 5
widges, how long would it take 100 machines to
make 100 widgets?
58- In a lake there is a patch of lily pads. Every
day the patch doubles in size. If it takes 48
days for the patch to cover the entire lake, how
long would it take for the patch to cover half
the lake?
59- Judgment
- Allais paradox
- Preference reversals
- Cognitive production and capital
- Decision theories
60Various Decision Theories
- Hey, John D., and Orme, Chris, Investigating
Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using
Experimental Data, Econometrica, 62(6), November
1994, 1291-1326.
61Hey and Orme
- 100 Circles pairwise lottery choices
- Include a Dont care option for indifference
- Cannot rule out that Left or Right still reflect
indifference - 4 sets of 25 questions
- Prizes 0, 10, 20, 30
- Models will be estimated for each subject
individually based on the 100 observations
62Models estimated
63(No Transcript)
64(No Transcript)
65Estimation
- Theory is deterministic
- Pick L, R, or Indifferent with p1 or 0
- Incorporate some error
- VVe
- Recognize that some models are nested
- Risk neutral is a special case of Expected
Utility (and Yaari Dual) - Expected Utility and Yaari are special cases of
all the others - Nested tests based on testing the parameter
restrictions required for the special cases
66- Risk neutrality is rejected for majority of
subjects - About 85 reject RN in favor of EUT
- Heterogeneity
- Reject EUT in favor of more general model for
almost 60 of subjects
67Mixture models
- Expected Utility Theory and Prospect Theory A
Wedding and a Decent Funeral - Pairwise lottery choices
- Hey-Orme lotteries
- EUT assuming CRRA
- U(sx)(sx)r
- EU?piu(sxi)
- Stochastic property added using logistic function
- ?(EU(R)-EU(L))e(EU(R)-EU(L))/(1e(EU(R)-EU(L)))
- Prospect Theory
- U(x)xa for x0 and U(x)-?(-x)ß
- W(p)p?/(p?(1-p)?)
- PT ?w(p)U(x)
- Logistic function
- Mixing probability p
- ln L(r, a, ß, ?, ?, pEUT y,X) ?i ln (pEUT
l iEUT ) (pPT l iPT )