1) Una introduzione storica: come si sono sviluppati - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 111
About This Presentation
Title:

1) Una introduzione storica: come si sono sviluppati

Description:

1) Una introduzione storica: come si sono sviluppati i 'Nirvana' economici e giuridici ... The Nirvana domain does best whatever the other domain does. ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:112
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 112
Provided by: pagan
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: 1) Una introduzione storica: come si sono sviluppati


1

Analisi economica del diritto.
  • 1) Una introduzione storica come si sono
    sviluppati i Nirvana economici e giuridici
  • 2) Verso una nuova relazione fra diritto e
    economia.
  • 3) Analisi delle posizioni legali e
    complementarità istituzionali.

2
Letture scaricabili.
  • Nicita A., Pagano U. (2005) Law and Economics in
    Retrospect. In corso di stampa Brousseau E.
    Glachant J. M. ESNIE Textbook Cambridge Un.
    Press.
  • Pagano U. (2005) Legal Positions and
    Institutional Complementarities. In corso di
    stampa in Nicita Pagano Legal Orderings and
    Economic Insitutions. Routledge.
  • Pagano U. Diritto in Boitani e Rodano (1995)
    Relazioni Pericolose. Laterza, Bari.

3
The common ethical roots of law and economics
the existence of God-given natural laws.
  • From Aquinas Summa Theologica
  • The rational guidance of created things on the
    part of God, as prince of the universe, has the
    quality of law..this we can call the eternal
    law.
  • The participation in the eternal law by rational
    creatures is called natural law.
  • Law must have as its proper object the
    well-being of the whole community.

Isnt the last quotation applicable also to
Economics?
4
The importance of the scholastic tradition
From H. Berman Law and Revolution(p. 9) (The
revolution is that of the Pope Gregory VII
against the Emperor)
  • In the Western legal tradition law is conceived
    to be a coherent whole
  • The phrase corpus juris Romani was not used by
    the Romans but by the twelfth - and thirteenth -
    century European canonists.
  • It was the twelfth-century scholastic technique
    of reconciling contradictions and deriving
    general concepts from rules and cases that first
    made it possible to coordinate and integrate the
    Roman Law of Justinian.

5
Natural Law and Legal Pluralism.
  • In the formative era of the Western legal
    tradition, natural-law theory predominated. It
    was generally believed that human law derived
    ultimately from, and was ultimately to be tested
    by, reason and conscience.
  • This theory had a basis in Christian Theology as
    well as Aristotelian philosophy. But it had also
    a basis in the history of the struggle between
    ecclesiastical and secular authorities, and the
    politics of pluralism.
  • Legal pluralism was a common legal order
    containing diverse legal systems (church vs.
    crown, crown vs. town, town vs. lord, lord vs.
    merchant).
  • Legal Pluralism was a source of freedom and of
    legal sophistication and was a decisive factor in
    the foundation of Universities and the origin of
    Western Science.

6
Typical questions
  • Which Court had jurisdiction?
  • Which law was applicable?
  • How were different legal differences going to be
    reconciled?

Institutions, like Universities, where different
approaches could co-exist, were needed and
founded in that age. This method of formulating
and discussing different hypothesis and checking
their validity of natural laws was extended
from law to medicine and to other disciplines.
7
Classical British positivism and the separation
between law and ethics
  • Every law and rule is a command.
  • The science of jurisprudence (or, simply and
    briefly, jurisprudence) is concerned with
    positive laws, or with laws strictly so called,
    as considered without regard to their goodness or
    badness.
  • John Austin (17901859) The Province of
    Jurisprudence Determined.

A law may be defined as assemblage of signs
declarative of volition conceived or adopted by
the sovereign in a state, concerning the conduct
to be observed in a certain person or class of
persons, who in the case in question are supposed
to be the subject of his power. Jeremy Bentham
(17481832) Of Laws in General.
8
Kelsen (1881-1973) Pure Theory of the Law
  • The pure theory of law separates the legal
    completely from the moral norm and establishes
    the law as a specific system independent even of
    moral law.
  • The law, or the legal order, is a system of
    legal norms. The first question we have to
    answer, therefore, is this What constitutes the
    unity in diversity of legal norms? Why does a
    particular legal norm belong to a particular
    legal order? A multiplicity of norms constitutes
    a unity a system, an order when validity can be
    traced back to its final source in a single norm.

Morality ? Validity? Efficacy
9
Walras Elements of Pure Economics.
  • From Smith onwards also Political Economy had
    been following a similar path of separation of
    morality that achieves its clearest expression
    with the concept of Pareto efficiency.
  • Particular instructive is the case of Walras
    Pure Economics that, well before Kelsens Pure
    Theory of Law, was sharply distinguished from
    moral considerations.
  • However, Walras believed in two basic principles
    of natural law
  • Everyone belong to himself or herself.
  • All the other natural resources belong to
    everybody.

10
The main proposition of Pure Economics.
  • Production in a market ruled by free competition
    will give the greatest possible satisfaction of
    wants within the the double condition,
  • that each service and each product have only one
    price in the market, namely the price at which
    the quantity supplied equals the quantity
    demanded
  • and that the selling price of the products be
    equal to the cost of services employed in making
    them.
  • (Walras, Elements of Pure economics)

11
Pure economics and natural law
  • This double condition was also necessary for
    commutative justice that implied that individuals
    would not change their wealth because of unjust
    exchanges.
  • But if the achievement of the greatest
    satisfaction was compatible with commutative
    justice it would have sustained any initial
    distribution of resources including that
    consistent with the natural laws of distributive
    justice.
  • Thus, Walras pure economics was sharply separated
    from distributive natural laws but it was used to
    show that these laws were consistent with the
    maximization of material welfare.

12
Pure Economics and Pure Law.
  • The separation of both disciplines from ethics
    went together with the separation between law and
    economics.
  • Pure economics concentrate on the internal
    consistency (equilibrium) and efficiency of the
    decentralized decisions of maximizing
    individuals.
  • Pure law concentrated on the validity of laws,
    that is the internal consistency (equilibrium?)
    of legal systems that were assumed to stem from a
    single authority or from a single grundnorm.

