Why NL is not CF - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 41
About This Presentation
Title:

Why NL is not CF

Description:

A. Why are the Swiss German constructions a proof that at least some NLs are not ... This argument is SUFFICIENT for Swiss German's status as a non-CFL. ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:58
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 42
Provided by: studentsW
Category:
Tags: german

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: Why NL is not CF


1
Why NL is not CF
  • As proven in Stuart Shiebers 1985
    paper,Evidence Against Context Freeness,and
    explained informally for people whose eyes glaze
    over formal proofs

2
Motivation
  • Important to theoretical linguists and
    philosophers of language. Central to Chomskys
    innateness hypothesis as well as to critics of
    transformational grammars and their derivatives
  • Should be of at least theoretical interest to
    Computational Linguists because computational
    processing difficulty of languages is directly
    linked to their formal complexity
  • Personal motivation If I label myself a Linguist
    I should have more than just a vague idea of what
    this question is about

3
Tiny subset of the question
  • A. Why are the Swiss German constructions a proof
    that at least some NLs are not CFLs?
  • B. How are the Swiss German examples crucially
    different from similar Dutch examples that are
    not a proof of the non-CFL-ness of NLs?
  • C. Are Polish (and other free word order
    languages) that contain sentences essentially
    identical to the Swiss German ones additional
    examples non-CFLs?

4
The Chomsky Hierarchyadapted from
www.wikipedia.com a, ß, ? strings of terminals
and nonterminals, A,B nonterminals, x-string of
nonterminals
5
Preliminaries Regular Languages
  • Productions (A-gtxB, A-gtx, where A and B are
    nonterminals and x is any string in the language)
  • Here is an example of a regular grammar
  • Vocabulary of terminalsa, cat, dog, mouse,
    chased, scared, squeaked
  • Vocabulary of non-terminalsS,VP,NP
  • S is the only initial symbol.
  • S-gta mouse VP
  • VP-gtsqueaked
  • VP-gtchased NP
  • VP-gtscared NP
  • NP-gta N
  • N-gtcat
  • N-gtdog
  • N-gtmouse

6
Preliminaries Regular Languages
  • S-gta mouse VP
  • VP-gtsqueaked
  • VP-gtchased NP
  • VP-gtscared NP
  • NP-gta N
  • N-gtcat
  • N-gtdog
  • N-gtmouse
  • What sentences can this grammar
    recognize/generate?
  • A mouse squeaked.
  • A mouse chased a cat.
  • A mouse chased a dog.
  • A mouse chased a mouse.
  • A mouse scared a cat.
  • A mouse scared a dog.
  • A mouse scared a mouse.

7
Preliminaries Regular Languages
  • If we want this grammar to generate sentences
    with a subject other than a mouse we have to
    add the following productions
  • S-gta cat VP
  • S-gta dog VP
  • This is inefficient
  • Whats worse, it doesnt capture the NP
    generalization (i.e. doesnt give us the right
    structure)
  • We need S-gtNP VP but this is not a legitimate
    production

8
Preliminaries Regular Languages
  • Consider a CFG that accepts the same sentences
    (slightly different nonterminal vocabulary)
  • S-gtNP VP
  • NP-gtDT N
  • DT-gta
  • N-gtcat
  • N-gtdog
  • N-gtmouse
  • VP-gtVI
  • VP-gtVT NP
  • VI-gtsqueaked
  • VT-gtchased
  • VT-gtscared

9
Preliminaries Regular Languages
  • Crucial point the regular grammar shown here
    recognizes the strings we want it to recognize
    but it doesnt assign to them the structure we
    want. That is, this grammar weakly generates the
    language in question but doesnt strongly
    generate it. Why is this important?

10
Preliminaries Regular Languages
  • An example of why it is important
  • I saw the man with a telescope.
  • Recognizing the string is not sufficient for
    expressing its syntactic ambiguity
  • We need some way of expressing the ambiguity to
    get at the two meanings.
  • The reason I am drawing attention to the
    weak/strong distinction is that it seems that
    there is some conceptual confusion. When people
    say language x is CF that dont always say
    whether they mean that it is strongly CF or just
    weakly CF. In the context of formal languages and
    automata, people talk about weak generative
    capacity, but to us linguists strong generative
    capacity is of greater interest.

