Title: THE ETHICS OF CAPITAL PUNISHMENT
1THE ETHICS OF CAPITAL PUNISHMENT
Electric Chair, Andy Warhol, 1971
2How to Argue About the Death Penalty
Hugo Adam Bedau
3FACTUAL ISSUES
- Bedau begins his paper by noting that the death
penalty controversy in the U. S. has largely
considered certain questions of fact, and has not
really concentrated on the normative
propositions crucial to the dispute which are of
greater importance. - The questions of fact are four
- 1. Is the death penalty a greater deterrent to
murder than life imprisonment without parole? - 2. Is the death penalty applied in a
discriminatory way? - 3. What is the risk that an innocent person
will be executed? - 4. What is the risk that a convicted murderer
who is not executed will kill again in or out of
jail, if not given life without parole ?
4ANSWERS TO THE FACTUAL QUESTIONS
- For Bedau the answers to these four questions
are - 1. There is no evidence that the death penalty
is a better deterrent to murder than life in
prison. Both life in prison and execution seem
about equally ineffective. - 2. There is good evidence that the death
penalty is not applied to everyone equally but
race makes a difference. - 3. The risk to an innocent person cannot be
calculated but the risk is not zero. - 4. There is recidivism amongst murders, and so
there is that risk that they will kill again.
5THE ETHICAL RELEVANCE OF FACTS I
- Bedau says that the important thing to see here
is that the answers to the questions cannot by
themselves answer the question of the morality of
the death penalty. - Even though Bedau thinks that the death penalty
should be abolished, he says that the facts as
they stand cannot show that the death penalty
ought to be eliminated. - The facts also do not show that life imprisonment
is better than the death penalty.
6THE ETHICAL RELEVANCE OF FACTS II
- The death penalty is not the only form of
punishment in which discrimination occurs, but
discrimination is found in other kinds of
punishment as well. - In addition, and as far as the facts are
concerned, it can always be argued that such
discrimination will decrease over time, and, if
that were the case then one could not use the
former fact of discrimination as an argument
against the morality of the death penalty.
7THE ETHICAL RELEVANCE OF FACTS III
- Bedau says that the important point when we
consider facts which concern the death penalty is
that the empirical evidence is not the major
factor in explaining why settling disputes over
matters of fact cannot settle the larger
controversy about the death penalty itself. - Rather, the larger controversy concerns the
morality of the death penalty. That is, whether
the death penalty should be legal or not is a
moral question which cannot be argued from facts.
8THE ETHICAL RELEVANCE OF FACTS IV
- Arguments in favor of or in opposition to the
death penalty will have to be moral arguments.
They will have to be normative and not just
practical. - That is, we have to look at what standard to
adopt, and not what uses or abuses may follow
from the adoption of that standard.
9THE ETHICAL RELEVANCE OF FACTS V
- Bedau As a matter of sheer logic, it is not
possible to deduce a policy conclusion (such as
the desirability of abolishing the death penalty)
from any set of factual premises, however general
and well supported. - Bedau Any argument intended to recommend
continuing or reforming current policy on the
death penalty must include among its premises one
or more normative propositions.
10NORM AND NORMATIVE
- The term normative means of, relating to, or
determining norms or standards, and a norm is
a principle of right action binding upon the
members of a group and serving to guide, control,
or regulate proper and acceptable behavior.
(Both definitions from the tenth edition of
Merriam-Websters Collegiate Dictionary.) - And Simon Blackburn says that A norm is a rule
for behavior, or a definite pattern of behavior,
departure from which renders a person liable to
some kind of censure. (The Oxford Dictionary of
Philosophy.)
11NORMATIVE STATEMENTS AND THE DEATH PENALTY
- Bedau says that normative statements which
concern the death penalty can be divided into two
groups - 1. Those which focus on relevant and desirable
social goals or purposes. - 2. Those which express relevant and respectable
moral principles. - An example of a social goal is reduction of
crime, and the question here would be to what
extent does the death penalty meet the goal of
reducing crime? - An example of a respected moral principle is that
everyone should receive a fair trial.