The two disciplines seemed to live into separate
pure Nirvanas and, besides their purities, only
a formal analogy seemed to relate them. But
there were also some hidden relations between
the two Nirvanas..
13
Two related Nirvanas?
  • Pure Economics assumes well defined and complete
    rights that are exchanged and enforced by a third
    party. Thus the Economic Nirvana requires a Legal
    Nirvana.
  • Pure Law assumes that the legal ordering could be
    completed and made consistent by a single agent
    or on the basis of a set of basic norms without
    limitations due to bounded rationality, cognitive
    ability, failure of collective action and other
    limits due to the scarcity of resources. In other
    words the Legal Nirvana requires an Economic
    Nirvana.

14
Coase and the fall of the Economic Nirvana.
  • Coase observed that in the world of pure
    economics all decisions were coordinated by
    prices at zero costs.
  • In this world firms would not exist. We would
    live in what became later the world of the Coase
    theorem.
  • In the world of the Coase theorem all possible
    externalities, including those related to
    economies and diseconomies to scale would have
    been internalized by market transactions.
  • Firms, state regulation and other arrangements
    can only appear in a word where no alternative
    institution is available at zero costs.
  • There is no Economic Nirvana all institutions
    are costly.

15
Fuller and the fall of the Legal Nirvana.
  • Fuller defined law as the enterprise to subject
    to rules human behaviour.
  • This enterprise is too costly to be carried out
    by a centralized ordering.
  • The costs of Law can and are in fact decreased by
    decentralizing its enterprise to a plurality of
    orderings.
  • Unions, Churches and Universities have their
    internal orderings. Firms themselves can also be
    seen as private orderings.
  • There is no Legal Nirvana completeness, unity
    and consistency can possibly be the aim of a
    legal ordering but they cannot be taken for
    granted.

16
The firm as a private ordering
In a firm a central authority replaces markets
(and state authorities) in enforcing and
co-ordinating the relations among the agents.
However central governance has the disadvantage
that the agents will exercise their influence on
the central authority to enhance their
privileges. In order to work well firms need to
develop adequate forms of Private Ordering. Fulle
r the firm as a decentralization of the public
ordering Coase the firm as a centralization of
market transactions
Coase
Fuller
17
The economic consequences of Justice
  • In a Coase-theorem world with zero transaction
    costs attributing the rights to a particular
    individual has no economic consequences. In any
    case rights will flow to the individual who
    values them the most. We are in a Legal and
    Economic Nirvana where judges can ignore the
    economic consequences of their decisions.
  • In a world with positive transactions the
    decisions of the judges have economic
    consequences because rights will not necessarily
    flow efficiently to the individuals who value
    them the most. According to Posner (and to much
    classical Chicago, law and economics) in this
    case judges should allocate rights, according to
    criteria of economic efficiency to the
    individuals who value them the most.

18
Judges al wealth maximizers?
  • According to Posner, Judges, aware of the
    economic consequences of their actions should
    behave like quasi-markets attributing the rights
    to the individuals who in a world of zero
    transaction costs would have acquired them.
  • They apply the Kaldor criterion according to an
    allocation is efficient if the gainers could have
    compensated the losers.
  • He claims that this is consistent with an
    intuitive view of justice. If avoiding some
    damages is very costly for some agents and not
    costly for the others, the latter are guilty for
    the damages.

19
Fading boundaries?
  • Posner view is extreme. Clearly, in most cases,
    economic efficiency cannot be only criterion for
    the administration of justice. But it shows how
    difficult is to separate efficiency and justice
    considerations in a world of positive transaction
    costs.
  • The impossibility of defining sharp boundaries
    becomes even more clear when we accept Fullers
    view (and also Hayeks and Bruno Leonis
    views!) all sorts of public and private
    orderings co-exist in the economy and they all
    face the problem of compromising efficiency and
    (other types) of justice considerations.

20
Posners public ordering Nirvana.
  • In spite of these interesting implications for
    the activity of the judiciary, Posner pushes to
    extreme consequences the economists implicit
    assumption of a legal Nirvana where judges can
    efficiently fix the problems of the market
    economy.
  • This assumption implies that the judiciary is
    not limited by any form of economic scarcity
    (both in terms of cognitive and physical
    resources).

21
Williamsona symmetric private ordering Nirvana?
  • While Williamson rejects the idea of an efficient
    public ordering, he assumes that private
    orderings can efficiently fill the gaps that are
    left open by the incompletness and the efficiency
    of the public ordering.
  • Firms and the organizations of private governance
    are explained by their efficiency attributes.
    They fix the problems due to the incompletness of
    public domain contracts.

22
Posner vs. Williamson.
  • There is an evident (and explicit!)
    contraddiction between Williamson NIE and
    Posners law and economics each one is making a
    Nirvana assumptions about one different domain.
  • The Nirvana domain is fixing the inefficiencies
    of the other domain and, therefore, there is no
    feed-back of its inefficiency on the other
    domain.
  • In both cases there is no mutual interaction
    between the possible inefficiencies of the two
    domains. The Nirvana domain does best whatever
    the other domain does.

23
The institutional complementarities research
programme.
  • No institutional domain has Nirvana
    characteristics. All institutions are humans made
    and they are limited by several types of economic
    scarcity.
  • The agents of each domain take as given
    institutional parameters the arrangements of
    other domains.
  • Multiple equilibria can characterise the mutual
    interactions among different domains.
  • The interactions can be usefully expressed in
    terms of institutional complementarities.

24
The nature of institutional complementarities.
  • The existence of institutional complementarities
    implies that individuals of each can do better if
    their decisions fit the arragements taken in
    other domains.
  • Institutional complementarities are strong when,
    independently of the degree of rationality of the
    agents, the mismatch between the domains cannot
    last over time.
  • Institutional complementarities are weak when
    rational individuals will have a tendency to make
    the two domains fit each other.
  • Observe that, even when different domains fit, we
    may be in a situation of inefficiency if they can
    fit each other in multiple ways.

