Todays Lecture - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

About This Presentation
Title:

Todays Lecture

Description:

Please check to ensure that the data matches what you have (this will be the ... 'Act only according to that maxim by which you can at the same time will that ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:52
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 43
Provided by: andrew106
Category:
Tags: lecture | study | time | todays

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: Todays Lecture


1
Todays Lecture
  • Grade spreadsheet
  • Turnitin.com
  • Study session on Monday 18th
  • Final Exam and office hours
  • Immanuel Kant

2
Grade spreadsheet
  • I will be placing an undated grade spreadsheet on
    the course website some time on Wednesday. Please
    check to ensure that the data matches what you
    have (this will be the last chance to do so
    before the exam).
  • If there are any discrepancies, come and see me.

3
Turnitin.com
  • Remember that if your assignments are not in
    Turnitin.com by Friday you will receive a zero on
    the relevant assignment.
  • There is no negotiation on this one, so dont
    leave this task to the last minute.

4
Study session on Monday 18th
  • There will be a study session on Monday the 18th,
    from 1100-1300 (or 1100 a.m. to 100 p.m.). This
    will be held in Talbot College room 310. You
    dont have to stay for the whole period, if you
    come at all. Attendance is strictly voluntary.
    But you may be able to help each other out.
  • Bring ideas and talk stuff over. I wont be able
    to give you any substantive answers, as that
    would defeat the purpose of the exam. But I can
    referee your discussion (i.e. if you need a
    referee).

5
Final Exam and office hours
  • Dont forget that the final exam is on Tuesday,
    the 19th, at 900 a.m.
  • The location, remember, is TC 343.
  • Also, I will choose the exam questions from the
    first fifteen questions on your original handout
    of possible exam questions (unfortunately we will
    not be getting to either Rawls or hooks - so drop
    questions 16 and 17).
  • My final office hours for this course are this
    week. I will be submitting your final grades on
    Friday the 22nd, so if you have any questions
    about grades, seek me out before the 22nd.

6
First Section Intrinsic versus extrinsic
goodness or value
  • You can understand the beginning of this section
    as assuming that the moral life is good. This is
    suggested by the status accorded those who would
    live morally (see FP, p.643). The question is, Is
    it extrinsically or intrinsically good?

7
First Section The good will
  • Under the influence of something like this
    consideration, Kant introduces the notion of the
    good will.
  • It is his contention that nothing in the world
    - indeed nothing beyond the world - can possibly
    be conceived which could be called good without
    qualification except a good will (FP, p.642).
  • As he implies in this claim, he will include God
    here.

8
First Section The good will
  • Kant considers candidates for unconditional goods
    (i.e. unqualified goods) among those personal
    traits associated with valuers, and with those
    environmental contingencies that inform the
    quality of their lives. He seems to treat this as
    exhaustive in its scope.
  • Neither the talents of mind (FP, p.642) nor the
    qualities of temperament (FP, p.642) can be
    taken to be unconditionally good.
  • If it were not for the goodness of will, or
    character, such qualities as intelligence or
    perseverance could do great harm. Their goodness,
    then, is derivative (FP, p.643).

9
First Section The good will
  • Gifts of fortune (FP, p.643) by which he
    means power, riches, honor, ... health,
    general well-being and the contentment with ones
    condition (FP, p.643) are also derivatively
    good. Without a good will, or character, such
    gifts could do great harm (FP, p.643).
  • This does not yet give what Kant wants, after all
    the good will could be extrinsically good.
  • But it is Kants contention that the will is not
    good because of what it accomplishes or because
    of its causal potency (i.e. it is not good for
    something else, or achieving something else).
    Indeed its goodness would not be diminished if it
    were to lack causal potency. It is good only
    because of its willing (i.e., it is good in
    itself) (FP, p.643).

10
First Section An(other) argument for the
intrinsic goodness of the will
  • (1) Every organ has a purpose.
  • (2) Every organ is best fitted or adapted for its
    purpose.
  • (3) The more a person tries to use her reason to
    secure her own happiness the more she fails.
  • (4) Whats more, those who live closer to
    instinct are happier than those who live
    according to their reason.
  • (5) Reason, therefore, is ill-equipped to secure
    an individuals happiness.

11
First Section An(other) argument for the
intrinsic goodness of the will
  • (6) Given (5), the purpose of reason cannot be a
    rational beings happiness.
  • (7) Reason is a practical faculty (or
    power)...that is, reason is a faculty (or power)
    for influencing the will.
  • (8) If reasons goodness (or value) lies in its
    purpose, then it lies in its influence on the
    will.
  • (9) Given (3) through (6), reasons goodness (or
    value) isnt in its power to yield an
    extrinsically good will.
  • (10) Therefore, reasons goodness (or value) must
    lie in its power to yield an intrinsically good
    will (FP, pp.643-44).