12GOALS, PRINCIPLES, AND FACTS
- Bedau thinks that the way to argue about the
death penalty is to look at the social goals
relevant to punishment in general, and to look at
the moral principles which are relevant to
correct management of the social goals. - Once we have looked at the social goals which are
relevant to punishment in general and have
identified and evaluated the moral principles
relevant to punishment, then we can consider
whatever facts are relevant to the issue. - Thus Bedau says that the issue of the death
penalty can be resolved in theory by first
looking at what our social goals are, how these
should be constrained by our moral principles,
and then by looking at whatever facts are
relevant to the use of the death penalty as a
kind of punishment.
13PUNISHMENT AND RELEVANT SOCIAL GOALS I
- Goal 1 Punishment should contribute to the
reduction of crime accordingly, the punishment
for a crime should not be so idle a threat or so
slight a deprivation that it has no deterrent or
incapacitative effects and it should not
contribute to an increase in crime. - Goal 2 Punishments should be economical -
they should not waste valuable social resources
in futile or unnecessarily costly endeavors.
14CONSIDERATION OF THE FIRST TWO GOALS
- The goals of reducing crime and doing so cheaply
have been seen by many as arguments in favor of
the death penalty. - However, Bedau says that opponents of capital
punishment need not reject these goals, and its
defenders cannot argue that accepting these goals
vindicates their preferred policy. - Bedau thinks then that thinking that capital
punishment is the best means of reducing crime
and doing so in the cheapest way can be
questioned.
15THE JUSTIFICATION OF PUNISHMENT AS A MEANS TO AN
END
- The justification of a particular punishment,
such as capital punishment, as a means to an end
or ends, such as reducing crime and being
economical, must involve two steps - 1. It must be shown that an end or ends which a
punishment is a means of reaching is desirable.
For instance, if an end is a reduction in crime,
then it must be shown that a reduction in crime
is a good thing. - 2. It must be shown that punishment is the
best means to that end or ends. Thus it must be
shown that the end cannot be better achieved
without punishment, that there is no better means
of reducing crime apart from punishment. For the
death penalty, this would mean that it would have
to be shown that a reduction in the murder rate
cannot be achieved without capital punishment.
16PUNISHMENT AND RELEVANT SOCIAL GOALS II
- Goal 3 Punishment should rectify the harm and
injustice caused by crime. - Goal 4 Punishment should serve as a recognized
channel for the release of public indignation and
anger at the offender. - Goal 5 Punishment should make convicted
offenders into better persons rather than leave
them as they are or make them worse.
17CONSIDERATION OF THE LAST THREE GOALS I
- As Bedau says, if you accept goal 5 you must
object to the death penalty since you cannot
improve a person by killing him. - He also says that he will not try to argue
against the death penalty on this goal, and notes
that many who are in favor of the death penalty
will not be persuaded by it. - Bedau recognizes that one can object to the third
goal that it is not really a goal of punishment
to rectify an injustice.
18CONSIDERATION OF THE LAST THREE GOALS II
- The problem with rectifying the crime of murder,
either through imprisonment or through the death
penalty, is that there is no possible way to
rectify the crime of murder. The only way to
rectify murder would be to bring the victim back. - Because that is the case, Bedau says that it may
make the fourth goal of punishment being an
outlet for anger even more important.
19CONSIDERATION OF THE LAST THREE GOALS III
- In fact, Bedau recognizes that some people think
that this fourth goal of punishment is the best
argument for the death penalty. They think that
it is important because it is necessary to have a
punishment which can express the outrage that
citizens perhaps especially the family and
friends of the victim feel towards a murderer. - That is, punishment appropriate to the expression
of anger is necessary for a mentally healthy
society, and the death penalty is the best means
of expressing that anger.
20POSSIBLE RESPONSES TO GOAL 4 AS A DEFENSE OF
CAPITAL PUNISHMENT I
- How might we respond to the fourth goal as an
argument for the death penalty - that it provides
for the release of public anger directed to the
murderer? - Bedau mentions three possible responses
- 1. Reject as false the view that the death
penalty provides for the release of public anger,
and is necessary for the mental health of a just
society. - 2. Concede that the death penalty does function
as a means of dealing with public anger, but
argue that it is only justified in a small number
of cases, such as for the likes of Timothy
McVeigh.