25
Legal positions and institutional
complementarities.
  • In the paper that has been indicated as the
    background reading of this talk we consider two
    major examples of strong and weak institutional
    complementarities.
  • Legal positions are claimed to be characterised
    by strong institutional complementarities.
  • The relations between legal entitlements, taken
    as a whole, and the technology of production is
    claimed to be characterised by weak institutional
    complementarities.
  • In this talk I will concentrate on the first
    case. I will have the time to consider the other
    cases in my other seminars.

26
Strong Complementarities and Social Scarcity.
In some cases the existence of some arrangements
in certain domains is a necessary condition for
the feasibility of other arrangements in other
domains. These extreme cases of complementarity
are more common than one may expect. Legal
relations are cases of strong complementarity
related to the problem of social
scarcity. Ex-ante an individual may expect to
have a right even if nobody else perceives the
corresponding duty. However, ex-post, one can
benefit from a right only if somebody else is
accepting to perform the corresponding duties and
give up the related liberties.
27
First order jural positions

Example 1 boat in danger. Boats that are in
danger enjoy some legal right to be helped by
other ships. This right is necessarily correlated
with the duty of other boats not to leave when
another ship is in danger. This duty does also
necessarily entails that other boats do not have
the liberty to leave and that boat that is danger
is not exposed to the liberty of other boat of
refusing help. Hohfeld W. N. (1919) Fundamental
Legal Conceptions Commons J. R.(1924) Legal
Foundations of Capitalism
28
Second order jural positions

Example 2 liberty of speech If, because of the
existence of a Bill of rights the State has no
power to change legal entitlements and restrict
my liberty of speech (Simmonds, 1986 p. 132),
this means that in this respect I have no
liability towards the state or, in other words,
an immunity against its power that is correlated
to the corresponding disability of the State.
29
Hohfeld vs Commons.
According to Hohfeld first order and second order
relations should necessarily fit as logical
necessities. In Commons approach the
expectations of the individuals could differ
widely ex-ante and the purpose of law was to make
ex-ante claims and expectations consistent with
each other. Second order relations are used to
make first order relations fit. Both public and
private orderings contribute with authorised and
authorative transactions to this goal. Mismatch
between legal positions is always costly. There
is clearly institutional complementarity between
the legal positions occurring in the different
domains and consistency makes individuals better
off. However consistency is a logical necessity
only ex-post.
30
Legal Positions and Social Scarcity.
The ex-ante mismatch of legal claims is not only
possible but also very likely. Legal positions
are characterised by the fact that the same
relation must be consumed with opposite signs by
different individuals. Legal relations involve
the consumption of positional goods like power
and status. While ex-ante legal disequilibrium
is likely it is very likely to occur because
positional goods are a case that is polar to
public goods.
31
Public and Positional Goods
Pure private good other individuals consumes a
zero amount of what each individual chooses to
consume. Pure public good each agent must
consume the same positive amount that other
agents decide to consume Pure positional good
given the consumption choice of an agent, the
other agent must consume a corresponding negative
amount of what the other agent chooses to
consume.
32

33
Legal Relations and the Oversupply of Positional
Goods
While public goods are undersupplied, positional
goods suffer from the opposite problem and they
are oversupplied. As Bobbio has pointed out the
oversupply of rights and liberties that are not
matched by the corresponding duties and exposure
to liberties is (in spite of Kelsen) an intrinsic
characteristic of the productions of laws.
34
Private property and institutional
complementarities
  • The right of exclusive use of assets by some
    individuals has to be correlated to the duties of
    others not to consume these resources.
  • 2) The liberty that the owners have to choose
    among different uses of the resources is to be
    correlated to the exposure of others to these
    liberties.
  • 3) The power that the private owner has to
    transfer her title has to be aligned to the
    liability that the other agents have towards
    these transfers of property.
  • 4) The immunity of the owner against having his
    title altered or transferred by the act of
    another is to be aligned to the disability of
    others to perform these acts.
  • Ex-ante the legal positions defining private
    property may be inconsistent. Ex-post they become
    identities.

35
An example the elettricity industry.
  • Besides private property competitive markets rely
    on other characteristics. Individuals must have
    the liberty to enter any market which means that
    no incumbent has the right to exclude other
    individuals from other markets and they must be
    exposed to this liberty. When this liberty does
    not exist the value of property goes down there
    is no clearcut distinctions between the
    characteristics of the markets and the nature of
    property.
  • In the case of elettricity industry this liberty
    and the simple exposure to it are not enough.
    Entrants have also a right to be connected to the
    network which requires the active cooperation of
    the incumbent. Incumbents must not simply be
    exposed to the liberty of the entrants but have a
    correlative duty to act to provide
    interconnection.Legal disequilibrium may easily
    arise
  • If Liberties and Rights of the entrants are set
    up in Brussels at community level
  • The corresponding exposures and duties are
    articulated at national level.

