Is Failing to Give to Famine Relief Wrong?

1 / 19
About This Presentation
Title:

Is Failing to Give to Famine Relief Wrong?

Description:

Is Failing to Give to Famine Relief Wrong? Is Failing to Give to Famine Relief Wrong? II II Is Failing to Give to Famine Relief Wrong? Arthur s Central Argument ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:48
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 20
Provided by: typetoken

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: Is Failing to Give to Famine Relief Wrong?


1
Is Failing to Give toFamine Relief Wrong?
Is Failing to Give toFamine Relief Wrong?
II
II
2
John Arthur World Hunger and Moral Obligation
Arthurs Central Argument
Singers argument
  • Ignores an important moral factor entitlement.
  • Requires an overhauling of our moral code, which
    is not required.

The General Principle
Singers General Principle (Arthur calls it the
greater moral evil rule) requires substantial
redistribution of wealth.
  • If it is in out power to prevent something bad
    from happening, without thereby sacrificing
    anything of comparable moral importance, we
    ought, morally, to do it.
  • Recall pond example The greater moral evil rule
    thus seems a natural way of capturing why we
    think it would be wrong not to help. (545)

3
The General Principle
  • Moral Equality We are attracted to the idea that
    like amounts of suffering (or the opposite) are
    of equal significance, regardless of who is
    experiencing them Equality demands equal
    consideration of interests as well as respect for
    certain rights. (545)
  • If we fail to give to famine relief, instead
    spending our money on a new car or fancy clothes,
    we are giving special consideration to ourselves
    or to our group, like a racist does. Equal
    consideration leads naturally to the greater
    moral evil rule.
  • There is, however, a flip-side to equality that
    Singer ignores entitlement, which falls into two
    broad categories.

4
Forms of Entitlement (1) Rights
Thought Experiment 1 Where you have two eyes and
two kidneys, some other person is blind or has a
disease that is destroying her kidneys. You can
donate one of your eyes or one of your kidneys,
to restore her sight, or extend her life. Of
course, you will, in doing so, lose something
either depth perception, or, possibly, some life
expectancy. Thought Experiment 2 There is some
person who, we can imagine, will be
psychologically harmed by your not granting
sexual favors to them. Of course, you do not want
to grant such sexual favors, and you will be, in
some less strong way, harmed by granting them.
5
Forms of Entitlement (1) Rights (contd)
  • According to the General Principle, to be
    justified in refusing, you must show that the
    unpleasantness you would experience is of equal
    importance to the harm you are preventing.
    Otherwise, you must consent.
  • If anything is clear, however, it is that our
    code does not require such heroism you are
    entitled to keep your second eye and kidney and
    not bestow sexual favors on anyone who may be
    harmed without them. (546)
  • That its your body, and you have a right to it,
    outweighs any duty you have to help.
  • (Recall discussion on a womans right to her body
    versus her duty to the fetus.)

6
Forms of Entitlement (1) Rights (contd)
Moral rights are divided into two categories
  • Negative Rights rights of noninterference.
  • The right to life, property rights, the right to
    privacy, etc.
  • Negative rights are natural, depending on what
    you are.
  • Positive Rights rights of recipience.
  • Your legal wards have a right to be fed, clothed,
    and housed.
  • Contractual rights, say, in business dealings,
    include the right not to be left holding the bag.
  • Positive rights are not natural they arise
    because others have promised, agreed, or
    contracted to give you something.

7
Forms of Entitlement (1) Rights (contd)
A duty to help a stranger in need is not the
result of a right he has.
  • Such a right would be positive, but you have made
    no promises nor entered into any contract with
    this person, so no such right exists.
  • Where the wards of a lifeguard, for instance,
    have a right to the lifeguards help, they do not
    have the same right to help from bystanders.
  • Bystanders may act cruelly in not helping a
    drowning child, but they do not thereby violate
    anyones rights.
  • We are entitled to invoke our own rights as
    justification for not giving to distant strangers
    or when the cost to us is substantial (an eye or
    a kidney, for example).

8
Forms of Entitlement (2) Deserts
The farmer who grows his good deserves it because
he earned it through his hard work.
  • A farmers deserts may be outweighed by the needs
    of his neighbors, but this is not to say that his
    deserts have no moral weight.
  • Negative Deserts A Nazi war criminal deserves
    punishment, and that will be a reason to send him
    to jail. But if nobody will be deterred by his
    suffering, or if he is old and harmless, this may
    weigh against his punishment. But this doesnt
    mean that he doesnt still deserve punishment.

9
Our Moral Code
Where our moral code tends to look to the future
(toward consequences), entitlements look to the
past
  • Whether we have rights to our money, property,
    eyes, etc., depends on how we came to acquire
    them.
  • Our common moral code requires that we ignore
    neither consequences nor entitlements.
  • Rights and deserts should not be discounted when
    considering the morality of our actions.

Are such values as rights and entitlements
outweighed by more fundamental values, such as
fairness, justice, or respect for others?
  • There seems no easy way to compare these factors.

