THE ETHICS OF CAPITAL PUNISHMENT - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 76
About This Presentation
Title:

THE ETHICS OF CAPITAL PUNISHMENT

Description:

2. Is the death penalty applied in a discriminatory way? ... The death penalty is not the only form of punishment in which discrimination ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:986
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 77
Provided by: JeffSt6
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: THE ETHICS OF CAPITAL PUNISHMENT


1
THE ETHICS OF CAPITAL PUNISHMENT
Electric Chair, Andy Warhol, 1971
2
How to Argue About the Death Penalty
Hugo Adam Bedau
3
FACTUAL ISSUES
  • Bedau begins his paper by noting that the death
    penalty controversy in the U. S. has largely
    considered certain questions of fact, and has not
    really concentrated on the normative
    propositions crucial to the dispute which are of
    greater importance.
  • The questions of fact are four
  • 1. Is the death penalty a greater deterrent to
    murder than life imprisonment without parole?
  • 2. Is the death penalty applied in a
    discriminatory way?
  • 3. What is the risk that an innocent person
    will be executed?
  • 4. What is the risk that a convicted murderer
    who is not executed will kill again in or out of
    jail, if not given life without parole ?

4
ANSWERS TO THE FACTUAL QUESTIONS
  • For Bedau the answers to these four questions
    are
  • 1. There is no evidence that the death penalty
    is a better deterrent to murder than life in
    prison. Both life in prison and execution seem
    about equally ineffective.
  • 2. There is good evidence that the death
    penalty is not applied to everyone equally but
    race makes a difference.
  • 3. The risk to an innocent person cannot be
    calculated but the risk is not zero.
  • 4. There is recidivism amongst murders, and so
    there is that risk that they will kill again.

5
THE ETHICAL RELEVANCE OF FACTS I
  • Bedau says that the important thing to see here
    is that the answers to the questions cannot by
    themselves answer the question of the morality of
    the death penalty.
  • Even though Bedau thinks that the death penalty
    should be abolished, he says that the facts as
    they stand cannot show that the death penalty
    ought to be eliminated.
  • The facts also do not show that life imprisonment
    is better than the death penalty.

6
THE ETHICAL RELEVANCE OF FACTS II
  • The death penalty is not the only form of
    punishment in which discrimination occurs, but
    discrimination is found in other kinds of
    punishment as well.
  • In addition, and as far as the facts are
    concerned, it can always be argued that such
    discrimination will decrease over time, and, if
    that were the case then one could not use the
    former fact of discrimination as an argument
    against the morality of the death penalty.

7
THE ETHICAL RELEVANCE OF FACTS III
  • Bedau says that the important point when we
    consider facts which concern the death penalty is
    that the empirical evidence is not the major
    factor in explaining why settling disputes over
    matters of fact cannot settle the larger
    controversy about the death penalty itself.
  • Rather, the larger controversy concerns the
    morality of the death penalty. That is, whether
    the death penalty should be legal or not is a
    moral question which cannot be argued from facts.

8
THE ETHICAL RELEVANCE OF FACTS IV
  • Arguments in favor of or in opposition to the
    death penalty will have to be moral arguments.
    They will have to be normative and not just
    practical.
  • That is, we have to look at what standard to
    adopt, and not what uses or abuses may follow
    from the adoption of that standard.

9
THE ETHICAL RELEVANCE OF FACTS V
  • Bedau As a matter of sheer logic, it is not
    possible to deduce a policy conclusion (such as
    the desirability of abolishing the death penalty)
    from any set of factual premises, however general
    and well supported.
  • Bedau Any argument intended to recommend
    continuing or reforming current policy on the
    death penalty must include among its premises one
    or more normative propositions.

10
NORM AND NORMATIVE
  • The term normative means of, relating to, or
    determining norms or standards, and a norm is
    a principle of right action binding upon the
    members of a group and serving to guide, control,
    or regulate proper and acceptable behavior.
    (Both definitions from the tenth edition of
    Merriam-Websters Collegiate Dictionary.)
  • And Simon Blackburn says that A norm is a rule
    for behavior, or a definite pattern of behavior,
    departure from which renders a person liable to
    some kind of censure. (The Oxford Dictionary of
    Philosophy.)

11
NORMATIVE STATEMENTS AND THE DEATH PENALTY
  • Bedau says that normative statements which
    concern the death penalty can be divided into two
    groups
  • 1. Those which focus on relevant and desirable
    social goals or purposes.
  • 2. Those which express relevant and respectable
    moral principles.
  • An example of a social goal is reduction of
    crime, and the question here would be to what
    extent does the death penalty meet the goal of
    reducing crime?
  • An example of a respected moral principle is that
    everyone should receive a fair trial.