36
The limits of private property.
Like the Coasian firm, in a world of zero
transaction costs, the main advatage of private
property disappears. Private property entails the
liberty to change the use of goods without having
to transact with other individuals - an advantage
that only holds in a world of positive
transaction costs. In a world of positive
transaction costs private property may be
advantageous even when there is a limited
exposure of the other individuals to the
liberties of the owner. At the same time the
labour contract cannot be considered as a
temporary private property of somebody else
labour. This is efficient only in the standard
neoclassical model where leisure and not work
enters the utility fuction so that the workers
can sell their labour and be indifferent among
its uses.
37
Private property and capitalism.
The genuine neoclassical solution would involve
that there is a price for each use of labour.
There is no symmetry between capital and labour
(despite Samuelson). For capital the price is the
same in each use!!! The symmetric treatment of
capital and labour makes labour a fictious
commodity over which temporary private property
can be defined. It does not describe an
unqualified economic Nirvana but the Nirvana for
capitalism! Workers cooperatives have been ofter
claimend to be alternative to this model. If
capital has no preferences for its use in
production choosy labour should hire malleable
capital! There are well-known limitations with
this solution and other alternative have involved
the unbundling and the redistribution of the
rights that define classical capitalism.
38
Models of capitalism and social scarcity
1) Classical capitalism Liberty of the employers
vs. workers' rights to care about the allocation
of their work. No private exercise of this
liberty without a damaging exposure to this
liberty. Complete liberty to use machines. 2)
Company workers' capitalism. Right to a job of
unspecified definition in a particular company.
The liberty of capitalists to use their machines
with all possible workers is umbundled and
redistributed as a job right for the present
workers of the firm. 3) Unionised workers'
capitalism. Exclusive right to job of specified
definitions in all the companies. The liberty of
the capitalists to employ their machines workers
with all sorts of qualifications is unbundled and
redistributed as job right for the workers
belonging to a certain craft.
39
Each one of the model of capitalism that we have
just considered is defined by different domains
such as markets for capital and market for labour
that must fit each other according to the tough
conditions of the strong institutional
complementarity due to social scarcity. There
is no Nirvana domain that, independetly of its
historical evolution involves an overall
efficient solutions for all of them. There is
not even a relative Nirvana because each model of
capitalism may end up developing particular
comparative institutional advantages due to the
symbiotic relations between its system of rights
and its technology. The curiosity for this
institutional diversity may perhaps compensate us
for all the lost Nirvanas of Law and Economics!
40
A more general definition of institutional
complementarities.
It is desirable to capture the case of
complementarities by referring to a more general
case where the institutional arrangements
occurring in one domain are simply favouring the
institutional arrangement in another domain but
they are not a necessary condition for their
(ex-post) existence. Samuelson statement In a
perfectly competitive economy it doesn't really
matter who hires whom...." It implies a double
neutrality. Technology does not influence rights.
Rights do not influence technology. One may
want challenge this statement by observing that
some technological arrangements do simply favour
some property rights and other organizational
safeguards and vice versa (and not that the
former are impossible when the latter do not
exist).
41
The Notion of Institutional Complementarity
(Aoki, 2001)
  • Economic agents face different domains of games
    in selecting their choice in a given
    institutional framework choices in one domain
    act as exogenous parameters in other domains and
    vice-versa
  • EXAMPLE
  • two domains of choices X and Y X1, X2 and Y1,
    Y2, with agents i choosing in X and agents j
    choosing in Y, according to their utilities
    (respectively, u for i and v for j).
  • a) for agent i
  • b) for agent j
  • There can be one Nash equilibrium, but also two
    pure Nash equilibria (institutional arrangements)
    for the system as (X1,Y1) and (X2,Y2).
  • When such multiple equilibria exist, we say that
  • (i) X1 and Y1 are institutional
    complements
  • (ii) X2 and Y2 are institutional
    complements.

42
Different cases of weak complementarities
  • Property rights and technology.
  • Skills and Intellectual Property Rights.
  • Financial Structure and Specificity of the
    Investments.

43
New Institutional theory has emphasized that
owners of specific and hard-to-monitor resources
tend to acquire rights and safeguards more than
the owners of general purpose and easy-to monitor
resource. This claim can be stated as (1) In
the property right domain, a property right
system PC is marginally better than another
property right system PL if the corresponding
technology Tc instead of the technology TL
prevails in the technology domain. Where Tc a
technology where capital is intensively used as a
specific and hard to monitor resource TL
technology where labour is intensively used as a
specific and hard to monitor resource PC a
governance system where the owners of capital
have strong rights and safeguards PL a
governance system where workers have strong
rights and Safeguards.
44
Inverting the Argument.
In a word of positive transaction costs the
owners of resources enjoying rights and
safeguards tend to become more specific and hard
to monitor than those without rights and
safeguards. This claim can be stated as (2) In
the technology domain a technology TL is
marginally better than a technology Tc if a
property right system PL instead of property
right system PC prevails in the property right
domain. This is an argument that has been
typical emphasized by radical economists against
the efficiency predictions of NIE. However, it is
consistent when NIE when one assumes positive
transaction costs.
45
(1) In the property right domain a property right
system PC is marginally better than another
property right system PL if the corresponding
technology Tc instead of the technology TL
prevails in the technology domain. (2) In the
technology domain a technology TL is marginally
better than a technology Tc if a property right
system PL instead of property right system PC
prevails in the property right domain. Where Tc
a technology where capital is intensively used
as a specific and hard to monitor resource TL
technology where labour is intensively used as a
specific and hard to monitor resource PC a
governance system where the owners of capital
have strong rights and safeguards PL a
governance system where workers have strong
rights and safeguards. We can have multiple
equilibria (PC, Tc) and (PL, TL ) PC and Tc and
PL and TL are, in this case, institutional
complements.
46
Pagano Rowthorn 1994
(2) Inverted argument Under capitalist
ownership (PC) firms maximise Rc Q (k,K,l,L)
- rk RK wl (HW)L (1) -----gt(Tc)
Under labour ownership (PL) firms maximise RL
Q (k,K,l,L) - rk (ZR)K wl WL (2)
----- gt(TL) (1) Original NIE argument
Capitalist property
rights PC can prevail if Rc ? RL or, ZK
- HL ? 0 (3) lt----- (Tc)
workers' property rights PL can prevail if RL
? Rc, or HL - ZK ? 0
(4) lt----- (TL) We can have multiple
self-enforcing equilibria (PC, Tc) and (PL, TL )
that are institutional complements.
47
Conditions for organizational equilibria

