Title: Diathesis Alternations and NP Semantics
1Diathesis Alternations and NP Semantics
- Barbara H. Partee
- University of Massachusetts, Amherst
2Acknowledgements
- Thanks to the Fulbright Foundation for a
Fellowship to teach in Moscow in 2005. - Thanks to many students in classes at RGGU and
MGU for data and suggestions. - Thanks to Vladimir Borschev, Elena Paducheva,
Ekaterina Rakhilina, and Yakov Testelets for
ongoing discussion. - This material is based upon work supported in
part by the National Science Foundation under
Grant No. BCS-0418311 to B.H. Partee and V.
Borschev.
3Abstract
- In this paper we examine the relationships among
diathesis alternations, the semantics of verbs,
and the referential status of NPs. - Some diathesis shifts are argued to involve
changes in the semantic type of NP arguments,
including possible alternations between
referential NPs and property-type NPs. - We explore applications of this approach to
alternations of Genitive and Accusative, both
with intensional verbs like dat and with the
Genitive of Negation.
41. Examples and issues.
- For the purposes of this paper, I take the notion
of diathesis alternation in a broad sense. I
include not only familiar alternations of
syntactic patterns as in examples (1a-b) - (1) a. The farmers loaded the truck with (the)
hay. - b. The farmers loaded (the/some) hay on the
truck. - but also alternations of case assignment, as in
the next examples.
5- (2) a. On det podrugu. (Neidle 1988,
p.31) - He waits girlfriend-acc
- Hes waiting for his girlfriend.
-
- b. On det otveta na vopros.
- He waits answer-gen to question
- Hes waiting for an answer to the
question. - (3) a. On ne polucil pismo.
- he NEG received letter-acc
- He didnt receive the letter.
- b. On ne polucil pisma.
- he NEG received letter-gen
- He didnt receive any letter.
6Examples and issues, continued.
- Concern the interaction between
- lexical semantic interpretation of the verb in
its various diathesis frames and - the semantic interpretation of noun phrase (NP)
arguments that appear in those frames. - Long-range goal integration of lexical semantics
with compositional semantics, (Borschev and
Partee 1999, 2002, Partee and Borschev 2003).
7Diatheses and referential differences
- (1a) The farmers loaded the truck with
(?the/?some) hay. - (1b) The farmers loaded (the/some) hay on the
truck. - In (1a-b) we see a preference for the direct
object to be definite in either diathesis frame. -
- The difference is most pronounced for the role
which is Means in (1a) (sredstvo -- Apresjan)
and Patient in (1b) hay is almost obligatorily
non-specific in (1a) but may be indefinite or
definite in (1b).
8Intensional verbs and referential status
- In (2a-b) there is a clear difference in
referential status of the direct object argument
in the two cases, and a correlated difference in
the sense of the verb. - (2) a. On det podrugu-acc (Neidle 1988)
- Hes waiting for his girlfriend.
- b. On det otveta-gen na vopros.
- Hes waiting for an answer to the
question.
9Genitive of Negation and Referential Status
- Similar difference in referential status of the
object in (3a-b) in this case the verb itself
does not seem different, but negation together
with the verb creates a context somehow similar
to the non-referential complement of dat. This
possibility was raised by Neidle (1988), Partee
and Borschev (2004), Kagan (2005). (More on this
later.) - (3) a. On ne polucil pismo-acc.
- He didnt receive the letter.
- b. On ne polucil pisma-gen.
- He didnt receive any letter.
10The Issues
- The questions of concern in this paper are to
what extent the semantic interpretation of the NP
is part of, or is affected by, the semantics
connected with the diathesis alternations seen in
such pairs, and how the semantics of the
diatheses are connected with the lexical
semantics of the verb.
11Not only diathesis alternations
- Correlation between different senses of a verb
and different interpretations of an NP argument - (4) John is looking for a blue Volkswagen.
- a. He cant remember where he parked it.
- b. If he finds one, he will buy it for his
wife. - Look for in (4a) denotes a relation between two
entities in (4b) it denotes a relation between
an entity (the agent) and some intensional object
(Montague 1973), perhaps a property as argued by
Zimmermann (1993). - (4a-b) are not normally classed as diathesis
alternation, but the interaction of verb and NP
interpretations is similar.
12Filip Verbal affixes, diathesis shift, and
quantificational effects
- Filip (In press) has explored some cases that
were first discussed in Partee (1991, 1995), in
which verbal affixes together with diathesis
shifts can be used to express various kinds of
quantificational and closely related meanings
like measure, distributivity, totality,
exclusivity or exhaustiveness.
