Title: Econ 805 Advanced Micro Theory 1
1Econ 805Advanced Micro Theory 1
- Dan Quint
- Fall 2007
- Lecture 4 Sept 18 2007
2Today Necessary and Sufficient Conditions For
Equilibrium
- Problem set 1 online (due 9 a.m. Wed Oct 3)
email list - Last lecture integral form of the Envelope
Theorem holds in equilibrium of any Independent
Private Value auction where - The highest type wins the object
- The lowest possible type gets expected payoff 0
- Today necessary and sufficient conditions for a
particular bidding function to be a symmetric
equilibrium in such an auction - Time permitting, stochastic dominance
3Todays General Results
- Consider a symmetric independent private values
model of some auction, and a bid function b T ?
R - Define g(x,t) as one bidders expected payoff,
given type t and bid x, if all the other bidders
bid according to b - Under fairly broad (but not all) conditions
- everyone bidding according to b is an
equilibrium - b strictly increasing and g(b(t),t)
g(b(t),t) òtt FN-1(s) ds
4Necessary Conditions
5With symmetric IPV, b strictly increasing implies
the envelope theorem
- If everyone bids according to the same bid
function b, - And b is strictly increasing,
- Then the highest type wins,
- And so the envelope theorem holds
- So what were really asking here is when a
symmetric bid function must be strictly increasing
6When must bid functions be increasing?
- Equilibrium strategies are solutions to the
maximization problem maxx g(x,t) - What conditions on g makes every selection x(t)
from x(t) nondecreasing? - Recall supermodularity and Topkis
- If g(x,t) has increasing differences in (x,t),
then the set x(t) is increasing in t (in the
strong set order) - For g differentiable, this is when 2g / x t
³ 0 - But let t t if x is not single-valued, this
still allows some points in x(t) to be above
some points in x(t), so it wouldnt rule out
equilibrium strategies which are decreasing at
some points
7Single crossing and single crossing differences
properties (Milgrom/Shannon)
- A function h T ? R satisfies the strict single
crossing property if for every t t, - h(t) ³ 0 ? h(t) 0
- (Also known as, h crosses 0 only once, from
below) - A function g X x T ? R satisfies the strict
single crossing differences property if for every
x x, the function h(t) g(x,t) g(x,t)
satisfies strict single crossing - That is, g satisfies strict single crossing
differences if - g(x,t) g(x,t) ³ 0 ? g(x,t) g(x,t)
0 - for every x x, t t
- (When gt exists everywhere, a sufficient
condition is for gt to be strictly increasing in
x)
8What single-crossing differences gives us
- Theorem. Suppose g(x,t) satisfies strict single
crossing differences. Let S Í X be any subset.
Let x(t) arg maxx Î S g(x,t), and let x(t) be
any (pointwise) selection from x(t). Then x(t)
is nondecreasing in t. - Proof. Let t t, x x(t) and x x(t).
- By optimality, g(x,t) ³ g(x,t) and g(x,t) ³
g(x,t) - So g(x,t) g(x,t) ³ 0 and g(x,t)
g(x,t) 0 - If x x, this violates strict single crossing
differences
Milgrom (PATW) theorem 4.1, or a special case
of theorem 4 in Milgrom/Shannon 1994
9Strict single-crossing differences will hold in
most symmetric IPV auctions
- Suppose b T ? R is a symmetric equilibrium of
some auction game in our general setup - Assume that the other N-1 bidders bid according
to bg(x,t) t Pr(win bid x) E(pay
bid x) - t W(x) P(x)
- For x x,
- g(x,t) g(x,t) W(x) W(x) t
P(x) P(x) - When does this satisfy strict single-crossing?
10When is strict single crossing satisfied
byg(x,t) g(x,t) W(x) W(x) t
P(x) P(x) ?
- Assume W(x) ³ W(x) (probability of winning
nondecreasing in bid) - g(x,t) g(x,t) is weakly increasing in t, so if
its strictly positive at t, its strictly
positive at t t - Need to check that if g(x,t) g(x,t) 0, then
g(x,t) g(x,t) 0 - This can only fail if W(x) W(x)
- If b has convex range, W(x) W(x), so strict
single crossing differences holds and b must be
nondecreasing (e.g. T convex, b continuous) - If W(x) W(x) and P(x) ¹ P(x) (e.g.,
first-price auction, since P(x) x), then
g(x,t) g(x,t) ¹ 0, so theres nothing to check - But, if W(x) W(x) and P(x) P(x), then
bidding x and x give the same expected payoff,
so b(t) x and b(t) x could happen in
equilibrium - Example. A second-price auction, with values
uniformly distributed over 0,1 È 2,3. The
bid function b(2) 1, b(1) 2, b(vi) vi
otherwise is a symmetric equilibrium. - But other than in a few weird situations, b will
be nondecreasing
11b will almost always be strictly increasing
- Suppose b(-) were constant over some range of
types t,t - Then there is positive probability
- (N 1) F(t) F(t) FN 2(t)
- of tying with one other bidder by bidding b
(plus the additional possibility of tying with
multiple bidders) - Suppose you only pay if you win let B be the
expected payment, conditional on bidding b and
winning - Since t t, either t B or B t, so
either you strictly prefer to win at t or you
strictly prefer to lose at t - Assume that when you tie, you win with
probability greater than 0 but less than 1 - Then you can strictly gain in expectation either
by reducing b(t) by a sufficiently small amount,
or by raising b(t) by a sufficiently small
amount - (In addition when T has point mass
second-price first-price)
12So to sum up, in well-behaved symmetric IPV
auctions, except in very weird situations,
- any symmetric equilibrium bid function will be
strictly increasing, - and the envelope formula will therefore hold
- Next when are these sufficient conditions for a
bid function b to be a symmetric equilibrium?