10
Our Moral Code (contd)
Above all else, the moral code that it is
rational for us to support must be
practicali.e., it must work.
  • As such, it must gain the support of (almost)
    everyone.
  • An ideal code cannot assume people are more
    unselfish than we are Rules that would work
    only for angels are not the ones it is rational
    to support for humans. (547)
  • An ideal code cannot assume we are more objective
    than we are.
  • An ideal code cannot assume that we have perfect
    knowledge.

11
Our Moral Code (contd)
A reasonable moral code, then, would require
people to help when there is no substantial cost
to themselveswhere helping would not mean
significant reduction in a persons current level
of happiness.
  • Getting ones pants muddy would likely not result
    in significant reduction in ones happiness.
  • Giving up ones savings, ones eye, or ones
    kidney would likely result in significant
    reduction in ones happiness.
  • An ideal moral code would probably not look too
    much different from our current working code.

12
Michael Slote Famine, Affluence, and Empathy
Slotes Virtue Ethics
Virtue Ethics of caring built on the tradition of
18th Century sentimentalism.
  • Caring is an overall attitude or motivational
    state.
  • Roughly, an ethics of caring holds that an act is
    morally right or permissible if it doesnt
    exhibit a lack of caring (not mere neutrality),
    and wrong if it does.
  • When I speak of acts exhibiting a caring
    attitude or one inconsistent with caring, the
    caring I am speaking of includes attitudes toward
    distant and personally-unknown others. (548)

13
Slotes Virtue Ethics (contd)
  • An ethics of caring will hold that it is
    virtuous to be more concerned about near and dear
    than about strangers or those one knows about
    merely by description but it will also insist
    that an ideally or virtuously caring individual
    will be substantially concerned about people who
    are distant from her. (549)
  • That we have special or stronger moral
    obligations to those who are (physically or
    sentimentally) closer to us is commonsensically
    appealing.

14
Slotes Virtue Ethics (contd)
Rather than sympathy (the word Hume uses in
forming his sentimentalist theory, which today
means, roughly, a favorable attitude toward
someone), Slote is concerned with empathy (the
state or process in which one takes on the
feelings of another).
  • Question Is the development of empathy necessary
    to ones development of altruistic concern for
    others?
  • Psychology, generally, hypothesizes that caring
    works via empathy, and that morally good caring
    can be specified in relation to the development
    of human empathy.

15
Slotes Virtue Ethics (contd)
If we believe that empathy has moral force or
relevance, then we can argue that
  • Since it is easier to empathize with another
    adult human than with a squidge
  • It is as such morally worse to harm an adult
    human than to do the same to a squidge.
  • That is, we can say that an action is right or
    wrong depending on whether or not such actions
    reflect a deficiency of normally or fully-capable
    caring motivation.
  • It would then (other things being equal) be
    morally worse to prefer a fetus or embryo to a
    born human being because such a preference runs
    counter to the flow of developed human empathy
    (550)
  • Contra Singer, then, a failure to save the life
    of a distant child (by making a charitable
    donation) is not as morally bad as failing to
    save the life of a child drowning in front of
    you.

16
Empathy and Spatial Distance
Singer holds that spatial distance simply cannot
be morally relevant to our obligations to aid
others.
  • Empathy gives us a firmer basis than distance for
    distinguishing the strength of our obligations in
    the cases Singer compares.
  • Spatial distance and (decreasing) empathy do, in
    fact, correlate in a wide variety of cases.
  • Such a view can not only help to explain why
    failing to help in the drowning case seems worse
    than a failure to give to famine relief, but it
    can also justify that ordinary moral intuition.

17
Empathy and Spatial Distance (contd)
  • Turning away from someone we see who is in need
    seems worse than ignoring someone whom one knows
    only by description is in need.
  • Our empathic capacities respond to immediacy.
  • What makes failing to give aid in the former case
    more objectionable than failing to give aid in
    the latter is, Slote claims, a failure in ones
    empathic response to someone whose need one
    directly perceives.

18
Empathy and Temporal Distance
The same principle applies to temporal distance
  • Given the choice, we would typically feel more
    compelled to spend money to aid miners trapped in
    a cave-in than to spend that money on shoring up
    other mines to save a greater number of lives in
    the future.
  • The danger in the former case engages our
    empathic juices in a way that the danger in the
    latter case does not the danger is not as
    immediate.

In the cases of the miners and of Singers
drowning child vs. famine relief cases, our
negative moral responses to ones choosing to
help in the distant cases rather than the
(proximally or temporally) immediate cases is
explained by some lack of (normal) human empathy
on the part of the agent.
19
Obligations and Sacrifice
Current social-psychological research supports
the idea that humans have a substantial capacity
for empathy and for altruistic concerns based on
empathy.
  • We are not morally obligated to sacrifice most of
    our time and money to aid others, because a
    failure to do so doesnt evince an absence of
    normal or fully-developed human empathy.
  • Such a sacrifice would be morally
    supererogatorymorally praiseworthy and/or good,
    but not (contra Singer) obligatory.
  • It may be obligatory for individuals like us to
    make some substantial contribution towards famine
    relief and other causes, but not to the point of
    becoming like a Bengali refugee.
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)