Diathesis Alternations and NP Semantics - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

About This Presentation
Title:

Diathesis Alternations and NP Semantics

Description:

He's waiting for his girlfriend.' b. On det otveta-gen na vopros. ... (2) a. On det podrugu-acc He's waiting for his girlfriend. ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:76
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 45
Provided by: barbara90
Learn more at: http://people.umass.edu
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: Diathesis Alternations and NP Semantics


1
Diathesis Alternations and NP Semantics
  • Barbara H. Partee
  • University of Massachusetts, Amherst

2
Acknowledgements
  • Thanks to the Fulbright Foundation for a
    Fellowship to teach in Moscow in 2005.
  • Thanks to many students in classes at RGGU and
    MGU for data and suggestions.
  • Thanks to Vladimir Borschev, Elena Paducheva,
    Ekaterina Rakhilina, and Yakov Testelets for
    ongoing discussion.
  • This material is based upon work supported in
    part by the National Science Foundation under
    Grant No. BCS-0418311 to B.H. Partee and V.
    Borschev.

3
Abstract
  • In this paper we examine the relationships among
    diathesis alternations, the semantics of verbs,
    and the referential status of NPs.
  • Some diathesis shifts are argued to involve
    changes in the semantic type of NP arguments,
    including possible alternations between
    referential NPs and property-type NPs.
  • We explore applications of this approach to
    alternations of Genitive and Accusative, both
    with intensional verbs like dat and with the
    Genitive of Negation.

4
1. Examples and issues.
  • For the purposes of this paper, I take the notion
    of diathesis alternation in a broad sense. I
    include not only familiar alternations of
    syntactic patterns as in examples (1a-b)
  • (1) a. The farmers loaded the truck with (the)
    hay.
  • b. The farmers loaded (the/some) hay on the
    truck.
  • but also alternations of case assignment, as in
    the next examples.

5
  • (2) a. On det podrugu. (Neidle 1988,
    p.31)
  • He waits girlfriend-acc
  • Hes waiting for his girlfriend.
  • b. On det otveta na vopros.
  • He waits answer-gen to question
  • Hes waiting for an answer to the
    question.
  • (3) a. On ne polucil pismo.
  • he NEG received letter-acc
  • He didnt receive the letter.
  • b. On ne polucil pisma.
  • he NEG received letter-gen
  • He didnt receive any letter.

6
Examples and issues, continued.
  • Concern the interaction between
  • lexical semantic interpretation of the verb in
    its various diathesis frames and
  • the semantic interpretation of noun phrase (NP)
    arguments that appear in those frames.
  • Long-range goal integration of lexical semantics
    with compositional semantics, (Borschev and
    Partee 1999, 2002, Partee and Borschev 2003).

7
Diatheses and referential differences
  • (1a) The farmers loaded the truck with
    (?the/?some) hay.
  • (1b) The farmers loaded (the/some) hay on the
    truck.
  • In (1a-b) we see a preference for the direct
    object to be definite in either diathesis frame.
  • The difference is most pronounced for the role
    which is Means in (1a) (sredstvo -- Apresjan)
    and Patient in (1b) hay is almost obligatorily
    non-specific in (1a) but may be indefinite or
    definite in (1b).

8
Intensional verbs and referential status
  • In (2a-b) there is a clear difference in
    referential status of the direct object argument
    in the two cases, and a correlated difference in
    the sense of the verb.
  • (2) a. On det podrugu-acc (Neidle 1988)
  • Hes waiting for his girlfriend.
  • b. On det otveta-gen na vopros.
  • Hes waiting for an answer to the
    question.

9
Genitive of Negation and Referential Status
  • Similar difference in referential status of the
    object in (3a-b) in this case the verb itself
    does not seem different, but negation together
    with the verb creates a context somehow similar
    to the non-referential complement of dat. This
    possibility was raised by Neidle (1988), Partee
    and Borschev (2004), Kagan (2005). (More on this
    later.)
  • (3) a. On ne polucil pismo-acc.
  • He didnt receive the letter.
  • b. On ne polucil pisma-gen.
  • He didnt receive any letter.