12
GOALS, PRINCIPLES, AND FACTS
  • Bedau thinks that the way to argue about the
    death penalty is to look at the social goals
    relevant to punishment in general, and to look at
    the moral principles which are relevant to
    correct management of the social goals.
  • Once we have looked at the social goals which are
    relevant to punishment in general and have
    identified and evaluated the moral principles
    relevant to punishment, then we can consider
    whatever facts are relevant to the issue.
  • Thus Bedau says that the issue of the death
    penalty can be resolved in theory by first
    looking at what our social goals are, how these
    should be constrained by our moral principles,
    and then by looking at whatever facts are
    relevant to the use of the death penalty as a
    kind of punishment.

13
PUNISHMENT AND RELEVANT SOCIAL GOALS I
  • Goal 1 Punishment should contribute to the
    reduction of crime accordingly, the punishment
    for a crime should not be so idle a threat or so
    slight a deprivation that it has no deterrent or
    incapacitative effects and it should not
    contribute to an increase in crime.
  • Goal 2 Punishments should be economical -
    they should not waste valuable social resources
    in futile or unnecessarily costly endeavors.

14
CONSIDERATION OF THE FIRST TWO GOALS
  • The goals of reducing crime and doing so cheaply
    have been seen by many as arguments in favor of
    the death penalty.
  • However, Bedau says that opponents of capital
    punishment need not reject these goals, and its
    defenders cannot argue that accepting these goals
    vindicates their preferred policy.
  • Bedau thinks then that thinking that capital
    punishment is the best means of reducing crime
    and doing so in the cheapest way can be
    questioned.

15
THE JUSTIFICATION OF PUNISHMENT AS A MEANS TO AN
END
  • The justification of a particular punishment,
    such as capital punishment, as a means to an end
    or ends, such as reducing crime and being
    economical, must involve two steps
  • 1. It must be shown that an end or ends which a
    punishment is a means of reaching is desirable.
    For instance, if an end is a reduction in crime,
    then it must be shown that a reduction in crime
    is a good thing.
  • 2. It must be shown that punishment is the
    best means to that end or ends. Thus it must be
    shown that the end cannot be better achieved
    without punishment, that there is no better means
    of reducing crime apart from punishment. For the
    death penalty, this would mean that it would have
    to be shown that a reduction in the murder rate
    cannot be achieved without capital punishment.

16
PUNISHMENT AND RELEVANT SOCIAL GOALS II
  • Goal 3 Punishment should rectify the harm and
    injustice caused by crime.
  • Goal 4 Punishment should serve as a recognized
    channel for the release of public indignation and
    anger at the offender.
  • Goal 5 Punishment should make convicted
    offenders into better persons rather than leave
    them as they are or make them worse.

17
CONSIDERATION OF THE LAST THREE GOALS I
  • As Bedau says, if you accept goal 5 you must
    object to the death penalty since you cannot
    improve a person by killing him.
  • He also says that he will not try to argue
    against the death penalty on this goal, and notes
    that many who are in favor of the death penalty
    will not be persuaded by it.
  • Bedau recognizes that one can object to the third
    goal that it is not really a goal of punishment
    to rectify an injustice.

18
CONSIDERATION OF THE LAST THREE GOALS II
  • The problem with rectifying the crime of murder,
    either through imprisonment or through the death
    penalty, is that there is no possible way to
    rectify the crime of murder. The only way to
    rectify murder would be to bring the victim back.
  • Because that is the case, Bedau says that it may
    make the fourth goal of punishment being an
    outlet for anger even more important.

19
CONSIDERATION OF THE LAST THREE GOALS III
  • In fact, Bedau recognizes that some people think
    that this fourth goal of punishment is the best
    argument for the death penalty. They think that
    it is important because it is necessary to have a
    punishment which can express the outrage that
    citizens perhaps especially the family and
    friends of the victim feel towards a murderer.
  • That is, punishment appropriate to the expression
    of anger is necessary for a mentally healthy
    society, and the death penalty is the best means
    of expressing that anger.