11
Preliminaries Regular Languages
  • In any case, for some sentences of English, one
    cannot write a regular grammar at all. That is,
    some sentences cannot be even recognized by a
    regular grammar, let alone assigned the correct
    structure. That is, they are not even weakly
    regular.
  • A mouse a cat chased squeaked.
  • A mouse a cat a dog scared chased squeaked.
  • Example of Center Embedding
  • NP1 NP2 NP3 V3 V2 V1
  • There is no way to write a regular grammar for an
    arbitrary number of such embeddings.
  • How do we know this for sure?

12
Preliminaries Regular Languages
  • Pumping Theorem for finite state languages
  • If a language is an infinite set over some
    alphabet E, then there are strings x,y,z made out
    of the characters of E, such that y is not the
    empty string, and xynz is in the language for
    all ngt0.
  • What does this mean?

13
Preliminaries Regular Languages
  • Example Labnngt0
  • Some strings in this language are
  • a
  • ab
  • abb
  • abbb
  • There are strings xynz such that y is not empty
    and xynz is in the language for all ngt0. For
    example, the string abb is such a string xa,
    yb, and zb. The following are all in the
    language
  • n0, xa, yb0, zb, ab
  • n1, xa, yb1, zb, abb
  • n2, xa, yb2, zb, abbb
  • Why does this have to be true?

14
Preliminaries Regular Languages
  • If a language is regular then by definition there
    is some regular grammar that accepts it.
  • By definition a grammar has a finite set of
    productions. In our example, one grammar for this
    language could be S-gtaB, B-gtbB, B-gtØ
  • But if the language is to consist of an infinite
    number of strings then there are strings in this
    language that have more symbols in them than
    there are productions, so some production must be
    applied more than once to generate the string.

15
Preliminaries Regular Languages
  • Lets call the substring read by the grammar up
    to the point in which the production which ends
    up being used more than once is used for the
    first time, x (so in our example, lets say that
    we have a production such as S-gtaB so xa) .
  • Now lets call the substring that is read when
    the production eventually used more than once is
    used for the first time, y (so in our example,
    lets say that we have a production such as
    B-gtbB so yb).
  • Lets call the substring that is read from the
    point where we used that B-gtbB production for the
    first time to the end of the string, z (in this
    case z can result from B-gtb or even be empty and
    correspond to no production).
  • But since the middle substring, y, is the result
    of applying a recursive production (in this
    example, B-gtbB), we know that we can apply this
    production arbitrarily many times and thus make n
    in yn arbitrarily large.

16
Preliminaries Regular Languages
  • So how would we use the Pumping theorem to prove
    that the language that accepts the sentences
    exhibiting center embedding that are shown above
    cannot be regular.
  • Similar language Lanbnngt0
  • ab
  • aabb
  • aaabbb
  • aaaabbbb
  • .
  • This language does not contain any strings in
    which the number of bs does not equal the number
    of preceding as or which includes any as after
    bs
  • a
  • aab
  • abb
  • abab

17
Preliminaries Regular Languages
  • Imagine that Lanbnngt0 were a regular
    language.
  • Then there would be some string xyz, such that y
    is not the empty string, and xynz is in the
    language for all ngt0.
  • The substring y is the substring created by the
    recursive rule and it therefore cannot contain
    both as and bs because wed end up with bs
    following as when we pump the string
  • So the substring y must consist entirely of as
    or entirely of bs.

18
Preliminaries Regular Languages
  • If y consists entirely of as then z consists
    entirely of bs.
  • But every time we apply the recursive rule that
    created y we get one more a and since z is fixed
    we cannot increase it by the same number of bs,
    so it will always be possible to get a greater
    number of as than bs.
  • If y consists entirely of bs then x consists
    entirely of as. But every time we apply the
    recursive rule that created y we get one more b
    and since x is fixed we cannot increase it by the
    same number of as, so it will always be possible
    to get a greater number of bs than as.
  • So there is no string xynz that satisfies the
    conditions for a regular language. So
    Lanbnngt0 is not a regular language.