21POSSIBLE RESPONSES TO GOAL 4 AS A DEFENSE OF
CAPITAL PUNISHMENT II
- 3. Concede that it is legitimate and important
to have some form of punishment which is an
outlet for public anger directed towards a
murderer, but that the death penalty is not the
right punishment since it is ruled out on grounds
of morality. - For Bedau, both the second and third responses
are sound.
22ANGER I
- For Bedau, simple anger at the crime of murder is
not enough by itself to justify the death penalty
in any case. - We need to know more details about the particular
crime including the context in which it occurred
and what caused it. - Bedau says that we rarely know enough about the
particulars in a crime to know whether to know to
what extent our anger is justified, and whether
we are justified in putting the person to death.
23ANGER II
- Bedau thinks that it is curious that those who
argue for the death penalty on the basis that it
is needed as an outlet for public outrage
nevertheless reject some forms of execution which
are true expressions of hatred and anger at
murderers. - We no longer behead, crucify, torture, or
dismember murderers, and the preferred method of
execution now is lethal injection, which Bedau
says seems too calm a form of execution to be an
expression of outrage at the crime.
24CONSEQUENCES, DUTY, AND PUNISHMENT
- Bedau If the purposes or goals of punishment
lend a utilitarian quality to the practice of
punishment, the moral principles relevant to the
death penalty operate as deontological
constraints on their pursuit. - Thus, the purposes or goals of punishment are to
be valued in terms of the positive consequences
which their implementation has for society, but
kinds of punishment utilized are constrained by
moral principles which we have a duty to
recognize.
25MORAL PRINCIPLES RELEVANT TO THE DEATH PENALTY I
- Principle 1 No one should deliberately and
intentionally take anothers life where there is
a feasible alternative. - (How does this pertain to the issue of
euthanasia? Should other language be added here
to make this first principle relevant to that
issue?) - Principle 2 The more severe a penalty is, the
more important it is that it be imposed only on
those who truly deserve it. - Principle 3 The more severe a penalty is, the
weightier the justification required to warrant
its imposition on anyone.
26MORAL PRINCIPLES RELEVANT TO THE DEATH PENALTY II
- Principle 4 Whatever the criminal offense, the
accused and convicted offender does not forfeit
all his rights and dignity as a person.
Accordingly, there is an upper limit to the
severity - cruelty, destructiveness, finality -
of permissible punishments, regardless of the
offense. - Principle 5 Fairness requires that punishments
should be graded in their severity according to
the gravity of the offense. - Principle 6 If human lives are to be risked,
the risk should fall more heavily on wrong-doers
(the guilty) than on others (the innocent).
27MORAL PRINCIPLES RELEVANT TO THE DEATH PENALTY III
- Bedau says that these principles are either
implicitly or explicitly recognized by society in
practice. - And these principles put limits on what we can
and cannot do to someone who has committed a
crime. - Bedau says that these principles are corollaries
or theorems of the general proposition that life,
limb, and security of person - of all persons -
are of paramount value. - Because of this general principle, it follows
that we can only interfere in the life of another
to the extent to which this is necessary to
protect the rights of others. - This is why principle 5 outlaws torture - only
minimal interference in the life of another, even
a criminal, is morally permissible.
28MORAL PRINCIPLES RELEVANT TO THE DEATH PENALTY IV
- Bedau recognizes that none of these principles
rules out the death penalty. - In fact, he says that he knows of no moral
principle which by itself would rule out the
death penalty - Even so, these principles do place a heavy burden
on anyone who advocates the death penalty to show
that it is necessary when locking up a criminal
will just as well protect society. - Imprisoning someone for life is less intrusive
then, and is more in conformity with the
principles, than capital punishment.
29MORAL PRINCIPLES RELEVANT TO THE DEATH PENALTY V
- Perhaps the principle which would seem to argue
most favorably for the death penalty is number 5
that the punishment should fit the crime. Thus,
if murder is the worst crime, which it is, then
it should have the severest penalty. - But even so, Bedau says that it does not follow
from this that the punishment has to be death.