20
POSSIBLE RESPONSES TO GOAL 4 AS A DEFENSE OF
CAPITAL PUNISHMENT I
  • How might we respond to the fourth goal as an
    argument for the death penalty - that it provides
    for the release of public anger directed to the
    murderer?
  • Bedau mentions three possible responses
  • 1. Reject as false the view that the death
    penalty provides for the release of public anger,
    and is necessary for the mental health of a just
    society.
  • 2. Concede that the death penalty does function
    as a means of dealing with public anger, but
    argue that it is only justified in a small number
    of cases, such as for the likes of Timothy
    McVeigh.

21
POSSIBLE RESPONSES TO GOAL 4 AS A DEFENSE OF
CAPITAL PUNISHMENT II
  • 3. Concede that it is legitimate and important
    to have some form of punishment which is an
    outlet for public anger directed towards a
    murderer, but that the death penalty is not the
    right punishment since it is ruled out on grounds
    of morality.
  • For Bedau, both the second and third responses
    are sound.

22
ANGER I
  • For Bedau, simple anger at the crime of murder is
    not enough by itself to justify the death penalty
    in any case.
  • We need to know more details about the particular
    crime including the context in which it occurred
    and what caused it.
  • Bedau says that we rarely know enough about the
    particulars in a crime to know whether to know to
    what extent our anger is justified, and whether
    we are justified in putting the person to death.

23
ANGER II
  • Bedau thinks that it is curious that those who
    argue for the death penalty on the basis that it
    is needed as an outlet for public outrage
    nevertheless reject some forms of execution which
    are true expressions of hatred and anger at
    murderers.
  • We no longer behead, crucify, torture, or
    dismember murderers, and the preferred method of
    execution now is lethal injection, which Bedau
    says seems too calm a form of execution to be an
    expression of outrage at the crime.

24
CONSEQUENCES, DUTY, AND PUNISHMENT
  • Bedau If the purposes or goals of punishment
    lend a utilitarian quality to the practice of
    punishment, the moral principles relevant to the
    death penalty operate as deontological
    constraints on their pursuit.
  • Thus, the purposes or goals of punishment are to
    be valued in terms of the positive consequences
    which their implementation has for society, but
    kinds of punishment utilized are constrained by
    moral principles which we have a duty to
    recognize.

25
MORAL PRINCIPLES RELEVANT TO THE DEATH PENALTY I
  • Principle 1 No one should deliberately and
    intentionally take anothers life where there is
    a feasible alternative.
  • (How does this pertain to the issue of
    euthanasia? Should other language be added here
    to make this first principle relevant to that
    issue?)
  • Principle 2 The more severe a penalty is, the
    more important it is that it be imposed only on
    those who truly deserve it.
  • Principle 3 The more severe a penalty is, the
    weightier the justification required to warrant
    its imposition on anyone.

26
MORAL PRINCIPLES RELEVANT TO THE DEATH PENALTY II
  • Principle 4 Whatever the criminal offense, the
    accused and convicted offender does not forfeit
    all his rights and dignity as a person.
    Accordingly, there is an upper limit to the
    severity - cruelty, destructiveness, finality -
    of permissible punishments, regardless of the
    offense.
  • Principle 5 Fairness requires that punishments
    should be graded in their severity according to
    the gravity of the offense.
  • Principle 6 If human lives are to be risked,
    the risk should fall more heavily on wrong-doers
    (the guilty) than on others (the innocent).

27
MORAL PRINCIPLES RELEVANT TO THE DEATH PENALTY III
  • Bedau says that these principles are either
    implicitly or explicitly recognized by society in
    practice.
  • And these principles put limits on what we can
    and cannot do to someone who has committed a
    crime.
  • Bedau says that these principles are corollaries
    or theorems of the general proposition that life,
    limb, and security of person - of all persons -
    are of paramount value.
  • Because of this general principle, it follows
    that we can only interfere in the life of another
    to the extent to which this is necessary to
    protect the rights of others.
  • This is why principle 5 outlaws torture - only
    minimal interference in the life of another, even
    a criminal, is morally permissible.

28
MORAL PRINCIPLES RELEVANT TO THE DEATH PENALTY IV
  • Bedau recognizes that none of these principles
    rules out the death penalty.
  • In fact, he says that he knows of no moral
    principle which by itself would rule out the
    death penalty
  • Even so, these principles do place a heavy burden
    on anyone who advocates the death penalty to show
    that it is necessary when locking up a criminal
    will just as well protect society.
  • Imprisoning someone for life is less intrusive
    then, and is more in conformity with the
    principles, than capital punishment.