13Sufficiency
14What are generally sufficient conditions for
optimality in this type of problem?
- A function g(x,t) satisfies the smooth single
crossing differences condition if for any x x
and t t, - g(x,t) g(x,t) 0 ? g(x,t) g(x,t) 0
- g(x,t) g(x,t) ³ 0 ? g(x,t) g(x,t) ³ 0
- gx(x,t) 0 ? gx(x,td) ³ 0 ³ gx(x,t d)
for all d 0 - Theorem. (PATW th 4.2) Suppose g(x,t) is
continuously differentiable and has the smooth
single crossing differences property. Let x
0,1 ? R have range X, and suppose x is the sum
of a jump function and an absolutely continuous
function. If - x is nondecreasing, and
- the envelope formula holds for every t,
- g(x(t),t) g(x(0),0) ò0t gt(x(s),s) ds
- then x(t) Î arg maxx Î X g(x,t)
- (Note that x only guaranteed optimal over X, not
over all X)
15But
- Establishing smooth single-crossing differences
requires a bunch of conditions on b - We can use the payoff structure of an IPV auction
to give a simpler proof - Proof is taken from Myerson (Optimal Auctions),
which were doing on Thursday anyway
16Claim
- Theorem. Consider any auction where the highest
bid gets the object. Assume the type space T
has no point masses. Let b T ? R be any
function, and define g(x,t) in the usual way. If - b is strictly increasing, and
- the envelope formula holds for every t,
- g(b(t),t) g(b(0),0) ò0t FN-1(s) ds
- then g(b(t),t) ³ g(b(t),t), that is, no bidder
can gain by making a bid that a different type
would make. - If, in addition, the type space T is convex, b
is continuous, and neither the highest nor the
lowest type can gain by bidding outside the range
of b, then everyone bidding b is an equilibrium.
17Proof.
- Note that when you bid b(s), you win with
probability FN-1(s) let z(s) denote the expected
payment you make from bidding s - Suppose a bidder had a true type of t and bid
b(t) instead of b(t) - The gain from doing this is
- g(b(t), t) g(b(t), t) t FN-1(t) z(t)
g(b(t),t) - (t t) FN-1(t) t FN-1(t) z(t)
g(b(t),t) - (t t) FN-1(t) g(x(t),t) g(x(t),t)
- Suppose t t. By assumption, the envelope
theorem holds, so - (t t) FN-1(t) òtt FN-1(s) ds
- òtt FN-1(s) FN-1(t) ds
- But F is increasing (weakly), so FN-1(t) ³
FN-1(s) for every s in the integral, so this is
(weakly) negative - Symmetric argument holds for t
- So the envelope formula is exactly the condition
that there is never a gain to deviating to a
different types equilibrium bid
18Proof.
- All thats left is deviations to bids outside the
range of b - With T convex and b continuous, the bid
distribution has convex support, so we only need
to check deviations to bids above and below the
range of b - Assume (for notational ease) that T 0,T
- If some type t deviated to a bid B b(T), his
expected gain would be - g(B,t) g(b(t),t) g(B,t) g(b(T),t)
g(b(T),t) g(b(t),t) - The second term is nonpositive (another types
bid isnt a profitable deviation) - We also know g(x,t) t Pr(win bid x) z(x)
has increasing differences in x and t, so for B
b(T), if g(B,t) g(b(T),t) 0, g(B,T)
g(b(T),t) 0 - So if the highest type T cant gain by bidding
above b(T), no one can - By the symmetric argument, we only need to check
the lowest types incentive to bid below b(0) - (If b was discontinuous or T had holes, we would
need to also check deviations to the holes in
the range of b) - QED
19So basically, in well-behaved symmetric IPV
auctions,
- b T ? R is a symmetric equilibrium if and only
if - b is increasing, and
- b (and the g derived from it) satisfy the
envelope formula
20Up next
- Recasting auctions as direct revelation
mechanisms - Optimal (revenue-maximizing) auctions
- Might want to take a look at the Myerson paper,
or the treatment in one of the textbooks - If you dont know mechanism design, dont worry,
well go over it - Meanwhile, since theres time
21A Few Slides on Second-OrderStochastic Dominance
22When is one probability distribution less risky
than another?