13Filip Verbal affixes, diathesis shift, and
quantificational effects, continued.
- One example is the use of the Czech prefix po- ,
discussed in Partee (1991, 1995) and illustrated
here by examples (5a-b) from Filip (In press) - (5) a. Maloval hesla (na sténu). Czech
- paint.past.impf.3sg slogan.acc (on wall)
- He painted (the/some) slogans (on the
wall). - b. PO-maloval sténu hesly.
- tot-paint.past. 3sg wall.acc
slogans.inst - He covered the wall with slogans.
- c. PO-maloval hesla na sténu.
- tot-paint.past.pf.3sg slogan.pl.acc on
wall.sg.acc He covered (the/some)
slogans on the wall.
14 a. Maloval hesla-acc (na sténu). b.
PO-maloval sténu-acc hesly-instr.
- When po- is applied to an imperfective verb with
a meaning like write, draw, etc., which
takes an object of creation (5a), the resulting
perfective verb in (5b) takes as its direct
object the optional locative complement of the
base verb, and the direct object of the base verb
is demoted to an optional instrumental complement
of the prefixed verb. - The meaning of the perfective verb pomaloval in
(5b) is he painted all over X or he covered X
with painting. Hence, the prefix po- is in a
certain sense quantificational but at a lexical
rather than a syntactic level (Partee 1995). - Note the different interpretations of the bare NP
hesla the/some slogans as direct object of the
imperfective verb in (5a), and in instrumental
form in (5b). In (5b) it can only be indefinite,
and in a sense is even more indefinite than it
can be in (5a).
15Lines of investigation
- Formal semanticists who have studyied connections
between verb semantics and the semantics of NP
arguments have emphasized quantificational
properties, - relation between aspectual properties of verbs
and the count/mass distinction - (Krifka, Bach, Dowty, Filip, Partee).
- Paducheva correlations between decreased
assertiveness (snjataja utverditelnost) in
sentences and decreased referential status in
NPs. - Yanko diathesis alternations correlating with
Theme-Rheme structure (also in recent work of
Levin and Rappaport Hovav, below).
16Debates about semantics of diathesis alternations
- Formal semanticists have recently begun seeking
arguments to distinguish between diathesis
alternations that carry genuine semantic
distinctions and those that may carry only
Theme-Rheme structure distinctions (Krifka 2004).
- An example of the difficulty of sorting out such
factors can be seen in debates concerning
semantics and pragmatics of the Dative
Alternation in English (6a-b). - (6) a. Ann sold the car to Beth
- NP0 V NP2 to NP1
- b. Ann sold Beth the car
- NP0 V NP1 NP2
- The double object construction in (6b) is argued
by Levin and Rappaport Hovav and by Bresnan to be
motivated largely to make the dative argument
the Theme.
Rheme
Theme
17(6) a. Ann sold the car to Beth NP0 V NP2
to NP1 b. Ann sold Beth the car NP0 V
NP1 NP2
- On Krifkas analysis, the lexical semantics of
many of the verbs that occur in both frames of
(6a-b) is a manner of action. - The construction in (6a) contributes an
entailment that NP0 caused NP2 to go to NP1. - The construction in (6b) contributes an
entailment that NP0 caused NP1 to have NP2. - Some verbs, like give and sell, have so much
information in their lexical semantics that the
constructions contribute nothing new, and the
sentences in the two frames end up
truth-conditionally equivalent in this case, it
is especially likely that differences in
Theme-Rheme structure will be the most salient
differences. - But in other cases, as with different sorts of
verbs of causation of motion, like throw vs.
push, the semantic difference between the two
frames may be quite noticeable.
18(6) a. Ann sold the car to Beth NP0 V NP2
to NP1 b. Ann sold Beth the car NP0 V
NP1 NP2
- Most relevant to this paper, we see the grounds
for a prediction of a difference in referential
status to arise in certain cases. - Consider the two subparts of the interpretations,
- NP2 to go to NP1 for (6a) vs. NP1 to have NP2
for (6b) - In the first, NP2 must exist throughout the
action in the second, NP2 may come into
existence as a result of the action. - Krifka shows cases where this results in only one
of the two diatheses being possible with some
NPs. - (7) a. The explanation gave a headache to
Susan. - b. The explanation gave Susan a headache.
- The headache does not exist throughout the event,
so only the (7b) frame (cause to have) is
appropriate for less referential headache.
19- In the case of the Dative Alternation, we see the
situation that the semantics of the two diatheses
permits cases in which the referential status of
NP2 differs, but does not require them to differ.