29
MORAL PRINCIPLES RELEVANT TO THE DEATH PENALTY V
  • Perhaps the principle which would seem to argue
    most favorably for the death penalty is number 5
    that the punishment should fit the crime. Thus,
    if murder is the worst crime, which it is, then
    it should have the severest penalty.
  • But even so, Bedau says that it does not follow
    from this that the punishment has to be death.
    The severest punishment could be life without
    parole.

30
LEX TALIONIS
  • It does not follow, Bedau says, unless you accept
    lex talionis - an eye for an eye, a tooth for a
    tooth, a life for a life - that the punishment
    should be the same as the crime, so that if a
    person kills he should be killed.
  • But Bedau says that lex talionis is not a sound
    principle on which to base punishment in general.
  • He does not say why, but the reason is that not
    all crimes can be repaid with the same kind of
    punishment - child abuse and rape for instance.

31
PRINCIPLE SIX I
  • Bedau says that the principle of greater interest
    is number 6 - that if humans lives are to be
    risked, better to risk the lives of the guilty
    than the innocent - which is what van den Haag
    will say.
  • The idea is that it is better to execute all
    murderers so that none of them can kill again
    than it is to execute none of them so that we
    avoid the risk of executing an innocent person.

32
PRINCIPLE SIX II
  • For van den Haag, if we do not have capital
    punishment then there is a risk to innocent
    people that a convicted murderer released from
    prison may kill again, and if we do have capital
    punishment, the risk is that an innocent person
    may be put to death.
  • But for van den Haag it is clear that it is
    better to place the risk of the killing of the
    innocent on the lives of convicted felons than it
    is to place the risk of being killed on the
    innocent population.

33
PRINCIPLE SIX III
  • Bedau says that this argument is not as
    conclusive as it may seem, and it is not enough
    to outweigh other arguments against the death
    penalty.
  • And he says that it is really a disguised version
    of the first policy goal of punishment which is
    that it should reduce crime.
  • Thus this principle argues that reducing crime is
    more important than anything else.
  • Bedau also objects that we cannot really compare
    the two risks discussed - the risk that an
    innocent person will be executed as opposed to
    the risk to the innocent given no death penalty.

34
BEDAUS CONCLUSIONS ABOUT THE DEATH PENALTY
  • 1. The death penalty is primarily a means to one
    or more goals, but is probably not the best means
    of reaching those goals.
  • 2. Several principles favor abolition of the
    death penalty.
  • 3. However, there is no conclusive argument
    either for or against the death penalty. (An
    argument which seems conclusive to one side, such
    as lex talionis, the other side does not have to
    accept.)
  • 4. The goals and principles which Bedau has
    looked at have no obvious rank or relative
    weighting - it is hard to say which are more
    important than others.

35
GOVERNMENT POWER
  • Bedaus first argument against the death penalty
    is that the power which the government has over
    the lives of individuals should be decreased and
    not increased.
  • Of course, some government power is necessary to
    have a civil society, but the governments power
    should be constructive not destructive.
  • A governments power should enhance liberty not
    decrease it.
  • The governments use of the death penalty is a
    destructive not a constructive use of power.
  • For Bedau, it is the ultimate symbol of
    government power.

36
PAST AND FUTURE I
  • Bedaus second argument against the death penalty
    is that the goals and principles of punishment
    should be directed towards the future, not the
    past.
  • We cannot do anything to benefit the dead
    victims of crime. This is the idea that reality
    is such that some problems may have no solutions,
    at least not the kind we would wish.
  • As Bedau himself wonders how many people would
    be opposed to the death penalty if executing a
    murderer would bring back his victim? Would we
    not owe it to the victim?

37
PAST AND FUTURE II
  • The point of looking to the future is that we can
    try to do something for the living in the time
    ahead of them even if we cannot go back to the
    past to help the victim.
  • What we do is try to protect the innocent, try to
    console those affected by crime, and try to
    prevent future crimes.
  • And Bedau thinks that none of these
    future-directed constructive goals demands
    capital punishment.
  • For Bedau the death penalty, in being vindictive
    and retributive and expressing our outrage at the
    murder of an innocent person, are all directed
    towards the past.

38
FALSE PICTURES
  • Bedaus third argument against the death penalty
    is that the death penalty gives a false picture
    of man and society.
  • Bedau Far from being a symbol of justice it is
    a symbol of brutality and stupidity.
  • Bedau thinks that the common conception of the
    criminal is as an autonomous Kantian moral agent
    who freely and knowingly acts deliberately to
    kill another.
  • But Bedau says that the killers actually on death
    row do not resemble Kants rational moral agents.