12
First Section Developing the notion of an
intrinsically good will
  • It is at this point that Kant begins his
    discussion of duty. The reason for this is that
    the notion of duty implies a good will. I.e. to
    act from duty is to exhibit a good will (FP,
    p.644).
  • He hopes, then, by developing the notion of what
    it is to act from duty, he will, ipso facto,
    develop the notion of a good will (FP, p.644).

13
First Section The first proposition
  • The moral worth of an action lies in the
    intentions of the agent. If the agent acts
    because duty requires her to so act, then her
    action has moral worth (FP, pp.644-45, 646).
  • An action motivated by self-interest,
    self-preservation or even feelings of warmth
    towards another lack moral worth, according to
    Kant (FP, pp.644-45).
  • This may seem strange at first, but Kant notes
    that the (albeit meager) moral worth of such
    actions only arises when they accord with our
    duties. But since such inclinations do not always
    so arise, they are not unconditionally good, and
    only what is unconditionally good has moral worth
    (FP, p.645).

14
First Section The first proposition
  • It is in this way, undoubtedly, that we should
    understand those passages of Scripture which
    command us to love our neighbor and even our
    enemy, for love as an inclination cannot be
    commanded. But beneficence from duty, even when
    no inclination impels it and even when it is
    opposed by a natural and unconquerable aversion,
    is practical love, not pathological love - it
    resides in the will and not in the propensities
    of felling, in principles of action not in tender
    sympathy and it is alone can be commanded (FP,
    p.646).

15
First Section The second proposition
  • An action done from duty does not have its moral
    worth in the purpose which is to be achieved
    through it but in the maxim whereby it is
    determined (FP, p.646).
  • This seems to follow from Kants earlier
    rejection of the view that an actions moral
    worth arises from the purposes or ends of said
    action. Though an actions effects/consequences
    or purposes may conform to what is right, the
    wrong motivation for said action can undermine
    its worth. What ensures the proper connection
    between an action and whats right is the
    principle of the will that gives rise to the
    action (FP, p.646).

16
First Section The second proposition
  • Interestingly, the success or failure of the
    willed action is irrelevant to its moral worth
    (on this account). Whether it succeeds or fails
    is largely out of the hands of the person willing
    the action. The goodness of a persons choice can
    only be reasonably ascribed, then, on other
    grounds, grounds over which the person has
    control. Thus the choice itself is the source of
    the moral worth of an act (if it has any moral
    worth at all) (FP, p.646).

17
First Section The third proposition
  • Duty is the necessity to do an action from
    respect for law (FP, p.646).
  • You have three elements in the notion of acting
    from duty (1) An objective principle (or
    practical law), (2) a subjective maxim which
    accords with, or follows from, said objective
    principle and (3) respect for the law (without
    any regard for the consequences of acting in
    accord with said law) (FP, p.647).

18
First Section practical laws, objective
principles and maxims
  • An objective principle is that which all rational
    beings (human or otherwise) could act upon if
    their reason has control over their desires.
  • A maxim is a subjective principle of the
    will...that is, a principle with which an agent
    wills herself to act (i.e. a psychological
    principle of action).
  • An objective principle is a practical law (see
    FP, pp.634, 637 and also the authors footnote on
    page 647 of your FP).
  • Note that, due to the abstract nature of duty and
    the moral law, only a rational being can be moral
    (FP, p.647). This will exclude children by the
    way (they are still too bound to contingencies
    and lack the ability to reflect without recourse
    to experience).

19
First Section The first categorical imperative
  • The supreme categorical imperative is proffered
    as a way of discovering what counts as an
    objective principle (or practical law).
  • Also, what he identifies as the supreme
    categorical imperative, of which there are at
    least three complementary versions, is to be
    imagined as lying at the foundation of our moral
    system.

20
First Section The first categorical imperative
  • Those imperatives that we use (or pretend to use)
    in our moral lives are derived from the supreme
    categorical imperative (FP, p.647).
  • The common sense of mankind in its practical
    judgments is in perfect agreement with this and
    has this principle constantly in view (FP,
    p.647)
  • The derivation of lower order imperatives from
    the supreme categorical imperative is thought to
    preserve the necessity enjoyed by the supreme
    categorical imperative.

21
First Section The first categorical imperative
  • The first categorical imperative is I ought
    never to act in such a way that I could not also
    will that my maxim should be a universal law
    (FP, p.647).
  • This falls out of Kants move to strip the will
    of all impulses which could come to it from
    obedience to any law, nothing remains to serve as
    a principle of the will except universal
    conformity to law as such (FP, p.647).