Let (kc,,Kc, lc, Lc) argmax Rc (k, K, l,
L) (5) (kL,
KL, lL, LL) argmax RL (k, K ,l, L) (6)
Then a firm will be in
a capitalist organisational equilibrium (COE)
if ZKc - HLc ? 0
(7)
and in a labour organisational
equilibrium (LOE) if HLL - ZKL ? 0
(8)
Or
48
Multiplicity of organizational equilibria
Kc/Lc ? H/Z
(7') KL/LL
? H/Z
(8') Because
(HW)/R ? W/(ZR) we have
Kc/Lc ? KL/LL
(9) We have therefore 3 cases 1) Kc/Lc ?
H/Z ? KL/LL
(10)
(multiple organisational equilibria). 2)
Kc/Lc ? KL/LL gt H/Z
(11)
(only a COE exists). 3) H/Z gt Kc/Lc ? KL/LL
(12)
(only a LOE
exists).
49
Organizational equilibria and complementarities
a) because of (1) and (2) when a property right
system PC (instead of the property right system
PL) prevails, a technology Tc (characterised by
a higher ratio K/L than a technology TL) does
marginally better than TL. b) (3) and (4) imply
that, when a technology Tc instead of a
technology TL prevails PC, does marginally better
than PL. Thus, the supermodularity conditions
are satisfied in the model and we can have
multiple organizational equilibria where PC is an
instituional complement of Tc and PL is an
institutional complement of TL
50
Institutional Complementarity between ownership
of intellectual property rights and firms
capabilities.(Pagano, Rossi EJLE 2004)
We interpret the NPR approach as a model of
allocation of IPR. The firms and individuals that
that are more capable to make investments
specific to the improvement of these assets
should acquire them.
  • The argument can again be inverted If
    transaction costs prevent property rights from
    being attributed to the efficient owner,
    whoever is the current owner will find it more
    convenient to invest in human capital specific to
    the assets.
  • A double relation of causation should be
    considered. If property rights are chosen on the
    basis of given technologies and abilities, also
    the opposite is true abilities and technologies
    are chosen on the basis of existing property
    rights
  • HIGH FIRM CAPABILITIES AND A RICH PORTFOLIO of
    IPR are institutional complements. And,
    unfortunately also low firm capabilities and a
    poor portfolio of IPR are institutional
    complements.

Firms Capabilities
Intellectual Property
51
Institutional Complementarity between financial
and technological structures. (Nicita-Pagano ALEA
2003, revised 2004 )
Williamson (1988) describes a direction of
causality moving from asset specificity to firms
financial structure, and then to firms
governance Prevalence of specific assets ------gt
Equity Finance Prevalence of general-purpose
assets -----gt Debt Finance
In the language of institutional
complementarites Equity finance is marginally
better than Debt Finance in the financial domain
when a technology characterised by a prevalence
of specific assets over general-purpose assets is
adopted in the technology domain.
52
In word of positive transaction costs the
argument can again be inverted
Equity Finance ------gt Prevalence of specific
assets Debt Finance -----gt Prevalence of
general-purpose assets
In the language of institutional
complementarites An asset-specific intensive
technology is marginally better than a general
purpose technology in the technology domain when
a financial structure with equity funding over
debt funding is adopted in the financial
domain. A high degree of equity finance and a
prevalence of specific assets are institutional
complements and, similarly, also a high degree of
debt funding and general purpose assets are
institutional complements.
53
The US Tayloristic model
(PA) A distribution of rights that gives
shareholders and management strong liberties
including the liberty to fire easily the workers.
The workers are exposed to this liberty and have
no right to a well-defined occupation or to some
generic job within a certain firm. The firm can
be traded as a commodity and takeovers often
imply that the implicit contracts of the workers
can be easily broken by new management. (TA)
The centralization of knowledge in the hands of
management and top-down co-ordination and
innovations workers at the bottom of the
hierarchy perform very detailed jobs and have to
execute very narrow and rigid instructions.
54
The Tayloristic model as an organizational
equilibrium
PA -----gt TA Weak rights decrease the intensity
of Labour as a high-agency cost factor. TA
-----gt PA Because workers tend to be
low-agency-cost factors they rarely have
organizational or occupational rights. Self-reinf
orcing organizational equilibrium -----gt PA
-----gt TA -----gt PA -----gt The U. S a.
Market-led economy? (i) market for low-skilled
jobs (ii) market for companies.
55
The Japanese Model.
(PJ) A distribution of rights limiting some
shareholders and management liberties including
the liberty to fire the workers who hold the
right to a job of unspecified nature in the
organization. Main banking and cross-shareholding
isolate the firm from the stock exchange and
protect the workers implicit contracts from the
risk of take-takeovers. (TJ) The
decentralisation of a great deal of knowledge and
some bottom-up co-ordination and innovations
workers have to rotate among different jobs and
acquire remarkable firm-specific jobs as well as
an overall vision of the way in which production
could be improved.
56
The Japanese Model as an Organizational
Equilibrium.
Also here -----gt PJ -----gt TJ -----gt PJ
-----gt PJ -----gt TJ Because workers have rights
in the organization some agency cost (monitoring
and specificity risk) are "cancelled". This
biases the technology towards a high intensity of
high-agency-cost labour. TJ -----gt PJ Because
the technology is intensive in high-agency-cost
workers (very specific and difficult-to
-monitor), more agency costs can be "cancelled"
by giving them rights in the organization.
57
The German Model property rights
(PG) A distribution of rights limiting some
shareholder and management liberties including
the liberty to organise some aspect of the
division of labour and of job specification. Unio
ns and employers' associations acquire the right
to interfere with the organization of production
of each single firm. Co-determination with
union representatives hold for the firms with
more than 200 employees. Banks have an important
in corporate governance through credit, direct
acquisition of shares and proxy voting, they make
it very difficult hostile take-takeovers and
their presence in many board of directors favours
the co-ordination among firms.
58
The German Model Technology.
(TG) The decentralisation of a great deal of
knowledge and some bottom-up co-ordination are
also a characteristic of the German system jobs
are standardised across firms and workers can
change organization finding equivalent
occupational slots in the different firms that
share a similar division of labour.
59
The German Model as an Organizational Equilibrium
PG----gt TG Occupational Rights bias technology
toward firm-general-purpose but occupational
specific rights. TG ----gt PG A technology
intensive of occupational specific rights makes
it convenient to decrease the agency costs of
occupational skills through the attribution of
occupational rights
60
Rigidity and Flexibility
American Capitalism organizational and
occupational flexibility. Japanese
Capitalism organizational flexibility and
occupational rigidity German Capitalism organiza
tional rigidity and occupational flexibility