39
CONCLUSION
  • For Bedau, the death penalty question concerns
    how controversial social goals, controversial
    moral principles, and disputed general facts are
    to be balanced and reasonably assessed.
  • Bedau thinks that deeper rational argument can
    decide the matter against the death penalty, but
    in this paper he has only attempted to sort out
    what the difficulties are.

40
The Ultimate Punishment a Defense
Ernest van den Haag
41
PRELIMINARY CONSIDERATIONS
  • van den Haag notes that, on average, there are
    about 20,000 homicides a year in the U. S., but
    fewer than 300 convicted murderers are sentenced
    to death - about 1.5.. Accordingly, most
    convicts sentenced to death are likely to die of
    old age.
  • It is interesting to note here that van den Haag
    finds death row as a semipermanent or permanent
    if they are never executed residence to be
    cruel, because convicts are denied the amenities
    of normal prison life, such as contact with
    other prisoners. (Cf. Kant.)
  • Even though the execution rate is so small, van
    den Haag says that the death penalty raises
    important moral questions independent of the
    number of executions.

42
DISCRIMINATION AND CAPRICIOUS DISTRIBUTION I
  • van den Haag notes that some people object to the
    death penalty because it is not evenly applied.
  • This can be for reason of discrimination, where
    minority murderers may be more likely to be
    sentenced to death and executed than murderers
    who form part of the majority population, or for
    reason of caprice, as when one person is executed
    and another not for no predictable or clearly
    understandable reason.
  • In addition, money may make a difference, so that
    of two equally guilty people one is executed and
    another not based on the affordable quality of
    his or her legal defense.

43
DISCRIMINATION AND CAPRICIOUS DISTRIBUTION II
  • However, van den Haag says that how the death
    penalty is in fact applied - whether or not it is
    evenly and so fairly applied - is irrelevant to
    the morality of the punishment.
  • The death penalty is either moral or immoral in
    itself.
  • You cannot make it moral if it is immoral by
    applying it equally, and you cannot make it
    immoral if it is moral by only applying it to
    some convicted murderers and not to others, for
    whatever reason or reasons. (Its uneven
    application would be a separate moral issue.)

44
DISCRIMINATION AND CAPRICIOUS DISTRIBUTION III
  • Further, in being applied unevenly, the death
    penalty is the same as every other punishment, in
    that every punishment is also unevenly applied.
  • And van den Haag says that Maldistribution of
    any punishment among those who deserve it is
    irrelevant to its justice or morality.
  • The only relevant question for van den Haag
    concerning the death penalty is does the
    convicted murderer deserve to be executed?

45
DISCRIMINATION AND CAPRICIOUS DISTRIBUTION IV
  • If the death penalty is morally justified for
    convicted murderers, then it does not matter to
    the morality of the punishment whether one
    murderer gets executed and another does not.
  • van den Haag Even if poor or black convicts
    guilty of capital offenses suffer capital
    punishment, and other convicts equally guilty of
    the same crimes do not, a more equal
    distribution, however desirable, would merely be
    more equal. It would not be more just to the
    convicts under the sentence of death.

46
DISCRIMINATION AND CAPRICIOUS DISTRIBUTION V
  • Even if a guilty person is not executed, he still
    deserves to be executed if capital punishment is
    morally justified.
  • van den Haags way of putting this is to say that
    equality is less important morally than justice.
  • And he says that Punishments are imposed on
    persons, not on racial or economic groups. Guilt
    is personal. The only relevant question is does
    the person to be executed deserve the
    punishment?

47
DISCRIMINATION AND CAPRICIOUS DISTRIBUTION VI
  • According to van den Haag, what is a just
    punishment for an offense is just no matter
    whether it is evenly or unevenly distributed
    amongst the guilty.
  • van den Haag Whether or not others who deserve
    the same punishment, whatever their economic or
    racial group, have avoided execution is
    irrelevant.
  • van den Haag Justice requires that as many of
    the guilty as possible be punished, regardless of
    whether others have avoided punishment.

48
DISCRIMINATION AND CAPRICIOUS DISTRIBUTION VII
  • For van den Haag, it is not just to let people
    escape punishment who deserve to be punished, but
    that does not make punishment unjust for those
    who are punished.
  • And van den Haag notes that some inequality of
    punishment is unavoidable in any legal system as
    a practical matter. People are not perfect, and
    so their legal and penal systems are not going to
    be perfect either.
  • But, for van den Haag, unequal justice is better
    than injustice, and injustice is what we have
    when anyone escapes punishment which he deserves.