The severest punishment could be life without
parole.
30LEX TALIONIS
- It does not follow, Bedau says, unless you accept
lex talionis - an eye for an eye, a tooth for a
tooth, a life for a life - that the punishment
should be the same as the crime, so that if a
person kills he should be killed. - But Bedau says that lex talionis is not a sound
principle on which to base punishment in general. - He does not say why, but the reason is that not
all crimes can be repaid with the same kind of
punishment - child abuse and rape for instance.
31PRINCIPLE SIX I
- Bedau says that the principle of greater interest
is number 6 - that if humans lives are to be
risked, better to risk the lives of the guilty
than the innocent - which is what van den Haag
will say. - The idea is that it is better to execute all
murderers so that none of them can kill again
than it is to execute none of them so that we
avoid the risk of executing an innocent person.
32PRINCIPLE SIX II
- For van den Haag, if we do not have capital
punishment then there is a risk to innocent
people that a convicted murderer released from
prison may kill again, and if we do have capital
punishment, the risk is that an innocent person
may be put to death. - But for van den Haag it is clear that it is
better to place the risk of the killing of the
innocent on the lives of convicted felons than it
is to place the risk of being killed on the
innocent population.
33PRINCIPLE SIX III
- Bedau says that this argument is not as
conclusive as it may seem, and it is not enough
to outweigh other arguments against the death
penalty. - And he says that it is really a disguised version
of the first policy goal of punishment which is
that it should reduce crime. - Thus this principle argues that reducing crime is
more important than anything else. - Bedau also objects that we cannot really compare
the two risks discussed - the risk that an
innocent person will be executed as opposed to
the risk to the innocent given no death penalty.
34BEDAUS CONCLUSIONS ABOUT THE DEATH PENALTY
- 1. The death penalty is primarily a means to one
or more goals, but is probably not the best means
of reaching those goals. - 2. Several principles favor abolition of the
death penalty. - 3. However, there is no conclusive argument
either for or against the death penalty. (An
argument which seems conclusive to one side, such
as lex talionis, the other side does not have to
accept.) - 4. The goals and principles which Bedau has
looked at have no obvious rank or relative
weighting - it is hard to say which are more
important than others.
35GOVERNMENT POWER
- Bedaus first argument against the death penalty
is that the power which the government has over
the lives of individuals should be decreased and
not increased. - Of course, some government power is necessary to
have a civil society, but the governments power
should be constructive not destructive. - A governments power should enhance liberty not
decrease it. - The governments use of the death penalty is a
destructive not a constructive use of power. - For Bedau, it is the ultimate symbol of
government power.
36PAST AND FUTURE I
- Bedaus second argument against the death penalty
is that the goals and principles of punishment
should be directed towards the future, not the
past. - We cannot do anything to benefit the dead
victims of crime. This is the idea that reality
is such that some problems may have no solutions,
at least not the kind we would wish. - As Bedau himself wonders how many people would
be opposed to the death penalty if executing a
murderer would bring back his victim? Would we
not owe it to the victim?
37PAST AND FUTURE II
- The point of looking to the future is that we can
try to do something for the living in the time
ahead of them even if we cannot go back to the
past to help the victim. - What we do is try to protect the innocent, try to
console those affected by crime, and try to
prevent future crimes. - And Bedau thinks that none of these
future-directed constructive goals demands
capital punishment. - For Bedau the death penalty, in being vindictive
and retributive and expressing our outrage at the
murder of an innocent person, are all directed
towards the past.
38FALSE PICTURES
- Bedaus third argument against the death penalty
is that the death penalty gives a false picture
of man and society. - Bedau Far from being a symbol of justice it is
a symbol of brutality and stupidity. - Bedau thinks that the common conception of the
criminal is as an autonomous Kantian moral agent
who freely and knowingly acts deliberately to
kill another. - But Bedau says that the killers actually on death
row do not resemble Kants rational moral agents.
39CONCLUSION
- For Bedau, the death penalty question concerns
how controversial social goals, controversial
moral principles, and disputed general facts are
to be balanced and reasonably assessed. - Bedau thinks that deeper rational argument can
decide the matter against the death penalty, but
in this paper he has only attempted to sort out
what the difficulties are.