10
The Issues
  • The questions of concern in this paper are to
    what extent the semantic interpretation of the NP
    is part of, or is affected by, the semantics
    connected with the diathesis alternations seen in
    such pairs, and how the semantics of the
    diatheses are connected with the lexical
    semantics of the verb.

11
Not only diathesis alternations
  • Correlation between different senses of a verb
    and different interpretations of an NP argument
  • (4) John is looking for a blue Volkswagen.
  • a. He cant remember where he parked it.
  • b. If he finds one, he will buy it for his
    wife.
  • Look for in (4a) denotes a relation between two
    entities in (4b) it denotes a relation between
    an entity (the agent) and some intensional object
    (Montague 1973), perhaps a property as argued by
    Zimmermann (1993).
  • (4a-b) are not normally classed as diathesis
    alternation, but the interaction of verb and NP
    interpretations is similar.

12
Filip Verbal affixes, diathesis shift, and
quantificational effects
  • Filip (In press) has explored some cases that
    were first discussed in Partee (1991, 1995), in
    which verbal affixes together with diathesis
    shifts can be used to express various kinds of
    quantificational and closely related meanings
    like measure, distributivity, totality,
    exclusivity or exhaustiveness.

13
Filip Verbal affixes, diathesis shift, and
quantificational effects, continued.
  • One example is the use of the Czech prefix po- ,
    discussed in Partee (1991, 1995) and illustrated
    here by examples (5a-b) from Filip (In press)
  • (5) a. Maloval hesla (na sténu). Czech
  • paint.past.impf.3sg slogan.acc (on wall)
  • He painted (the/some) slogans (on the
    wall).
  • b. PO-maloval sténu hesly.
  • tot-paint.past. 3sg wall.acc
    slogans.inst
  • He covered the wall with slogans.
  • c. PO-maloval hesla na sténu.
  • tot-paint.past.pf.3sg slogan.pl.acc on
    wall.sg.acc He covered (the/some)
    slogans on the wall.

14
a. Maloval hesla-acc (na sténu). b.
PO-maloval sténu-acc hesly-instr.
  • When po- is applied to an imperfective verb with
    a meaning like write, draw, etc., which
    takes an object of creation (5a), the resulting
    perfective verb in (5b) takes as its direct
    object the optional locative complement of the
    base verb, and the direct object of the base verb
    is demoted to an optional instrumental complement
    of the prefixed verb.
  • The meaning of the perfective verb pomaloval in
    (5b) is he painted all over X or he covered X
    with painting. Hence, the prefix po- is in a
    certain sense quantificational but at a lexical
    rather than a syntactic level (Partee 1995).
  • Note the different interpretations of the bare NP
    hesla the/some slogans as direct object of the
    imperfective verb in (5a), and in instrumental
    form in (5b). In (5b) it can only be indefinite,
    and in a sense is even more indefinite than it
    can be in (5a).

15
Lines of investigation
  • Formal semanticists who have studyied connections
    between verb semantics and the semantics of NP
    arguments have emphasized quantificational
    properties,
  • relation between aspectual properties of verbs
    and the count/mass distinction
  • (Krifka, Bach, Dowty, Filip, Partee).
  • Paducheva correlations between decreased
    assertiveness (snjataja utverditelnost) in
    sentences and decreased referential status in
    NPs.
  • Yanko diathesis alternations correlating with
    Theme-Rheme structure (also in recent work of
    Levin and Rappaport Hovav, below).

16
Debates about semantics of diathesis alternations
  • Formal semanticists have recently begun seeking
    arguments to distinguish between diathesis
    alternations that carry genuine semantic
    distinctions and those that may carry only
    Theme-Rheme structure distinctions (Krifka 2004).
  • An example of the difficulty of sorting out such
    factors can be seen in debates concerning
    semantics and pragmatics of the Dative
    Alternation in English (6a-b).
  • (6) a. Ann sold the car to Beth
  • NP0 V NP2 to NP1
  • b. Ann sold Beth the car
  • NP0 V NP1 NP2
  • The double object construction in (6b) is argued
    by Levin and Rappaport Hovav and by Bresnan to be
    motivated largely to make the dative argument
    the Theme.