19
Preliminaries Regular Languages
  • Now how does this relate to the center embedding
    examples?
  • The set of sentences that exhibit center
    embedding as described above may be viewed as a
    special case of the Lanbnngt0 language, with
    nouns being as and verbs being bs, or
  • L(catdogmouse)n(chasedscaredsqueaked)nngt0
    .
  • There is no way of writing a regular grammar that
    accepts strings with an arbitrarily long number
    of nouns followed by the same exact number of
    verbs.

20
Preliminaries Regular Languages
  • So we have shown that the subset of English which
    consists of these types of sentences is not
    regular.
  • But this doesnt in itself prove that English
    itself is not regular.
  • In order to show that English is not regular we
    need to use a few more steps in our proof.
  • Regular languages are closed under intersection.
    This means that intersecting a regular language
    with a regular language produces a regular
    language.

21
Preliminaries Regular Languages
  • If English were a regular language than
    intersecting it with some other regular language
    would result in a regular language. We will try
    to find some regular language and show that
    intersecting it with English results in
    L(catdogmouse)n(chasedscaredsqueaked)nngt0
    which we have already shown is not a regular
    language.
  • What language when intersected with English would
    produce L(catdogmouse)n(chasedscaredsqueake
    d)nngt0?
  • L(catdogmouse)(chasedscaredsqueaked) is
    clearly regular and intersecting it with English
    results in L(catdogmouse)n(chasedscaredsquea
    ked)nngt0.
  • So English is not regular.

22
Brief History
  • Chomsky (1963) NLs are not regular or CF.
    Proposed the transformational grammar model as an
    alternative
  • The notion that all NL phenomena are regular was
    put to rest. But the inadequacy of context free
    grammars for handling NL proved more
    controversial. Chomskys proofs for the
    non-CFG-ness of NL are not accepted.
  • Peters Ritchie (1973) showed that Chomskys
    transformational grammar framework was powerful
    enough to describe any recursively enumerable set
    - perhaps too powerful.
  • Until 1985, all the arguments for the claim that
    NLs are not CF were shown to be flawed (see
    alleged counterexamples debunked in Gazdar
    Pullum (1982))
  • Shieber (1985) provides the first syntactic
    counterexample to the claim that CFGs are
    powerful enough to generate NL. Shiebers
    argument survived until today.

23
Dutch
  • Dutch has been initially introduced as a
    counterexample but later dismissed. The example
    and the explanation of why it is not a
    counterexample is presented in Bresnan, Kaplan,
    Peters Zaenen (1982).
  • Dutch has the following structures
  • dat Jan Marie Piet de kinderen zag
    helpen laten zwemmen
  • that Jan Marie Piet the children see-past
    help-inf make-inf swim-inf
  • ..that Jan saw Marie help Piet make the children
    swim
  • The structure is
  • that NP1 NP2 NP3 NP4 V1 V2 V3 V4

24
Dutch
  • Arbitrarily many of these NP V pairs may be
    inserted to form longer sentences.
  • The number of verbs and NPs must be the same.
  • The first verb has to be tensed and it must agree
    with the first NP.
  • All the other verbs have to be infinitives.
  • The subcategorization constraints between the
    final NP and final verb must be satisfied.
  • This is an example of cross-serial dependencies.
  • A language that has strings with arbitrarily long
    cross-serial dependencies is not a CFL.

25

Center Embedding
1
3
3
2
2
1

Cross Serial Dependencies
1
2
3
2
1
3
26
Context Free Languages
  • Lambncmdnm,ngt0
  • We can use the pumping theorem for CFLs to show
    this.
  • If L is an infinite CFL, then there is some
    constant K such that any string w in L longer
    than K can be factored into substrings wuvxyz
    such that v and y are not both empty and uvnxynz
    is in L for all ngt0.
  • What does this mean?