49
RISK TO THE INNOCENT I
  • van den Haag says that there seems little doubt
    that innocent people have been executed, and that
    such people will also be unjustly executed in the
    future.
  • But he says that nearly all human activities, and
    not just punishment, carry some risk to the
    innocent. In this sense then punishment,
    including capital punishment, is not unusual.
  • Innocent people can be killed in driving
    accidents or from construction, for instance, but
    we do not give these things up because we think
    that the benefits of travel and construction
    outweigh the risks to the innocent.

50
RISK TO THE INNOCENT II
  • Analogously, van den Haag says that the
    occasional execution of an innocent person is
    outweighed by the benefits to society of the
    death penalty.
  • The chief benefit of the death penalty to
    society, for van den Haag, is its justness or its
    morality.
  • This is because, for van den Haag, the death
    penalty is the only appropriate punishment for
    the crime of murder, and not to punish murderers
    by executing them would be unjust, and so not a
    benefit to society.

51
RISK TO THE INNOCENT III
  • van den Haag also maintains that, for people who
    think that the death penalty is immoral in any
    case - whether evenly applied or not, or whether
    or not an innocent person is executed - the
    occasional miscarriage of justice which happens
    from executing an innocent person can hardly be
    the decisive reason for finding it immoral.

52
DETERRENCE I
  • van den Haag admits that there is no conclusive
    evidence that the death penalty is a better
    deterrent to crime than other kinds of
    punishment.
  • However, he does not think that the issue of
    deterrence argues either for or against the death
    penalty.
  • He thinks that those people who are opposed to
    the death penalty would be opposed to it even if
    it were shown to be a better deterrent than some
    other form of punishment, say life in prison
    without parole.

53
DETERRENCE II
  • van den Haag says that opponents of the death
    penalty appear to value the life of a convicted
    murder or, at least, his non-execution, more
    highly than they value the lives of the innocent
    victims who might be spared by using the death
    penalty to deter prospective murderers.
  • van den Haag also says that he would still favor
    the death penalty for murder even if it were
    shown that capital punishment is not a better
    deterrent than other forms of punishment, and
    would only favor its abolition if evidence showed
    that executions increased rather than decreased
    the murder rate by functioning as a deterrent.
  • But van den Haag does think that the threat of
    capital punishment is a better deterrent to crime
    than other forms of punishment because of its
    finality.

54
DETERRENCE III
  • van den Haag thinks that saving the lives of
    innocent people by using the threat of capital
    punishment is more important than preserving the
    lives of convicted murderers by thinking that the
    death penalty is not a deterrent.
  • For van den Haag, the important point is that the
    lives of innocent people are valuable, whereas
    the lives of convicted murderers are not due to
    their crimes.
  • van den Haag says that it is the purpose of the
    law to protect the innocent, not the guilty.

55
DETERRENCE IV
  • van den Haag recognizes that murder rates are
    determined by many factors, and recognizes that
    we cannot be sure that by threatening execution
    for a convicted murderer that the murder rate
    will thereby be lower than it would if we did not
    have that form of threatened punishment.
  • Even so he maintains that the threat of execution
    does deter at least some people from murdering
    others, and this deterrence is an argument in
    favor of the death penalty in addition to his
    fundamental argument that there is no justice for
    the crime of murder without it.

56
DETERRENCE V
  • Thus whether it is a deterrent or not, van den
    Haag says that The severity and finality of the
    death penalty is appropriate to the seriousness
    and finality of murder. And this
    appropriateness is moral appropriateness.

57
COST
  • Some people object to the death penalty because
    they maintain that it is more expensive than life
    imprisonment. This is because of the legal costs
    which must be born by the state in the lengthy
    appeals process.
  • van den Haag says that this argument is flawed
    by the implied assumption that life prisoners
    will generate no judicial costs during their
    imprisonment.
  • This cannot be assumed, and so the issue of
    expense can be questioned, but even if the cost
    of pursuing the death penalty is more expensive
    than life imprisonment, still the death penalty
    is justified on grounds of justice.

58
SUFFERING I
  • Some people object to the death penalty on the
    grounds that it makes the murderer on death row
    suffer more than his victim did - for instance,
    isolation and anxiety from anticipating execution
    - and no punishment ought to inflict more
    suffering on the criminal than the victim.
  • This view is related to lex talionis, or the law
    of retaliation which says that the punishment
    should fit the crime. According to this
    principle, what the criminal took from his victim
    society should take from the criminal. In the
    case of murder this would be a life for a life.
    And it would follow from considering suffering as
    just punishment in relation to lex talionis that
    the criminal should suffer at least as much as
    his victim, but not more than his victim.