40The Ultimate Punishment a Defense
Ernest van den Haag
41PRELIMINARY CONSIDERATIONS
- van den Haag notes that, on average, there are
about 20,000 homicides a year in the U. S., but
fewer than 300 convicted murderers are sentenced
to death - about 1.5.. Accordingly, most
convicts sentenced to death are likely to die of
old age. - It is interesting to note here that van den Haag
finds death row as a semipermanent or permanent
if they are never executed residence to be
cruel, because convicts are denied the amenities
of normal prison life, such as contact with
other prisoners. (Cf. Kant.) - Even though the execution rate is so small, van
den Haag says that the death penalty raises
important moral questions independent of the
number of executions.
42DISCRIMINATION AND CAPRICIOUS DISTRIBUTION I
- van den Haag notes that some people object to the
death penalty because it is not evenly applied. - This can be for reason of discrimination, where
minority murderers may be more likely to be
sentenced to death and executed than murderers
who form part of the majority population, or for
reason of caprice, as when one person is executed
and another not for no predictable or clearly
understandable reason. - In addition, money may make a difference, so that
of two equally guilty people one is executed and
another not based on the affordable quality of
his or her legal defense.
43DISCRIMINATION AND CAPRICIOUS DISTRIBUTION II
- However, van den Haag says that how the death
penalty is in fact applied - whether or not it is
evenly and so fairly applied - is irrelevant to
the morality of the punishment. - The death penalty is either moral or immoral in
itself. - You cannot make it moral if it is immoral by
applying it equally, and you cannot make it
immoral if it is moral by only applying it to
some convicted murderers and not to others, for
whatever reason or reasons. (Its uneven
application would be a separate moral issue.)
44DISCRIMINATION AND CAPRICIOUS DISTRIBUTION III
- Further, in being applied unevenly, the death
penalty is the same as every other punishment, in
that every punishment is also unevenly applied. - And van den Haag says that Maldistribution of
any punishment among those who deserve it is
irrelevant to its justice or morality. - The only relevant question for van den Haag
concerning the death penalty is does the
convicted murderer deserve to be executed?
45DISCRIMINATION AND CAPRICIOUS DISTRIBUTION IV
- If the death penalty is morally justified for
convicted murderers, then it does not matter to
the morality of the punishment whether one
murderer gets executed and another does not. - van den Haag Even if poor or black convicts
guilty of capital offenses suffer capital
punishment, and other convicts equally guilty of
the same crimes do not, a more equal
distribution, however desirable, would merely be
more equal. It would not be more just to the
convicts under the sentence of death.
46DISCRIMINATION AND CAPRICIOUS DISTRIBUTION V
- Even if a guilty person is not executed, he still
deserves to be executed if capital punishment is
morally justified. - van den Haags way of putting this is to say that
equality is less important morally than justice. - And he says that Punishments are imposed on
persons, not on racial or economic groups. Guilt
is personal. The only relevant question is does
the person to be executed deserve the
punishment?
47DISCRIMINATION AND CAPRICIOUS DISTRIBUTION VI
- According to van den Haag, what is a just
punishment for an offense is just no matter
whether it is evenly or unevenly distributed
amongst the guilty. - van den Haag Whether or not others who deserve
the same punishment, whatever their economic or
racial group, have avoided execution is
irrelevant. - van den Haag Justice requires that as many of
the guilty as possible be punished, regardless of
whether others have avoided punishment.
48DISCRIMINATION AND CAPRICIOUS DISTRIBUTION VII
- For van den Haag, it is not just to let people
escape punishment who deserve to be punished, but
that does not make punishment unjust for those
who are punished. - And van den Haag notes that some inequality of
punishment is unavoidable in any legal system as
a practical matter. People are not perfect, and
so their legal and penal systems are not going to
be perfect either. - But, for van den Haag, unequal justice is better
than injustice, and injustice is what we have
when anyone escapes punishment which he deserves.