22
First Section The first categorical imperative
  • Consider Kants test case May I, when in
    distress, make a promise with the intention not
    to keep it? (FP, p.647).
  • Kant suggests we can distinguish a prudential and
    strictly moral approach to answering this
    question.
  • Prudentially, we can go either way (FP, p.648).
  • Morally, however, we can only go in the direction
    of not making such a promise (at least according
    to Kant) (FP, p.648).
  • After all, if we imagine such a maxim holding as
    a universal law, no promises could subsequently
    exist. No one would trust me, nor could I trust
    them, so promises would be of no effect. Since I
    cannot so will my maxim to be a universal law, I
    ought not to follow it myself (FP, p.648).

23
First Section The first categorical imperative
  • Note that, for Kant, his account thus far
    accords, or purports to accord, with our common
    moral knowledge (FP, pp.648-49).
  • Kant does not view the discussion thus far as
    innovative, he has merely highlighted what is
    already at work in our moral reasoning (FP,
    p.648).
  • We have an imperative that yields maxims which
    hold universally.
  • We have an imperative that yields maxims which
    hold impartially.
  • We also have a method of discovering our duty
    which does not require theoretical knowledge, a
    wealth of experience or intellectual expertise
    (FP, p.648).

24
Second Section
  • In this Second Section, Kant will move from a
    critical examination of our common moral
    knowledge, to a metaphysics that will explain or
    make sense of this knowledge.

25
Second Section Kants pessimism
  • Kant opens the second section up with the
    admission that it is, in fact, absolutely
    impossible by experience to discern with complete
    certainty a single case in which the maxim of an
    action, however much it might conform to duty,
    rested solely on moral grounds and on the
    conception of ones duty (FP, p.650).

26
Second Section Kants pessimism
  • This is primarily to indicate that Kants notion
    of duty is not an empirical notion. That is, Kant
    didnt merely glean his theory of duty from what
    can be observed in common moral practice (FP,
    p.650).
  • It also indicates that, for Kant, the success or
    failure of his theory does not depend on whether
    we can successfully implement it (see page 650 of
    your FP).
  • Is this a problem?

27
Second Section Kants pessimism
  • Our concern is with actions of which perhaps the
    world has never had an example, with actions
    whose feasibility might be seriously doubted by
    those who base everything on experience i.e.
    empiricists, and yet with actions inexorably
    commanded by reason. For example, pure sincerity
    in friendship can be demanded of every man, and
    this demand is not in the least diminished if a
    sincere friend has never existed, because this
    duty, as duty in general, prior to all experience
    lies in the idea of reason which determines the
    will on a priori grounds (FP, p.650).

28
Second Section Kants pessimism
  • Think of this another way Kant is committed to
    the view that the a priori demands of reason are
    there to be discovered, but this does not mean
    that all or any rational beings will do so.
  • Isnt something like this readily conceded by
    anyone who believes that there is an objective
    ground to morality, and that there is a
    distinction to be made between what we do and
    what we ought to do?

29
Second Section Against the situatedness of moral
principles
  • (1) Moral laws must be valid universally. (This
    Kant takes to be fundamental to an understanding
    of the nature of morality).
  • (2) From this it follows that, where there is a
    moral agent, s/he or it ought to act in accord
    with the moral laws.
  • (3) From this it follows that the moral laws are
    not grounded in those properties that make a
    particular moral agent human or nonhuman.
  • (4) It must also be the case, then, that the
    moral laws are not grounded in particular (or
    localized) circumstances or cultures.
  • (5) Therefore, no set of experiences, no set of
    empirical facts, can ground or entail the moral
    laws (FP, p.651).

30
Second Section Against the situatedness of moral
principles
  • For Kant, if we try to ground our moral
    principles/laws on our nature, or in our moral
    practice, we may focus on principles or laws that
    only sensibly hold for humans, rather than for
    all moral agents.
  • However, if our moral principles or laws ought to
    hold for all moral agents, then we cannot ground
    our moral principles on our nature or moral
    practice (FP, pp.651, 653).
  • This leaves nowhere else to go than pure reason,
    according to Kant (FP, p.651).

31
Second Section Against the situatedness of moral
principles
  • But a completely isolated metaphysics of morals,
    mixed with no anthropology, no theology, no
    physics, or hyperphysics, and even less with
    occult qualities (which might be called
    hypophysical), is not only an indispensable
    substrate of all theoretically sound and definite
    knowledge of duties it is also a desideratum of
    the highest importance to the actual fulfillment
    of its precepts (FP, p.652).

32
Second Section categorical and hypothetical
imperatives
  • Hypothetical imperatives are conditionally
    necessary. Given a certain end (whether it is
    currently willed or not), one should act
    according to a certain principle (which will
    enable one to achieve that end) (FP, p.654).
  • Think of a hypothetical imperative as an
    if...then proposition. E.g. if you want to drive
    to university this morning, then you need to make
    sure there is enough gas in the car.