Occupational rigidity
Organizational flexibility
Occupational flexibility
Organizational rigidity
61
Changes in the Biodiversity of Capitalism
Different rights -----------gt Different agency
costs-----gt Different factor prices------gt
Different Institutional Comparative Advantage
-------- (Because of Globalization)---------gt I
ncreased specialization in the sectors where the
country has an Institutional Comparative
Advantage -------------------gt
Institutional Specialization ----------gt
------gt Increase in inter-country
Institutional Biodiversity ------gt Decrease
in intra-country Institutional Biodiversity
62
Globalization may increase the Biodiversity of
Capitalism
Thus, as a result of Globalization, the variety
of models of capitalism should not tend to
decrease. For instance, the U. S. should
specialize even more its institutions in goods
and processes requiring top-down co-ordination
and innovation while Germany and Japan should
specialize its institutions in different goods
and processes requiring bottom-up co-ordination
and innovation. All models could co-exist
increasing and exploiting their institutional
differences according to the well-know principles
of comparative advantage.
63
The commodification of intellectual capital a
global revenge of Taylorism?
Increasing biodiversity good picture of the
eighties? Even then American attempt to imitate
Japan. In the nineties the situation got
completely reversed and America seems to be the
model that everyone should imitate. What
happened? Here, we should consider
Globalization not simply as cultural and economic
integration but as a new set of political
conditions that has allowed the global definition
and enforcement of property rights and, in
particular, of intellectual property rights.
64
Intellectual property rights are global rights.
Intellectual property rights cannot be locally
defined and enforced like the rights on physical
assets. For a physical asset the existence in a
given location implies that it is not used in
other locations. For intellectual assets
non-rivalry in use implies that the enforcement
of property rights should be global. In nineties
the downfall of the Soviet Union made it possible
a much stronger definition and enforcement of
Intellectual Private Property Rights.
65
When there is weak enforcement of IPR (80')
a) More technologically advanced countries give
free knowledge to less advanced countries.
Catch-up is possible. b) Top down co-ordination
and innovations systems, based on the
transmission of precise and formalised knowledge,
are easily exploitable by bottom-up co-ordination
systems based on informal and tacit knowledge.
The knowledge developed by the former can be
appropriated by the latter while the opposite is
not possible.
66
When there is strong enforcement of IPR (90)
a') More advanced countries can exploit with
monopoly prices less advanced countries. A
widening gap is possible. b') Top-down
co-ordination and innovation systems, based on
the transmission of precise and formalised
knowledge, are better suited for the production
of IPRs than bottom-up systems that produce
informal and tacit knowledge. Thus, the global
enforcement of IPR favoured the U. S. in both
respects. This may explain the change from the
eighties to the nineties.
67
A revenge of Taylorism?
There is pressure to adopt this new version of
Taylorism where commodified knowledge (or reified
intellectual) capital separates conception from
execution. Fundamental difference between
private property of intellectual and physical
assets - The exclusion from access to a
physical asset is a local exclusion access to
other similar assets in different locations is
usually possible. - The exclusion from access to
an intellectual asset is a global exclusion
access to other similar assets in other locations
is not usually possible.
68
A new model of accumulation?
The New Property Right Approach has stressed the
incentive effect of ownership of specific assets
in a world of incomplete contracts. However,
these incentive effects are much stronger for
intellectual regime.
The complementarity between the accumulation of
skills and intellectual capital may generate
increasing inequality
-----gt Ownership of Intellectual Capital -----gt
Incentive to acquire new IPR-specific skills
-- -----gt Ownership of more Intellectual Capital
- --------gt
69
Cutural standardisation another dimension of
globalization
  • Markets are complicated instituions that require
    also important cultural changes.
  • We will consider
  • The relation between culture and division of
    labour in agrarian societies.
  • The relations between them in market and
    industrial societies.
  • How the relations changes with globalization.

70
This seminar draws on
Bowles S., Pagano U. (2003) Economic Integration,
Cultural Standardisation and the Politics of
Social Insurance. Quaderni del Dipartmento di
Economia Politica N. 408 Università di Siena.
Forthcoming in Bardhan P., Bowles S., Wallerstein
M. (2005) Globalization and Egalitarian
Redistribution Russell Sage Foundation and the
Princeton University Press, Princeton D'Antoni
M., Pagano U (2002) National Cultures and Social
Protection as Alternative Insurance Devices.
Structural Change and Economic Dynamics, Vol. 13
pp. 367-386 . Pagano U. (2003) Nationalism,
Development and Integration the Political
Economy of Ernest Gellner. Cambridge Journal of
Economics V. 27 N. 5 pp.623-646. Pagano U, Rossi
M. A. (2004) Incomplete Contracts, Intellectual
Property and Institutional Complementarities. The
European Journal of Law and Economics V.18 pp.
55-76. .
71
Babbage Principle of the division of labour.
  • "That the master manufacturer, by dividing the
    work to be executed into different processes,
    each requiring different degrees of skills or
    force, can purchase exactly that precise quantity
    of both which is necessary for each process
    whereas, if the whole work were executed by one
    workman, that person must possess sufficient
    skill to perform the most difficult, and
    sufficient strength to execute the most
    laborious, of the operations in which that art is
    divided."(Babbage, 1832 pp.137-8).

72
According to Babbage
  • The division of labour entails
  • - the exploitation of the principle of
    comparative advantage (because it allows each
    individual to perform only that activity in which
    she is comparatively more gifted).
  • - a dramatic saving of training time.
  • If each worker is performing all the tasks
    necessary for a certain productive process , it
    also becomes necessary that each worker learn all
    these tasks.
  • By contrast if a very detailed division of labour
    happens to be introduced, and each worker is
    assigned only one task, then she obviously has to
    learn only that task.