49RISK TO THE INNOCENT I
- van den Haag says that there seems little doubt
that innocent people have been executed, and that
such people will also be unjustly executed in the
future. - But he says that nearly all human activities, and
not just punishment, carry some risk to the
innocent. In this sense then punishment,
including capital punishment, is not unusual. - Innocent people can be killed in driving
accidents or from construction, for instance, but
we do not give these things up because we think
that the benefits of travel and construction
outweigh the risks to the innocent.
50RISK TO THE INNOCENT II
- Analogously, van den Haag says that the
occasional execution of an innocent person is
outweighed by the benefits to society of the
death penalty. - The chief benefit of the death penalty to
society, for van den Haag, is its justness or its
morality. - This is because, for van den Haag, the death
penalty is the only appropriate punishment for
the crime of murder, and not to punish murderers
by executing them would be unjust, and so not a
benefit to society.
51RISK TO THE INNOCENT III
- van den Haag also maintains that, for people who
think that the death penalty is immoral in any
case - whether evenly applied or not, or whether
or not an innocent person is executed - the
occasional miscarriage of justice which happens
from executing an innocent person can hardly be
the decisive reason for finding it immoral.
52DETERRENCE I
- van den Haag admits that there is no conclusive
evidence that the death penalty is a better
deterrent to crime than other kinds of
punishment. - However, he does not think that the issue of
deterrence argues either for or against the death
penalty. - He thinks that those people who are opposed to
the death penalty would be opposed to it even if
it were shown to be a better deterrent than some
other form of punishment, say life in prison
without parole.
53DETERRENCE II
- van den Haag says that opponents of the death
penalty appear to value the life of a convicted
murder or, at least, his non-execution, more
highly than they value the lives of the innocent
victims who might be spared by using the death
penalty to deter prospective murderers. - van den Haag also says that he would still favor
the death penalty for murder even if it were
shown that capital punishment is not a better
deterrent than other forms of punishment, and
would only favor its abolition if evidence showed
that executions increased rather than decreased
the murder rate by functioning as a deterrent. - But van den Haag does think that the threat of
capital punishment is a better deterrent to crime
than other forms of punishment because of its
finality.
54DETERRENCE III
- van den Haag thinks that saving the lives of
innocent people by using the threat of capital
punishment is more important than preserving the
lives of convicted murderers by thinking that the
death penalty is not a deterrent. - For van den Haag, the important point is that the
lives of innocent people are valuable, whereas
the lives of convicted murderers are not due to
their crimes. - van den Haag says that it is the purpose of the
law to protect the innocent, not the guilty.
55DETERRENCE IV
- van den Haag recognizes that murder rates are
determined by many factors, and recognizes that
we cannot be sure that by threatening execution
for a convicted murderer that the murder rate
will thereby be lower than it would if we did not
have that form of threatened punishment. - Even so he maintains that the threat of execution
does deter at least some people from murdering
others, and this deterrence is an argument in
favor of the death penalty in addition to his
fundamental argument that there is no justice for
the crime of murder without it.
56DETERRENCE V
- Thus whether it is a deterrent or not, van den
Haag says that The severity and finality of the
death penalty is appropriate to the seriousness
and finality of murder. And this
appropriateness is moral appropriateness.
57COST
- Some people object to the death penalty because
they maintain that it is more expensive than life
imprisonment. This is because of the legal costs
which must be born by the state in the lengthy
appeals process. - van den Haag says that this argument is flawed
by the implied assumption that life prisoners
will generate no judicial costs during their
imprisonment. - This cannot be assumed, and so the issue of
expense can be questioned, but even if the cost
of pursuing the death penalty is more expensive
than life imprisonment, still the death penalty
is justified on grounds of justice.
58SUFFERING I
- Some people object to the death penalty on the
grounds that it makes the murderer on death row
suffer more than his victim did - for instance,
isolation and anxiety from anticipating execution
- and no punishment ought to inflict more
suffering on the criminal than the victim. - This view is related to lex talionis, or the law
of retaliation which says that the punishment
should fit the crime. According to this
principle, what the criminal took from his victim
society should take from the criminal. In the
case of murder this would be a life for a life.
And it would follow from considering suffering as
just punishment in relation to lex talionis that
the criminal should suffer at least as much as
his victim, but not more than his victim.