Rheme
Theme
17
(6) a. Ann sold the car to Beth NP0 V NP2
to NP1 b. Ann sold Beth the car NP0 V
NP1 NP2
  • On Krifkas analysis, the lexical semantics of
    many of the verbs that occur in both frames of
    (6a-b) is a manner of action.
  • The construction in (6a) contributes an
    entailment that NP0 caused NP2 to go to NP1.
  • The construction in (6b) contributes an
    entailment that NP0 caused NP1 to have NP2.
  • Some verbs, like give and sell, have so much
    information in their lexical semantics that the
    constructions contribute nothing new, and the
    sentences in the two frames end up
    truth-conditionally equivalent in this case, it
    is especially likely that differences in
    Theme-Rheme structure will be the most salient
    differences.
  • But in other cases, as with different sorts of
    verbs of causation of motion, like throw vs.
    push, the semantic difference between the two
    frames may be quite noticeable.

18
(6) a. Ann sold the car to Beth NP0 V NP2
to NP1 b. Ann sold Beth the car NP0 V
NP1 NP2
  • Most relevant to this paper, we see the grounds
    for a prediction of a difference in referential
    status to arise in certain cases.
  • Consider the two subparts of the interpretations,
  • NP2 to go to NP1 for (6a) vs. NP1 to have NP2
    for (6b)
  • In the first, NP2 must exist throughout the
    action in the second, NP2 may come into
    existence as a result of the action.
  • Krifka shows cases where this results in only one
    of the two diatheses being possible with some
    NPs.
  • (7) a. The explanation gave a headache to
    Susan.
  • b. The explanation gave Susan a headache.
  • The headache does not exist throughout the event,
    so only the (7b) frame (cause to have) is
    appropriate for less referential headache.

19
  • In the case of the Dative Alternation, we see the
    situation that the semantics of the two diatheses
    permits cases in which the referential status of
    NP2 differs, but does not require them to differ.
    A fully referential NP2 is possible in both
    frames, while non-referential NP2 is possible
    only in construction (6b).

20
Still to come
  • In the second half of the paper, we look at the
    interaction of indefiniteness and decreased
    referential status of NPs with diathesis
    alternations and verbal semantics.

21
Referential Status in formal semantics
  • In formal semantics there has been a great deal
    of work on NP interpretations, including much
    work on
  • quantification,
  • definiteness and indefiniteness
  • kind-denoting NPs
  • property-denoting NPs
  • type-shifting among different possible
    interpretations of NPs
  • and recently on semantic typology and different
    kinds of indefinite and quantificational NPs.

22
Generalized Quantifiers
  • Classic formal semantics adopted Montagues
    proposal (Montague 1973) for the semantics of
    Noun Phrases (NPs). Every NP was interpreted as
    denoting a Generalized Quantifier, i.e. a set of
    sets, type ,t (strictly, a set of
    properties, type ,t.)

23
NP interpretations Montague
  • Some NP interpretations on Montagues analysis
  • John ?PP(j) (the set of all of Johns
    properties)
  • every student ?P?xstudent(x) ? P(x)
  • (the set of all of properties that every student
    has)
  • a student ?P?xstudent(x) P(x)
  • (the set of properties that at least one student
    has)
  • the king ?P ?xking(x) ?y ( king(y) ? y x)
    P(x))
  • (the set of properties which the one and only
    king has)

24
Indefinites
  • What could indefinite mean in such a framework?
    The need for such a distinction first arose in
    discussions of the prohibition of definite NPs
    in English existential there-sentences see the
    contrast between the acceptable sentences in (9)
    and the sentences in (10), which are anomalous
    without special contexts.
  • (9) a. There is a new problem.
  • b. There are three/many/several/few/no
    semantics textbooks.
  • (10) a. There is every/neither/the linguistics
    student.
  • b. There are most/both/the three democratic
    governments.