- Two random variables X and Y with the same mean,
with distributions F and G - Three conditions to consider
- 1. Every risk-averse utility maximizer prefers
X to Y, i.e., E u(X) ³ E u(Y) for every
nondecreasing, concave u, or ò- u(s) dF(s) ³
ò- u(s) dG(s) (also called SOSD) - 2. Y is a mean-preserving spread of X, or Y
X noise r.v. Z s.t. Y d X Z, with
E(ZX) 0 for every value of X - 3. For every x,ò-x F(s) ds ò-x G(s) ds
- Rothschild-Stiglitz (1970) 1 2 3
23What does this tell us?
- Risk-averse buyers greatly impact auction design
changes equilibrium strategies well get to
that in a few lectures (Maskin and Riley) - Risk-averse sellers have less impact
equilibrium strategies are the same, all that
changes is sellers valuation of different
distributions of revenue - Claim. With symmetric IPV, a risk-averse seller
prefers a first-price to a second-price auction
24Proof well show revenue in second-price auction
is MPS of revenue in first-price
- Recall that revenue in a second-price auction is
v2, and revenue in a first-price auction is E(v2
v1) - Let X, Y, and Z be random variables derived from
bidders valuations, as follows - X g(v1)
- Z v2 g(v1)
- Y v2
- where g(t) ò0t s dFN-1(s) / FN-1(t) E(v2 v1
t) - Note that Y X Z, andE(Z Xg(t)) E(v2
v1 t) E(v2 v1 t) 0 - So Y is a mean-preserving spread of X, so any
risk-averse utility maximizer prefers X to Y - But X is the revenue in the first-price auction,
and Y is the revenue in the second-price auction
Q.E.D.
25A cool proof SOSD º ò-x F(s) ds ò-x G(s) ds
everywhere
- Well use the extremal method or basis
function method - Well rewrite our generic (increasing concave)
function u(s) as a positive sum of basis
functions - u(s) ò- w(q) h(s,q) dq
- with w(q) ³ 0, where these basis functions are
themselves increasing and concave - Then well show that X SOSD Y if and only if
- ò- h(x,q) dF(x) ³ ò- h(y,q) dG(y)
- for all the basis functions
- (Only if is trivial, since h(s,q) is increasing
and concave if just involves multiplying this
inequality by w(q) and integrating over q)
26A cool proof SOSD º ò-x F(s) ds ò-x G(s) ds
everywhere
- Well do the special case of u twice
differentiable. Our basis functions will be a
constant, a linear term, and the
functions h(x,q) min(x,q) - Claim is that u(x) a bx ò0 (-u(q))
h(x,q) dq - Note that -u(q) is nonnegative, since u is
concave - To see the equality, integrate by parts, with db
-u dq, a hò a db a b ò b da
h(x,q)u(q)q- ò- u(q) 1qxu() constant ò-x u(q) dq - Since X and Y have the same mean,
- ò- (abx) dF(x) ò- (aby) dG(y)
27A cool proof SOSD º ò-x F(s) ds ò-x G(s) ds
everywhere
- So all thats left is to determine when
- ò- h(s,q) dF(s) ³ ò- h(s,q) dG(s)
- Integrate by parts u h(s,q), dv dF(s), LHS
becomesh(,q) F() h(-,q) F(-) ò- F(s)
hs(s,q) ds q 0 ò- F(s) 1sò- q F(s) ds - Similarly, the right-hand side becomes q ò- q
G(s) ds - So EsF h(s,q) ³ EsG h(s,q) ò- q F(s)
ds ò- q G(s) ds - So X SOSD Y if and only if this holds for every q
28(I dont expect to get to) First-Order
Stochastic Dominance
29When is one probability distribution better
than another?
- Two probability distributions, F and G
- F first-order stochastically dominates G if
- ò- u(s) dF(s) ³ ò- u(s) dG(s)
- for every nondecreasing function u
- So anyone whos maximizing any increasing
function prefers the distribution of outcomes F
to G - (Very strong condition.)
- Theorem. F first-order stochastically dominates
G if and only if F(x) G(x) for every x.
30Proving FOSD º F(x) G(x) everywhere
- Proof for differentiable u. Rewrite it using a
basis consisting of step functions dq(s)
0 if s - Up to an additive constant, u(s) ò- u(q)
dq(s) dq - To see this, calculate u(s) u(s) ò- u(q)
(dq(s) dq(s)) dq òss u(q) dq - So F FOSD G if and only if ò- dq(s) dF(s) ³
ò- dq(s) dG(s) for every q
31Proving FOSD º F(x) G(x) everywhere
- But ò- dq(s) dF(s) Pr(s ³ q) 1 F(q)and
similarly ò- dq(s) dG(s) 1 G(q) - So if F(x) G(x) for all x, EsF u(s) ³ EsG
u(s) - for any increasing u
- Only if is because dq(x) is a valid increasing
function of x