59
SUFFERING II
  • van den Haags first response to this objection
    to the excessive suffering caused by capital
    punishment is that we cannot really know if the
    murderer suffers more than the victim.
  • However, whether he does or not is irrelevant
    since, for van den Haag, the crucial point here
    is that the victim did not deserve to suffer
    whatever she suffered.
  • van den Haags second response is that the
    limitations of the lex talionis were meant to
    restrain private vengeance, not the social
    retribution which has taken its place.

60
SUFFERING III
  • van den Haag Punishment - regardless of the
    motivation - is not intended to revenge, offset,
    or compensate for the victims suffering, or to
    be measured by it.
  • van den Haag Punishment is to vindicate the law
    and the social order undermined by the crime.
  • van den Haag This is why a kidnappers penal
    confinement is not limited to the period for
    which he imprisoned his victim not is a
    burglars confinement meant merely to offset the
    suffering or harm he caused his victim nor is it
    meant only to offset the advantage he gained.

61
THE LEGITIMIZATION OF UNLAWFUL KILLING I
  • van den Haag Another argument, heard at least
    since Beccaria is that, by killing a murderer, we
    encourage, endorse, or legitimize unlawful
    killing.
  • Yet van den Haag says that although all
    punishments are meant to be unpleasant, it is
    seldom argued that they legitimize the unlawful
    imposition of identical unpleasantness. For
    instance, imprisonment is not thought to
    legitimize kidnapping.

62
THE LEGITIMIZATION OF UNLAWFUL KILLING II
  • For van den Haag, The difference between murder
    and execution is that the first is unlawful and
    undeserved, the second a lawful and deserved
    punishment for an unlawful act.
  • van den Haag The physical similarities of the
    punishment to the crime are irrelevant. The
    relevant difference is not physical, but social.

63
WHY DOES SOCIETY PUNISH?
  • van den Haag notes that society threatens
    punishment in order to deter crime, and society
    imposes punishment in order to make the threats
    credible. Thus the threat of punishment for a
    crime committed is of no use unless the
    punishment is enforced.
  • van den Haag says that both the threat of
    punishment and actual punishment are necessary to
    deter crime. And the fact that they function as
    deterrents is sufficient practical justification
    for them.
  • Societies also punish as retribution for the
    crimes actually committed. And this retribution
    is an independent moral justification.

64
THE JUSTIFICATION OF PUNISHMENT
  • van den Haag says that An explicit threat of
    punitive action is necessary to the justification
    of any legal punishment. Thus, a punishment is
    not just if there is no prior law which threatens
    the punishment as a consequence for committing a
    particular crime.
  • But van den Haag notes that a prior law
    legitimizes the threatened punishment only if
    the threat is warranted. To that end, To be
    sufficiently justified, the threat of
    punishment must have a rational and legitimate
    purpose.
  • Thus, van den Haag says that Your money or your
    life does not qualify nor does the threat of an
    unjust law nor, finally, does a threat that is
    altogether disproportionate to the importance of
    its purpose.

65
JUST PUNISHMENT OF CRIMINAL ACTION I
  • For van den Haag, punishment is not only
    practically justified but it is morally
    justified, and is so justified independently of
    its practical justification.
  • That punishment is morally justified means that
    the infliction of legal punishment on a guilty
    person cannot be unjust.
  • It cannot be unjust because when a criminal
    commits a crime he volunteers to assume the risk
    of being punished for the crime which he commits.

66
JUST PUNISHMENT OF CRIMINAL ACTION II
  • Because the punishment which a criminal receives
    is the one which he risked suffering, it is not
    unjust.
  • In the case of the death penalty, since a
    murderer voluntarily risks the death penalty in
    deliberately killing an innocent person, the
    punishment of death for him is not unjust.
  • Further, there is a disparity of volunteering to
    risk something here between criminal and victim
    since, whereas the criminal voluntarily risks
    being punished in committing his crime, his
    victim volunteered to risk nothing.

67
JUST PUNISHMENT OF CRIMINAL ACTION III
  • For van den Haag, because
  • A) a murderer voluntarily risks execution in
    murdering
  • B) his victim did not voluntarily risked being
    killed and
  • C) because we have the advance threat of
    execution for murder,
  • It follows that capital punishment is just.