27
Context Free Languages
  • Lets look first at Lanbnngt1
  • One CFG for this L would be
  • S-gtaSb
  • S-gtab
  • n0, wempty, va0, xab, yb0, zempty, ab
  • n1, wempty, va1, xab, yb1, zempty, aabb
  • n2, wempty, va2, xab, yb2, zempty, aaabbb

28
Context Free Languages
  • We can show that ambncmdn is not CF by using the
    pumping theorem.
  • If ambncmdn were a CFL then there would be some
    constant K such that any string in L longer than
    K, say ak bk ck dk, for example, could be written
    as wuvxyz such that v and y are not both empty
    and v and y are pumpable.

29
Context Free Languages
  • v cant consist of both as and bs because when
    pumped it would produce strings with as after
    bs. Similarly, it cannot consist of both bs and
    cs or both cs and ds. The same goes for the
    other pumpable term, y.
  • So v must consist entirely of as or entirely of
    bs or entirely of cs or entirely of ds. Then
    no matter what y we choose, any pumping of v and
    y simultaneously will result in strings not in L
    because we can pump only 2 symbols at a time but
    not 4.

30
Dutch
  • The Dutch example seems to exhibit the same cross
    serial dependencies we just showed could not be
    handled by a CFG.
  • However, it is possible to write a CFG that would
    accept these Dutch strings.

31
Dutch
  • We can divide the verbs as follows
  • 1. V-index Form infinitive, Subcats for a
    subject (swim)
  • 2. V-tensed Form tensed, Subcats for a subject
    it agrees with and an S or S complement without
    complementizer (saw)
  • 3. V-infinitive Form infinitive, Subcats for a
    subject and an S or S complement without
    complementizer (help, make)
  • 1. S-gtNP-agr S-agr-index V-index
  • 2. S-agr-index-gtNP S-agr-index V-infinitive
  • 3. S-agr-index-gtNP S-agr-index V-infinitive
  • 4. S-agr-index-gtNP-index V-tensed
  • 5. NP-index -gt JanPietMariethe children
  • 6. V-tensed-gtsaw
  • 7. V-index-gtswim
  • 8. V-infinitive-gt helpmake
  • These productions would accept the example
    sentence as well as the following sentences
  • that Jan Marie Piet the children see-past
    make-inf help-inf swim-inf
  • that Jan Marie the children Piet see-past
    help-inf make-inf swim-inf
  • that Jan Marie the children Piet see-past
    make-inf help-inf swim-inf
  • These are perfectly grammatical.

32
Dutch
  • How come this works? Note that the only items we
    care about are the ones in bold.
  • that Jan Marie Piet the children see-past
    help-inf make-inf swim-inf
  • thar Jan saw Marie help Piet make the children
    swim
  • that Jan Marie Piet the children see-past
    make-inf help-inf swim-inf
  • thar Jan saw Marie make Piet help the children
    swim
  • that Jan Marie the children Piet see-past
    help-inf make-inf swim-inf
  • thar Jan saw Marie help the children make Piet
    swim
  • that Jan Marie the children Piet see-past
    make-inf help-inf swim-inf
  • thar Jan saw Marie make the children help Piet
    swim

33
Dutch
  • We can recognize and generate all the grammatical
    strings with this grammar because the number of
    items we need to cross-reference is finite and
    all the other items are interchangeable
    syntactically.
  • Note that the sentences above are all grammatical
    but each has a different interpretation in Dutch.
  • The final tree structure of each sentence will
    only reflect the order of the words in the
    sentence and not all the cross-serial
    dependencies.
  • So we can write a grammar to recognize and
    generate all these strings but not to assign a
    structure to them that will preserve the
    cross-serial dependencies.
  • So the grammar above weakly generates the
    cross-serial examples but doesnt strongly
    generate them.
  • This is sufficient if we are interested in
    classifying sentences as grammatical or
    ungrammatical but is it sufficient for semantic
    interpretation? Probably not.

34
Swiss German
  • How is the Swiss German example set presented by
    Shieber (1985) crucially different from the Dutch
    example set?
  • mer em Hans es haus halfed
    aastriiche
  • we Hans-DAT the house-ACC helped paint
  • we helped Hans paint the house.
  • mer dchind em Hans es haus
    lond halfe aastriiche
  • we the-children-ACC Hans-DAT the house-ACC let
    help paint
  • we let the children help Hans paint the house.