A fully referential NP2 is possible in both
frames, while non-referential NP2 is possible
only in construction (6b).
20Still to come
- In the second half of the paper, we look at the
interaction of indefiniteness and decreased
referential status of NPs with diathesis
alternations and verbal semantics.
21Referential Status in formal semantics
- In formal semantics there has been a great deal
of work on NP interpretations, including much
work on - quantification,
- definiteness and indefiniteness
- kind-denoting NPs
- property-denoting NPs
- type-shifting among different possible
interpretations of NPs - and recently on semantic typology and different
kinds of indefinite and quantificational NPs.
22Generalized Quantifiers
- Classic formal semantics adopted Montagues
proposal (Montague 1973) for the semantics of
Noun Phrases (NPs). Every NP was interpreted as
denoting a Generalized Quantifier, i.e. a set of
sets, type ,t (strictly, a set of
properties, type ,t.)
23NP interpretations Montague
- Some NP interpretations on Montagues analysis
- John ?PP(j) (the set of all of Johns
properties) - every student ?P?xstudent(x) ? P(x)
- (the set of all of properties that every student
has) - a student ?P?xstudent(x) P(x)
- (the set of properties that at least one student
has) - the king ?P ?xking(x) ?y ( king(y) ? y x)
P(x)) - (the set of properties which the one and only
king has)
24Indefinites
- What could indefinite mean in such a framework?
The need for such a distinction first arose in
discussions of the prohibition of definite NPs
in English existential there-sentences see the
contrast between the acceptable sentences in (9)
and the sentences in (10), which are anomalous
without special contexts. - (9) a. There is a new problem.
- b. There are three/many/several/few/no
semantics textbooks. - (10) a. There is every/neither/the linguistics
student. - b. There are most/both/the three democratic
governments.
25- No intuitive notion of definite vs.
indefinite explains why some quantifiers, like
three and many, pattern with indefinites while
others, like every, most, and both, pattern with
definites. Milsark (1974, 1977) provided the
kernel of a semantic explanation, dividing
determiners into weak and strong, which was
further developed by Barwise and Cooper (1981)
and by Keenan (1987).
26Semantic explanation Milsark, Barwise and
Cooper, Keenan
- Definition (Keenan 1987) A determiner D is a
basic existential determiner if for all models M
and all A,B ? E, - D(A)(B) D(A?B)(E).
- English test Det CN VP is true iff Det CN
which VP exist(s) is true.
27Examples
- (i) Three is an existential determiner Three
cats are in the tree iff three cats which are in
the tree exist. - (ii) Every is not existential
- Suppose there are 5 cats, and 3 are in the tree.
Then - Every cat is in the tree is false but Every
cat which is in the tree exists is true.
28Existential Symmetric
- Basic existential determiners symmetric
determiners. - One can prove, given that all determiners are
conservative (Barwise and Cooper 1981), that
Keenans basic existential determiners are
exactly the symmetric determiners. - Symmetry A determiner D is symmetric iff for all
A, B, D(A)(B) D(B)(A).
29Weak and Strong Determiners
- The determiners three, a, some, no, at least
three, exactly three, at most three are all weak.
- The determiners the, the three, every, both,
most, neither are all strong. - These semantic definitions laid a successful
groundwork for a great deal of further research
on the semantics of weak and strong NPs and their
distribution (Büring, de Hoop, Partee, Rullmann).
30Property-type NP interpretations
- While some properties of weak and strong NPs
can be accounted for within the theory of
generalized quantifiers, as in the account above,
it has been argued that in some cases, weak NPs
are really of property type (Montagues type
, functions from possible situations to
sets of entities), rather than generalized
quantifiers. - Property-type analyses of various weak NPs are
becoming increasingly common in Western formal
semantics, and they may have an important role to
play in accounting for non-referential readings
of NPs in various diatheses, possibly including
the Russian Genitive of Negation (Partee and
Borschev, Kagan)
31Property-type interpretations
- Zimmermann 1993 argues against Montagues
analysis of intensional transitive verbs like
seek - Montague object is intensional generalized
quantifier, type ,t. - Zimmermann object is property-type, type
.
32Fundamental properties of intensional contexts
- (11) Caroline found a unicorn.
- (extensional, unambiguous)
- (12) Caroline sought a unicorn.
- (intensional, ambiguous)
- Sentences with seek are ambiguous between a
specific and a non-specific reading (or
transparent vs. opaque reading). (11) is
unambiguous, (12) is ambiguous. - On the opaque reading of (12), the existence of a
unicorn is not entailed.