25
  • No intuitive notion of definite vs.
    indefinite explains why some quantifiers, like
    three and many, pattern with indefinites while
    others, like every, most, and both, pattern with
    definites. Milsark (1974, 1977) provided the
    kernel of a semantic explanation, dividing
    determiners into weak and strong, which was
    further developed by Barwise and Cooper (1981)
    and by Keenan (1987).

26
Semantic explanation Milsark, Barwise and
Cooper, Keenan
  • Definition (Keenan 1987) A determiner D is a
    basic existential determiner if for all models M
    and all A,B ? E,
  • D(A)(B) D(A?B)(E).
  • English test Det CN VP is true iff Det CN
    which VP exist(s) is true.

27
Examples
  • (i) Three is an existential determiner Three
    cats are in the tree iff three cats which are in
    the tree exist.
  • (ii) Every is not existential
  • Suppose there are 5 cats, and 3 are in the tree.
    Then
  • Every cat is in the tree is false but Every
    cat which is in the tree exists is true.

28
Existential Symmetric
  • Basic existential determiners symmetric
    determiners.
  • One can prove, given that all determiners are
    conservative (Barwise and Cooper 1981), that
    Keenans basic existential determiners are
    exactly the symmetric determiners.
  • Symmetry A determiner D is symmetric iff for all
    A, B, D(A)(B) D(B)(A).

29
Weak and Strong Determiners
  • The determiners three, a, some, no, at least
    three, exactly three, at most three are all weak.
  • The determiners the, the three, every, both,
    most, neither are all strong.
  • These semantic definitions laid a successful
    groundwork for a great deal of further research
    on the semantics of weak and strong NPs and their
    distribution (Büring, de Hoop, Partee, Rullmann).

30
Property-type NP interpretations
  • While some properties of weak and strong NPs
    can be accounted for within the theory of
    generalized quantifiers, as in the account above,
    it has been argued that in some cases, weak NPs
    are really of property type (Montagues type
    , functions from possible situations to
    sets of entities), rather than generalized
    quantifiers.
  • Property-type analyses of various weak NPs are
    becoming increasingly common in Western formal
    semantics, and they may have an important role to
    play in accounting for non-referential readings
    of NPs in various diatheses, possibly including
    the Russian Genitive of Negation (Partee and
    Borschev, Kagan)

31
Property-type interpretations
  • Zimmermann 1993 argues against Montagues
    analysis of intensional transitive verbs like
    seek
  • Montague object is intensional generalized
    quantifier, type ,t.
  • Zimmermann object is property-type, type
    .

32
Fundamental properties of intensional contexts
  • (11) Caroline found a unicorn.
  • (extensional, unambiguous)
  • (12) Caroline sought a unicorn.
  • (intensional, ambiguous)
  • Sentences with seek are ambiguous between a
    specific and a non-specific reading (or
    transparent vs. opaque reading). (11) is
    unambiguous, (12) is ambiguous.
  • On the opaque reading of (12), the existence of a
    unicorn is not entailed.

33
Fundamental properties of intensional contexts,
continued
  • Substitution of extensionally equivalent
    expressions in an intensional context does not
    always preserve truth-value.
  • Caroline is looking for a unicorn
  • The set of unicorns the set of 13-leaf clovers
  • Not entailed Caroline is looking for a 13-leaf
    clover

34
Zimmermanns account
  • (Montagues account see written text.)
  • Zimmermann we can capture the relevant
    generalizations if we treat definite and
    indefinite arguments of intensional verbs, (but
    not generalized quantifiers) as properties, type
    .
  • Zimmermanns proposal is that a verb like seek1
    denotes a relation between an individual and a
    property.

35
Zimmermanns account, continued
  • Zimmermann seek a unicorn
  • seek(unicorn)
  • ( is Montagues intension operator)
  • This is a case of NP type-shifting by coercion
    seek demands a property-type argument.
  • We know that indefinite NPs easily shift into
    readings, as was shown for predicate
    nominals in (Partee 1986).
  • transparent, or de re, reading quantify in to
    e-type argument position of seek2.