73
Babbage and Taylor
  • Braverman (1974) pointed out how the three main
    principles of Taylor's "scientific management"
    implied respectively
  • a) the dissociation of the labour process from
    the skills of the workers
  • b) the separation of conception from execution
  • c) the use of management's knowledge of the
    productive process to plan and control each step
    of the productive process.
  • In this respect "Taylorism" can be considered as
    a detailed set of corollaries of the
    Gioia-Babbage principle.

74
Hierarchy and the firm
  • The Gioia-Babbage principle gives powerful
    reasons for the relative efficiency of an
    authoritarian and detailed division of labour. It
    offers a normative justification for the
    hierarchical structure of the firm hierarchies
    increase productivity, and therefore human
    welfare, because they save on the learning
    necessary to acquire new skills and use more
    efficiently given skills because of the principle
    of comparative advantage.
  • Command giving and taking save on training costs.
  • Firms exists because the evaluation of command is
    costly?
  • (Indeed, the great informational advantage of
    command is that you do not have to evaluate it)

75
Smithian principles of the division of labour.
  • The difference in skills more a consequence
    than a cause of the division of labour. There is
    little comparative advantage to be exploited
    before the introduction of the division of
    labour. The differences in skills arise as a
    consequence of the introduction of the division
    of labour.
  • Smithian principles of the division of labour
    improved dexterity, saving of time otherwise
    spent on changing occupation, and invention of
    machines by workmen. Specialization favours the
    acquisition of job-specific skills.

76
Smith vs. Babbage.
  • Babbage concentrate on the advantages due to an
    optimal utilization of given skills
  • Smith the advantages of the division of labour
    due to a better acquisition of new skills,
  • Babbage the division of labour increases
    productivity because it minimises the amount of
    learning which is required for doing.
  • Smith the division of labour increases
    productivity because it maximizes the amount of
    learning acquired by doing.
  • For Babbage the learning necessary for the doing
    should be minimized
  • For Smith the learning due to the doing should
    be maximized.

77
Time profile of Smith and Babbage principles.
  • The benefits of the Babbage principles is
    different occur immediately by reducing the
    training time
  • The Smithian principles take more time. They
    occur after that the workers have acquired
    additional skills because of the learning by
    doing process.
  • Overall optimization problem of productivity over
    time often involves some compromise between the
    degrees of specialization suggested by the
    Babbage and the Smithian principles.

78
Degrees of specialization.
  • The Smithian principles involve a less detailed
    division of labour than that which the
    Gioia-Babbage principle does.
  • Increases in specialization decrease the
    learning required for doing certain activities,
    but, after a certain point, they may also inhibit
    the future advantages to be gained from the
    learning by doing process. In this case enlarging
    the job may be a way of exploiting the Smithian
    advantages.
  • Work satisfaction (also enphasized by Smith)
    points in the same direction.

79
Babbage-type and Smith-type workers
  • Up to now we have spoken in terms of an optimal
    average degree of specialization involved by the
    two principles.
  • In actual market economies some workers enjoy the
    Smithian advantages of learning by doing and
    others are employed in such a way to minimize
    training time.
  • In the global economy this has also become often
    a distinction between workers of core
    industrialized countries and of third world
    countries.

80
The market and the division of labour.
  • According to Smith the market is the ultimate
    cause of the division of labour and its size
    limits the extension of the division of labour.
  • However, as Marx and Coase, pointed out some
    years later firms have a division of labour
    without exchanges. Moreover in primitive and
    agrarian societies there is a sophisticated
    division of labour but there are very
    underdeveloped markets.
  • So, what is the link between specialization and
    market economies?

81
According to Gellner,
  • Markets may inhibit the division of labour.
  • The job mobility that is typical of markets
    implies that acquiring job specific skills may be
    more dangerous than in agrarian societies. How is
    this problem overcome?
  • Here the role of cultural standardisation and of
    nationalism becomes very important.

82
Agrarian vs.. Market Industrial Economies.
Agrarian societies Horizontal and vertical
cultural and linguistic diversity are a product
and a cause of social and economic
immobility. Linguistic/cultural diversity and
socio/geographical immobility are complementary
elements of a very stable institutional
equilibrium.

Industrial societies Horizontal and vertical
cultural and linguistic standardisation are a
product and a cause of social and economic
mobility. Linguistic/cultural homogenization and
socio/geographical mobility are complementary
elements of a very stable institutional
equilibrium.
83
Institutional Equilibrium of the Agrarian Society
----gt Economic stagnation ----gt No structural
changes ----gt Immobile division of labour ----gt
Vertical and horizontal cultural
differentiation (no nationalism) ----gt No
reward for productive effort and innovation ----gt
Economic stagnation ----gt
84
Institutional Equilibrium of the Industrial
Society.
----gt Economic development ----gt Frequent
structural changes ----gt Mobile division of
labour ----gt Social mobility and cultural
homogenisation (nationalism) ----gt Rewards for
productive effort and innovation ----gt Economic
development ----gt
85
Stable Institutional EquilibriaAgrarian Society
Social and Economic Immobility
Horizontal and Cultural Diversity
86
Stable Institutional EquilibriaIndustrial
Society
Social and Economic Mobility
Horizontal and Cultural Standardisation
87
Transition from agrarian to industrial societies.
It requires a marriage between a State (a
potential National State) and a High Culture to
be spread on the majority of the population.
Ideal initial conditions (France and England) a
single State ruling on a territory with a shared
view of the dominant high culture. Italy and
Germany a groom (National State) for a bride (a
high culture). Belgium and Switzerland symmetric
cases? The difficult Balkans no groom and no
bride?
88
Political conditions and cultural- linguistic
differentiation
89
Gellners Problem.
Adam Smith a market economy entails the
learning by doing advantages associated to the
division of labour Marx underlined how a complex
division of labour pre-dates market economies and
Coase (and Marx) how the division of labour is
organised also by other institutions such as
firms. Gellners problem contrary to Smiths
intuition the highly mobile market economy would
be the most unfriendly environment for promoting
the acquisition of job-specific skills. Gellners
Solution complementary institutions (mainly
nationalism), promoting cultural standardisation
and social protection, make market mobility
compatible with a complex division of labour
90
According to Schumpeter
  • Industrial mutation ..... incessantly
    revolutionises the economic structure from
    within, incessantly destroying the old one,
    incessantly creating a new one. This process of
    Creative Destruction is the essential fact about
    capitalism. It is what capitalism consists of and
    what every capitalist concern has got to live in
  • The problem may be reformulated by saying that
    the fear of future "Destruction" may seriously
    inhibit the "Creative" element of Capitalism.
    Specialising in new skills and equipment may be
    inhibited by the fear that they will soon become
    old and redundant.