59SUFFERING II
- van den Haags first response to this objection
to the excessive suffering caused by capital
punishment is that we cannot really know if the
murderer suffers more than the victim. - However, whether he does or not is irrelevant
since, for van den Haag, the crucial point here
is that the victim did not deserve to suffer
whatever she suffered. - van den Haags second response is that the
limitations of the lex talionis were meant to
restrain private vengeance, not the social
retribution which has taken its place.
60SUFFERING III
- van den Haag Punishment - regardless of the
motivation - is not intended to revenge, offset,
or compensate for the victims suffering, or to
be measured by it. - van den Haag Punishment is to vindicate the law
and the social order undermined by the crime. - van den Haag This is why a kidnappers penal
confinement is not limited to the period for
which he imprisoned his victim not is a
burglars confinement meant merely to offset the
suffering or harm he caused his victim nor is it
meant only to offset the advantage he gained.
61THE LEGITIMIZATION OF UNLAWFUL KILLING I
- van den Haag Another argument, heard at least
since Beccaria is that, by killing a murderer, we
encourage, endorse, or legitimize unlawful
killing. - Yet van den Haag says that although all
punishments are meant to be unpleasant, it is
seldom argued that they legitimize the unlawful
imposition of identical unpleasantness. For
instance, imprisonment is not thought to
legitimize kidnapping.
62THE LEGITIMIZATION OF UNLAWFUL KILLING II
- For van den Haag, The difference between murder
and execution is that the first is unlawful and
undeserved, the second a lawful and deserved
punishment for an unlawful act. - van den Haag The physical similarities of the
punishment to the crime are irrelevant. The
relevant difference is not physical, but social.
63WHY DOES SOCIETY PUNISH?
- van den Haag notes that society threatens
punishment in order to deter crime, and society
imposes punishment in order to make the threats
credible. Thus the threat of punishment for a
crime committed is of no use unless the
punishment is enforced. - van den Haag says that both the threat of
punishment and actual punishment are necessary to
deter crime. And the fact that they function as
deterrents is sufficient practical justification
for them. - Societies also punish as retribution for the
crimes actually committed. And this retribution
is an independent moral justification.
64THE JUSTIFICATION OF PUNISHMENT
- van den Haag says that An explicit threat of
punitive action is necessary to the justification
of any legal punishment. Thus, a punishment is
not just if there is no prior law which threatens
the punishment as a consequence for committing a
particular crime. - But van den Haag notes that a prior law
legitimizes the threatened punishment only if
the threat is warranted. To that end, To be
sufficiently justified, the threat of
punishment must have a rational and legitimate
purpose. - Thus, van den Haag says that Your money or your
life does not qualify nor does the threat of an
unjust law nor, finally, does a threat that is
altogether disproportionate to the importance of
its purpose.
65JUST PUNISHMENT OF CRIMINAL ACTION I
- For van den Haag, punishment is not only
practically justified but it is morally
justified, and is so justified independently of
its practical justification. - That punishment is morally justified means that
the infliction of legal punishment on a guilty
person cannot be unjust. - It cannot be unjust because when a criminal
commits a crime he volunteers to assume the risk
of being punished for the crime which he commits.
66JUST PUNISHMENT OF CRIMINAL ACTION II
- Because the punishment which a criminal receives
is the one which he risked suffering, it is not
unjust. - In the case of the death penalty, since a
murderer voluntarily risks the death penalty in
deliberately killing an innocent person, the
punishment of death for him is not unjust. - Further, there is a disparity of volunteering to
risk something here between criminal and victim
since, whereas the criminal voluntarily risks
being punished in committing his crime, his
victim volunteered to risk nothing.
67JUST PUNISHMENT OF CRIMINAL ACTION III
- For van den Haag, because
- A) a murderer voluntarily risks execution in
murdering - B) his victim did not voluntarily risked being
killed and - C) because we have the advance threat of
execution for murder, - It follows that capital punishment is just.
68IS THE DEATH PENALTY EXCESSIVE?