36
(2) a. On det podrugu-acc Hes waiting for
his girlfriend. b. On det otveta-gen.
Hes waiting for an answer.
  • In the case of the potentially intensional verb
    dat in (2a-b), we see that its intensional
    genitive-taking variant in (2b) has all the
    properties of English seek.
  • Its extensional accusative-taking variant, (2a),
    allows referential NPs and quantificational NPs.
  • We predict that genitive should be disallowed
    with essentially quantificational NPs such as
    those formed with kadyj.

37
What about Genitive of Negation?
  • Hypothesis (Neidle, Partee Borschev, Kagan)
  • Wherever we see Nom/Gen and Acc/Gen alternation
    (under negation, just as under intensional
    verbs)
  • Nom or Acc represents an ordinary e-type argument
    position (referential and may be quantified)
  • Gen NP is always interpreted as property-type
    , or .

38
Russian Genitive of Negation, continued.
  • In the case of Genitive of Negation, the
    construction is not intensional.
  • But Russian linguists from Jakobson to Paducheva
    have argued that Genitive-marked NPs have reduced
    referential status, and Western linguists have
    generally claimed that they must be indefinite.

39
Kinds of reduced referentiality
  • Negation is not really intensional there seem to
    be different kinds of reduced referentiality.
  • Intensional NPs existence in possible worlds
  • Abstract NPs peace, justice, trouble may exist
    in actual world, but their existence is less
    concrete.
  • Quantificational NPs many different kinds, some
    just as real-world existent as a definite NP,
    some not (Paducheva, others)
  • Indefinites under negation if non-presuppo-sition
    al, then non-existence may be implied.
  • Predicate NPs, Property-type NPs less
    referential just as adjectives are less
    referential.

40
Genitive as a mark of reduced referentiality
  • A Genitive NP as an argument of a verb may always
    be less referential in some sense competing
    theories may all be right
  • There may well be more than one way for an NP to
    be less referential (much as there are several
    different kinds of imperfective meaning),
    including being quantificational/partitive,
    being modalized/intensional (not necessarily
    actual), being property-type or kind-type or
    abstract

41
Are Gen Neg NPs property-denoting?
  • Evidence in favor parallels to ?????.
  • (a) ???? ????? ?????.
  • (b) ???? ?? ????? ?????.
  • (c) ???? ?? ????? ??????.
  • Accusative implies actual-world existence,
    Genitive does not.

42
Parallels between Gen Neg and Subjunctive
  • From Kagan 2005
  • 25 a. Ivan ne pocuvstvoval, cto bylo
    xolodno
  • Ivan NEG felt that
    be(past) cold
  • Ivan didnt feel that it was cold.
  • b. Ivan ne pocuvstvoval, ctoby
    bylo xolodno
  • Ivan NEG felt that-subj
    be(past) cold
  • 26 a. Ivan ne pocuvstvoval xolod.
  • Ivan NEG felt cold(acc)
  • Ivan didnt feel the cold.
  • b. Ivan ne pocuvstvoval xoloda.
  • Ivan NEG felt cold(gen)
  • Such parallels support a property-type analysis

43
Problems for property-type analysis
  • Evidence casting doubt on property analysis
  • (a) ? ?? ?????? ????.
  • (b) ? ?? ?????? ????.
  • The (b) case causes problems for all
    quantificational approaches to the Genitive of
    Negation, unless we suggest a meaning like any
    trace of Masha.
  • (c) ???? ?? ????? ??? ??????.
  • (d) ???? ?? ????? ???? ?????.
  • Exs. (c-d) may differ in scope, but not in
    intensionality.

44
Possible non-uniform analysis
  • There may be more than one way that the reduced
    referentiality of Gen Neg NPs comes about,
    licensed by different classes of verbs. (Cf.
    multiple kinds of Imperfective meanings.) The
    property-type idea may be correct for a number of
    cases, but other quantity-based ideas may be
    better for other cases.
  • Work in progress!
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com