68
IS THE DEATH PENALTY EXCESSIVE?
  • However, van den Haag recognizes that, although
    capital punishment cannot be unjust in this
    sense, still people might object that it is
    overly punitive and is morally degrading.
  • To view the death penalty as overly punitive one
    would think that no crime, not even first degree
    murder, warranted this punishment.
  • And here van den Haag says that Such a belief
    can be neither corroborated nor refuted it is an
    article of faith.
  • van den Haag thinks that the murderer does not
    have the same right to life which everyone else
    has. Rather, he forfeits his right to life
    because of his crime. Not only is it not
    excessive, but it is the only just punishment for
    the crime of murder.

69
IS THE DEATH PENALTY MORALLY DEGRADING? I
  • Some objectors to the death penalty might argue
    that it is immoral because everybody, the
    murderer no less than the victim, has an
    imprescriptible (natural?) right to life.
  • (An imprescriptible right is one that cannot in
    any circumstances be taken away or abandoned.
    Thus if there is an imprescriptible right to life
    then the murderer has it as much as his or her
    victim and so cannot for this reason be
    executed.)
  • van den Haag says that he agrees here with
    Jeremy Benthams view that any such natural and
    imprescriptible rights are nonsense upon
    stilts.

70
IS THE DEATH PENALTY MORALLY DEGRADING? II
  • Further, van den Haag cites both Kant and Hegel
    who thought that, far from degrading the
    executed convict, the death penalty affirms his
    humanity by affirming his rationality and his
    responsibility for his actions.
  • This of course assumes that all adults, including
    murderers, are rational, and do not act
    irrationally when killing, and it assumes that
    they are capable of taking responsibility for
    their actions.
  • We have already seen that Bedau does not think
    that the average person on death row much
    resembles a Kantian rational moral agent, and so
    would find van den Haags argument here
    unconvincing.

71
IS THE DEATH PENALTY MORALLY DEGRADING? III
  • Both Kant and Hegel thought that execution is
    required to preserve the convicted murderers
    dignity as a rational moral agent.
  • As van den Haag puts it They thought that
    execution, when deserved, is required for the
    sake of the convicts dignity. (Does not life
    imprisonment violate human dignity more than
    execution, by keeping alive a prisoner deprived
    of all ? autonomy?)

72
IS THE DEATH PENALTY MORALLY DEGRADING? IV
  • One might question the use of the term all in
    the preceding quote since in fact it is death
    which deprives a person of all autonomy. The
    incarcerated individual still has some autonomy -
    freedom of thought for instance.
  • If the person did not have this freedom of
    thought then he could not be protected by some
    human rights theories which say that convicted
    killers should not be executed because they still
    have the right - fundamental to all persons - to
    dialogue, to be a partner in the search for
    truth.

73
DEATH AND THE DEATH PENALTY
  • van den Haag thinks that common sense does not
    see normal death as inhuman. This is because
    death is an essential part of our humanity.
  • Therefore, those, such as Justice Brennan, who
    see the death penalty as morally degrading must
    see death as inhuman when it is neither natural
    nor accidental.
  • van den Haag says that capital punishment tells
    the convicted killer that he is not fit to be a
    member of society, that his fellow humans have
    found him unworthy of living.
  • Because of his crime, the murderer is being
    expelled from the realm of the living.

74
THE SELF-DEGRADATION OF MURDER
  • In deliberately murdering, the killer degrades
    himself as a person, and the death penalty is
    simply societys recognition of his
    self-degradation.
  • For van den Haag, the essence of capital
    punishment is societys recognition that the
    killer has degraded himself by killing.
  • To believe that it is the execution which
    degrades the criminal rather than the act of
    murder is to get things the wrong way around.
  • For van den Haag, capital punishment is the only
    punishment which fits the crime of murder.

75
SHOULD EXECUTIONS BE TELEVISED? I
  • No, according to van den Haag, and this is the
    case even if, by televising, it might be thought
    to be a greater deterrent than it is without
    making the execution public.
  • The reasons, according to van den Haag, are
  • 1. The death of even a murderer, however
    well-deserved, should not serve as public
    entertainment.
  • 2. Television would unavoidably trivialize
    executions. This is because they would appear
    between game shows, situation comedies, and the
    like.

76
SHOULD EXECUTIONS BE TELEVISED? II
  • 3. A televised execution would present the
    murderer as the victim of the state. This is
    because televised executions would focus on the
    physical aspects of the punishment, rather than
    the nature of the crime and the suffering of the
    victim. As a result, the moral significance of
    the execution would not be communicated to the
    audience. Rather television would shift the
    focus to the pitiable fear of the murderer.
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com