33Fundamental properties of intensional contexts,
continued
- Substitution of extensionally equivalent
expressions in an intensional context does not
always preserve truth-value. - Caroline is looking for a unicorn
- The set of unicorns the set of 13-leaf clovers
- Not entailed Caroline is looking for a 13-leaf
clover
34Zimmermanns account
- (Montagues account see written text.)
- Zimmermann we can capture the relevant
generalizations if we treat definite and
indefinite arguments of intensional verbs, (but
not generalized quantifiers) as properties, type
. - Zimmermanns proposal is that a verb like seek1
denotes a relation between an individual and a
property.
35Zimmermanns account, continued
- Zimmermann seek a unicorn
- seek(unicorn)
- ( is Montagues intension operator)
- This is a case of NP type-shifting by coercion
seek demands a property-type argument. - We know that indefinite NPs easily shift into
readings, as was shown for predicate
nominals in (Partee 1986). - transparent, or de re, reading quantify in to
e-type argument position of seek2.
36(2) a. On det podrugu-acc Hes waiting for
his girlfriend. b. On det otveta-gen.
Hes waiting for an answer.
- In the case of the potentially intensional verb
dat in (2a-b), we see that its intensional
genitive-taking variant in (2b) has all the
properties of English seek. - Its extensional accusative-taking variant, (2a),
allows referential NPs and quantificational NPs. - We predict that genitive should be disallowed
with essentially quantificational NPs such as
those formed with kadyj.
37What about Genitive of Negation?
- Hypothesis (Neidle, Partee Borschev, Kagan)
- Wherever we see Nom/Gen and Acc/Gen alternation
(under negation, just as under intensional
verbs) - Nom or Acc represents an ordinary e-type argument
position (referential and may be quantified) - Gen NP is always interpreted as property-type
, or .
38Russian Genitive of Negation, continued.
- In the case of Genitive of Negation, the
construction is not intensional. - But Russian linguists from Jakobson to Paducheva
have argued that Genitive-marked NPs have reduced
referential status, and Western linguists have
generally claimed that they must be indefinite.
39Kinds of reduced referentiality
- Negation is not really intensional there seem to
be different kinds of reduced referentiality. - Intensional NPs existence in possible worlds
- Abstract NPs peace, justice, trouble may exist
in actual world, but their existence is less
concrete. - Quantificational NPs many different kinds, some
just as real-world existent as a definite NP,
some not (Paducheva, others) - Indefinites under negation if non-presuppo-sition
al, then non-existence may be implied. - Predicate NPs, Property-type NPs less
referential just as adjectives are less
referential.
40Genitive as a mark of reduced referentiality
- A Genitive NP as an argument of a verb may always
be less referential in some sense competing
theories may all be right - There may well be more than one way for an NP to
be less referential (much as there are several
different kinds of imperfective meaning),
including being quantificational/partitive,
being modalized/intensional (not necessarily
actual), being property-type or kind-type or
abstract
41Are Gen Neg NPs property-denoting?
- Evidence in favor parallels to ?????.
- (a) ???? ????? ?????.
- (b) ???? ?? ????? ?????.
- (c) ???? ?? ????? ??????.
- Accusative implies actual-world existence,
Genitive does not.
42Parallels between Gen Neg and Subjunctive
- From Kagan 2005
- 25 a. Ivan ne pocuvstvoval, cto bylo
xolodno - Ivan NEG felt that
be(past) cold - Ivan didnt feel that it was cold.
- b. Ivan ne pocuvstvoval, ctoby
bylo xolodno - Ivan NEG felt that-subj
be(past) cold - 26 a. Ivan ne pocuvstvoval xolod.
- Ivan NEG felt cold(acc)
- Ivan didnt feel the cold.
- b. Ivan ne pocuvstvoval xoloda.
- Ivan NEG felt cold(gen)
- Such parallels support a property-type analysis
43Problems for property-type analysis
- Evidence casting doubt on property analysis
- (a) ? ?? ?????? ????.
- (b) ? ?? ?????? ????.
- The (b) case causes problems for all
quantificational approaches to the Genitive of
Negation, unless we suggest a meaning like any
trace of Masha. - (c) ???? ?? ????? ??? ??????.
- (d) ???? ?? ????? ???? ?????.
- Exs. (c-d) may differ in scope, but not in
intensionality.
44Possible non-uniform analysis
- There may be more than one way that the reduced
referentiality of Gen Neg NPs comes about,
licensed by different classes of verbs. (Cf.
multiple kinds of Imperfective meanings.) The
property-type idea may be correct for a number of
cases, but other quantity-based ideas may be
better for other cases. - Work in progress!