91
Keynes and illiquidity.
  • From the General Theory
  • capital equipment will differ from another "(a)
    in the variety of the consumable in the
    production of which they are capable of
    assisting, ......(c) in the rapidity with which
    the wealth embodied in them can become "liquid",
    in the sense of producing output, the proceeds of
    which can be re-embodied if desired in quite a
    different form"
  • Extending the Keynesian concept the lack of
    liquidity of specialised (human and non-human)
    capital may inhibit specialised investments (in
    both human and non-human investments). It may
    favour Babbage over Smith.

92
Williamson and the safeguards for specific
investments
  • The degree of specificity of investments is
    measured by the percentage of these investments
    and it is not substantially different from the
    concept of (lack of) liquidity considered above.
    When complete contracts are not possible, agents
    who make specific investments cannot defend
    themselves against opportunistic behaviour by
    moving their investment to alternative relations
    with new partners. They need safeguards for these
    investments.
  • Job rights and safeguards are not necessarily
    inefficient limitations to market mobility but
    they can rather be efficient ways of encouraging
    human capital investments

93
Williamson and the market economy dilemma.
  • The mobility of market economy could inhibit the
    "specific" investment in human capital that are
    typically associated to the Smithian advantages
    of the division of labour.
  • A market economy would find itself in this
    dilemma
  • either to give up the productivity improvements
    that come with the learning by doing Smithian
    advantages,
  • or to give up that mobility among occupations
    that is the most typical characteristics of
    markets.

94
Gellner and New Institutional Economics.
  • A) Cultural standardisation can eliminate a lot
    of specificy. Liquid markets emerge with cultual
    nationalism. The large majority of assets are
    specific in agrarian societies. Specificity or
    liquidity are not technologically given but they
    can be altered by national policies.
  • B) National solidarity can reduce the risks of
    specificy. Unemployment benefits and subdised
    retraining imply that one has more time to find
    the right employer and to retrain if he is not
    available.
  • C) The specifity risk re-appears in the form of
    specificity to a certain culture. Investments in
    this culture require appropriate poltical
    safeguards.
  • D) Only, when all this fails, we are in
    Williamsons world of private governance.
  • E) Institutional complexity related more to
    liquidity than to specificity.

95
Globalism the highest stage of nationalism?
Like nationalism, globalism favours a
self-reinforcing interaction between cultural
standardisation and various forms of market
mobility. (But, because of globalism a new
diversification emerges in many national
states). Unlike nationalism, globalism does not
stress the complementarity aspects between social
protection and cultural standardisation.
Economic integration is not associated to
redistribution and risk- sharing among the
individuals sharing the same culture. Social
policy becomes a divisive issue. Some individuals
(the cosmopolitans and/or the rich) can more
easily replace social protection with cultural
standardisation than other individuals (the
provincial and/or the poor).
96
Globalism is unrestricted cultural and economic
integration without social protection (offered at
international level). But can nations still
offer social insurance at national level in a
global economy? Can the gains due to
international trade fund the insurance
expenses due to the risks of increased
specialization?
Social insurance can be provided if there is a
sufficient number of sectors in the
economy. Specialization and economic integration
increase collective risk and imply that
countries find it more difficult to offer social
insurance. The optimal degree of specialization
should involve that the marginal gains from
specialization should offset the increase in risk
due to specialization. However, the number of
sectors is a public good and private agents will
tend to overspecialize the national economy.
97
  • If globalism is economic and cultural integration
    without
  • social protection, it implies
  • a) Increased international cultural
    standardisation among nations
  • but increased vertical cultural diversity within
    nations (cosmopolitans and provincials).
  • Neo-agrarian characteristics of the modern
    globalised world?
  • b) Decreased social protection due to the absence
    or the weakening of international and national
    social protection. The argument can be also based
    on the tendency to overspecialise according to
    the standard theory of comparative advantage.

While international institutions provide enforce
IPR and various standards they provide little
insurance for the specialised economy. In this
sense globalization is also a transition to a
world of uncertainty where the different sectors
cannot insure each other.
98
Globalization summing up the argument
  • 1) Globalism is (like nationalism) characterised
  • by cultural standardisation and economic
    integration.
  • Unlike nationalism, the process occurs in an
    international environment
  • without forms of social protection.
  • Moreover specialization, which is carried out
    according to the
  • standard principle of comparative advantage may
    imply that each
  • country overspecialises and it is unable to
    offer social insurance
  • for the losers.
  • 2) Specialization according to the principle of
    comparative institutional advantage may imply
    that for some countries there is counter-tendency
    (as long as social protection and job rights
    allow some form of Comparative institutional
    advantage).
  • 3) However, this countertendency may be rather
    weakened by the fact that globalization is also
    associated to stronger and upstreamed IPRs.

99
Globalization are we moving towards a
neo-agrarian society?
  • There are some paradoxical similarities between
    the inequalities of
  • the modern world and those of agrarian societies
  • a) Vertical and horizontal cultural diversity due
    to differential
  • access to the global culture.
  • b) Lack of social security and solidarity.
  • c) A new cosmopolitan aristocracy based on
    monopolies
  • on Intellec
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com