35
Swiss German
  • we the-children-ACC Hans-DAT the house-ACC let
    help paint
  • In Swiss German verbs subcategorize for NPs with
    specific cases.
  • Some verbs subcategorize for accusative NPs and
    some verbs subcategorize for dative NPs
  • The number of verbs subcategorizing for
    accusative case NPs must be the same as the
    number of accusative NPs in the sentence and the
    number of verbs subcategorizing for dative case
    NPs must be the same as the number of dative NPs
    in the sentence.

36
Swiss German
  • Why cant we produce arbitrarily long sentences
    of this type with a CFG?
  • Simplest case all the accusatives precede all
    the datives
  • NPam NPdn Vam Vdn
  • This is the same as ambncmdn which is non-CF, as
    shown earlier.

37
Swiss German
  • The Swiss German strings with all the accusatives
    preceding all the datives may be presented as
  • NP_ACCmNP_DATnV_ACCmV_DATn
  • which is the same as
  • ambncmdn which has been shown not to be CF.
  • CFLs are closed under intersection with regular
    languages.
  • If Swiss German were CF then intersecting it with
    the regular language abcd would yield a CF.
  • But the intersection, wambnxcmdny, is not CF, so
    Swiss German cannot be CF.

38
Swiss German
  • Shiebers argument rests on the impossibility of
    writing a CFG that would insure that the total
    number of accusatives and datives matched and not
    on the order they appear in.
  • This argument is SUFFICIENT for Swiss Germans
    status as a non-CFL.
  • The argument does NOT DEPEND on the ORDER of the
    inner NPs and inner Verbs.
  • Surprising.
  • Orders other than NP1 NP2 NP3..NPn V1 V2 V3 ..Vn
    are acceptable.
  • So, Polish and other similar examples provide the
    same exact counterexamples that Swiss German
    does.

39
Conclusions
  • If I am right then one important point to take
    away from this the often cited Swiss German
    example is by no means unique. It just happens to
    be the first published counterexample of NL
    syntax not being CF. Once the inadequacy of CFGs
    was shown for one language, there is no need to
    show it for other languages.

40
Conclusions
  • Another important point is that the proof shows
    that Swiss German, and thus NL, is not even
    weakly CF.
  • Since in CL we are not interested in merely
    recognizing strings, weak generative capacity
    without strong generative capacity is of limited
    use to us and plenty of examples have been
    presented to support the claim that NLs are not
    strongly CF before Shiebers paper, so its
    importance is perhaps more theoretical than
    practical from a CL point of view.

41
References
  • Bresnan, Kaplan, Peters Zaenen (1982) - Joan
    Bresnan, Ron Kaplan, Stanley Peters, and Annie
    Zaenen. 1982. Cross-serial dependencies in Dutch.
    Linguistic Inquiry, 13(4)613--35.
  • Chomsky (1963) - Chomsky, Noam. 1963. Formal
    properties of grammar. In Luce, R.D., R.R. Bush
    and E. Galanter (eds), Handbook of Mathematical
    Psychology, vol.II. New York Wiley, pp. 323-418.
  • Partee (1993) - Mathematical Methods in
    Linguistics, Corrected second printing of the
    first edition (Studies in Linguistics and
    Philosophy) by Barbara H. Partee, Alice Ter
    Muelen and Robert Wall
  • Peters Ritchie (1973) - Peters, Stanley R.
    Ritchie (1973). "On the generative power of
    transformational grammars". Information Sciences
    6 49-83.
  • Pullum Gazdar (1982) - Pullum, Geoffrey K., and
    Gerald Gazdar (1982) "Natural languages and
    context-free languages," ltugtLinguistics and
    Philosophylt/ugt 4, 471--504.
  • Savitch (1987) - The formal complexity of natural
    language" by Walter J. Savitch, Emmon Bach,
    William Marsh, and Gila Safran-Naveh. D. Reidel
    1987
  • Shieber (1985) - Stuart M. Shieber. Evidence
    against the context-freeness of natural language.
    Linguistics and Philosophy, 8333-343, 1985.
    http//www.eecs.harvard.edu/shieber/Biblio/Papers
    /shieber85.pdf
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com