- However, van den Haag recognizes that, although
capital punishment cannot be unjust in this
sense, still people might object that it is
overly punitive and is morally degrading. - To view the death penalty as overly punitive one
would think that no crime, not even first degree
murder, warranted this punishment. - And here van den Haag says that Such a belief
can be neither corroborated nor refuted it is an
article of faith. - van den Haag thinks that the murderer does not
have the same right to life which everyone else
has. Rather, he forfeits his right to life
because of his crime. Not only is it not
excessive, but it is the only just punishment for
the crime of murder.
69IS THE DEATH PENALTY MORALLY DEGRADING? I
- Some objectors to the death penalty might argue
that it is immoral because everybody, the
murderer no less than the victim, has an
imprescriptible (natural?) right to life. - (An imprescriptible right is one that cannot in
any circumstances be taken away or abandoned.
Thus if there is an imprescriptible right to life
then the murderer has it as much as his or her
victim and so cannot for this reason be
executed.) - van den Haag says that he agrees here with
Jeremy Benthams view that any such natural and
imprescriptible rights are nonsense upon
stilts.
70IS THE DEATH PENALTY MORALLY DEGRADING? II
- Further, van den Haag cites both Kant and Hegel
who thought that, far from degrading the
executed convict, the death penalty affirms his
humanity by affirming his rationality and his
responsibility for his actions. - This of course assumes that all adults, including
murderers, are rational, and do not act
irrationally when killing, and it assumes that
they are capable of taking responsibility for
their actions. - We have already seen that Bedau does not think
that the average person on death row much
resembles a Kantian rational moral agent, and so
would find van den Haags argument here
unconvincing.
71IS THE DEATH PENALTY MORALLY DEGRADING? III
- Both Kant and Hegel thought that execution is
required to preserve the convicted murderers
dignity as a rational moral agent. - As van den Haag puts it They thought that
execution, when deserved, is required for the
sake of the convicts dignity. (Does not life
imprisonment violate human dignity more than
execution, by keeping alive a prisoner deprived
of all ? autonomy?)
72IS THE DEATH PENALTY MORALLY DEGRADING? IV
- One might question the use of the term all in
the preceding quote since in fact it is death
which deprives a person of all autonomy. The
incarcerated individual still has some autonomy -
freedom of thought for instance. - If the person did not have this freedom of
thought then he could not be protected by some
human rights theories which say that convicted
killers should not be executed because they still
have the right - fundamental to all persons - to
dialogue, to be a partner in the search for
truth.
73DEATH AND THE DEATH PENALTY
- van den Haag thinks that common sense does not
see normal death as inhuman. This is because
death is an essential part of our humanity. - Therefore, those, such as Justice Brennan, who
see the death penalty as morally degrading must
see death as inhuman when it is neither natural
nor accidental. - van den Haag says that capital punishment tells
the convicted killer that he is not fit to be a
member of society, that his fellow humans have
found him unworthy of living. - Because of his crime, the murderer is being
expelled from the realm of the living.
74THE SELF-DEGRADATION OF MURDER
- In deliberately murdering, the killer degrades
himself as a person, and the death penalty is
simply societys recognition of his
self-degradation. - For van den Haag, the essence of capital
punishment is societys recognition that the
killer has degraded himself by killing. - To believe that it is the execution which
degrades the criminal rather than the act of
murder is to get things the wrong way around. - For van den Haag, capital punishment is the only
punishment which fits the crime of murder.
75SHOULD EXECUTIONS BE TELEVISED? I
- No, according to van den Haag, and this is the
case even if, by televising, it might be thought
to be a greater deterrent than it is without
making the execution public. - The reasons, according to van den Haag, are
- 1. The death of even a murderer, however
well-deserved, should not serve as public
entertainment. - 2. Television would unavoidably trivialize
executions. This is because they would appear
between game shows, situation comedies, and the
like.
76SHOULD EXECUTIONS BE TELEVISED? II
- 3. A televised execution would present the
murderer as the victim of the state. This is
because televised executions would focus on the
physical aspects of the punishment, rather than
the nature of the crime and the suffering of the
victim. As a result, the moral significance of
the execution would not be communicated to the
audience. Rather television would shift the
focus to the pitiable fear of the murderer.