33
Second Section categorical and hypothetical
imperatives
  • Categorical imperatives are unconditionally
    necessary. That is, the imperative is not
    conditional on a certain end being willed (FP,
    p.654).
  • It is clear from what has already been covered
    that moral laws, under Kants account, are
    categorical imperatives (see FP, p.655).

34
Second Section categorical and hypothetical
imperatives
  • Kant will also contend that the content of the
    supreme categorical imperative from which our
    moral laws follow, can be deduced from the mere
    concept of a categorical imperative (page 658 of
    your FP).
  • This, of course, must be the case if the supreme
    categorical imperative is to hold for all
    rational beings (be they human or nonhuman, in
    our solar system or elsewhere)...right?

35
Second Section categorical and hypothetical
imperatives
  • But if I think of a categorical imperative, I
    know immediately what it will contain. For since
    the imperative contains, besides the law, only
    the necessity of the maxim of acting in
    accordance with the law, while the law contains
    no condition to which it is restricted, nothing
    remains except the universality of law as such to
    which the maxim of the action should conform and
    this conformity alone is what is represented as
    necessary by the imperative (FP, p.658).

36
Second Section the supreme categorical imperative
  • Since the supreme categorical imperative requires
    that all rational beings act in accord with it,
    without restrictions, the content of this
    imperative must be universal in scope.
  • There is also only one categorical imperative.
  • Thus Act only according to that maxim by which
    you can at the same time will that it should
    become a universal law (FP, p.658).
  • All other moral imperatives are derived from this
    principle (FP, p.658).

37
Second Section the second version of the
categorical imperative
  • Act as though the maxim of your action were by
    your will to become a universal law of nature
    (FP, p.658).
  • This, for Kant, captures the necessity attached
    to the supreme categorical imperative (FP,
    p.658). Understand it as a way of imagining a
    universe in which all rational agents perfectly
    follow the dictates of their reason.
  • Also note how he is more explicitly introducing
    the notion of autonomy (or self rule).
  • So understood such a law seemed to nicely mirror,
    in Kants view, the relationship between natural
    objects and the laws of nature (FP, p.658).

38
Second Section the second categorical imperative
  • Note in Kants examples of how to apply his
    procedure of deciding our duty there are two
    different ways in which we appear to run into
    trouble if we depart from what can be willed as a
    universal law.
  • (1) What we propose to do may, if universalized,
    self-destruct (examples 1 and 2 FP,
    pp.658-59).
  • (2) Even if what we propose to do does not
    self-destruct, it may be the case that we still
    cannot sincerely will it to be a universal law
    (examples 3 and 4 FP, p.659).

39
Second Section the second categorical imperative
  • Example 1 The Suicide Candidate (FP, pp658-69).
  • Example 2 The False Promise Maker (FP, p.659).
  • Example 3 The Talented (But Lazy) Person (FP,
    p.659).
  • Example 4 Selfish, and Unscrupulous, Rich Person
    (FP, p.659).
  • What do you think of his examples? Does his
    fourth example deal with Glaucons concerns in
    our previous readings?
  • What of his earlier claim, in connection to false
    promising, that immediately I see that I could
    will the lie but not a universal law to lie (FP,
    p.648)?
  • Are there counter-examples of morally acceptable
    lies?

40
Second Section the second categorical imperative
  • Note that in all of his examples, Kant seeks to
    infer our moral duties from the Supreme
    Categorical Imperative (FP, p.659).
  • The foregoing are a few of the many actual
    duties, or at least of duties we hold to be
    actual, whose derivation form the one stated
    principle is clear (FP, p.659).

41
Second Section on transgression
  • Kant suggests that when we shirk our moral duty
    we do not do so by not willing that our maxims
    become universal laws. Rather, we take the
    liberty of viewing ourselves as the exception,
    even if only momentarily (FP, p.660).
  • Is he right?

42
Second Section Rational beings as ends in
themselves
  • The third version of the supreme categorical
    imperative rests on a recognition that each of
    us, when we will an action, treat ourselves as
    ends in ourselves ... not merely as means. Since
    we could not (without contradiction) will
    ourselves to be regarded as means only, we ought
    not to treat other rational beings in this way
    (FP, p.662).
  • This is true whether we talk of hypothetical or
    categorical imperatives (FP, pp.661-62).
  • This Kant contends, is a duty of every rational
    agent (FP, p.662).
  • The third version reads Act so that you treat
    humanity, whether in your own person or in that
    of another, always as an end and never as a means
    only (FP, p.662).
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com