Title: Is Failing to Give to Famine Relief Wrong?
1Is Failing to Give toFamine Relief Wrong?
Is Failing to Give toFamine Relief Wrong?
II
II
2John Arthur World Hunger and Moral Obligation
Arthurs Central Argument
Singers argument
- Ignores an important moral factor entitlement.
- Requires an overhauling of our moral code, which
is not required.
The General Principle
Singers General Principle (Arthur calls it the
greater moral evil rule) requires substantial
redistribution of wealth.
- If it is in out power to prevent something bad
from happening, without thereby sacrificing
anything of comparable moral importance, we
ought, morally, to do it. - Recall pond example The greater moral evil rule
thus seems a natural way of capturing why we
think it would be wrong not to help. (545)
3The General Principle
- Moral Equality We are attracted to the idea that
like amounts of suffering (or the opposite) are
of equal significance, regardless of who is
experiencing them Equality demands equal
consideration of interests as well as respect for
certain rights. (545) - If we fail to give to famine relief, instead
spending our money on a new car or fancy clothes,
we are giving special consideration to ourselves
or to our group, like a racist does. Equal
consideration leads naturally to the greater
moral evil rule. - There is, however, a flip-side to equality that
Singer ignores entitlement, which falls into two
broad categories.
4Forms of Entitlement (1) Rights
Thought Experiment 1 Where you have two eyes and
two kidneys, some other person is blind or has a
disease that is destroying her kidneys. You can
donate one of your eyes or one of your kidneys,
to restore her sight, or extend her life. Of
course, you will, in doing so, lose something
either depth perception, or, possibly, some life
expectancy. Thought Experiment 2 There is some
person who, we can imagine, will be
psychologically harmed by your not granting
sexual favors to them. Of course, you do not want
to grant such sexual favors, and you will be, in
some less strong way, harmed by granting them.
5Forms of Entitlement (1) Rights (contd)
- According to the General Principle, to be
justified in refusing, you must show that the
unpleasantness you would experience is of equal
importance to the harm you are preventing.
Otherwise, you must consent. - If anything is clear, however, it is that our
code does not require such heroism you are
entitled to keep your second eye and kidney and
not bestow sexual favors on anyone who may be
harmed without them. (546) - That its your body, and you have a right to it,
outweighs any duty you have to help. - (Recall discussion on a womans right to her body
versus her duty to the fetus.)
6Forms of Entitlement (1) Rights (contd)
Moral rights are divided into two categories
- Negative Rights rights of noninterference.
- The right to life, property rights, the right to
privacy, etc. - Negative rights are natural, depending on what
you are.
- Positive Rights rights of recipience.
- Your legal wards have a right to be fed, clothed,
and housed. - Contractual rights, say, in business dealings,
include the right not to be left holding the bag. - Positive rights are not natural they arise
because others have promised, agreed, or
contracted to give you something.
7Forms of Entitlement (1) Rights (contd)
A duty to help a stranger in need is not the
result of a right he has.
- Such a right would be positive, but you have made
no promises nor entered into any contract with
this person, so no such right exists. - Where the wards of a lifeguard, for instance,
have a right to the lifeguards help, they do not
have the same right to help from bystanders. - Bystanders may act cruelly in not helping a
drowning child, but they do not thereby violate
anyones rights. - We are entitled to invoke our own rights as
justification for not giving to distant strangers
or when the cost to us is substantial (an eye or
a kidney, for example).
8Forms of Entitlement (2) Deserts
The farmer who grows his good deserves it because
he earned it through his hard work.
- A farmers deserts may be outweighed by the needs
of his neighbors, but this is not to say that his
deserts have no moral weight. - Negative Deserts A Nazi war criminal deserves
punishment, and that will be a reason to send him
to jail. But if nobody will be deterred by his
suffering, or if he is old and harmless, this may
weigh against his punishment. But this doesnt
mean that he doesnt still deserve punishment.
9Our Moral Code
Where our moral code tends to look to the future
(toward consequences), entitlements look to the
past
- Whether we have rights to our money, property,
eyes, etc., depends on how we came to acquire
them. - Our common moral code requires that we ignore
neither consequences nor entitlements. - Rights and deserts should not be discounted when
considering the morality of our actions.
Are such values as rights and entitlements
outweighed by more fundamental values, such as
fairness, justice, or respect for others?
- There seems no easy way to compare these factors.
10Our Moral Code (contd)
Above all else, the moral code that it is
rational for us to support must be
practicali.e., it must work.
- As such, it must gain the support of (almost)
everyone. - An ideal code cannot assume people are more
unselfish than we are Rules that would work
only for angels are not the ones it is rational
to support for humans. (547) - An ideal code cannot assume we are more objective
than we are. - An ideal code cannot assume that we have perfect
knowledge.
11Our Moral Code (contd)
A reasonable moral code, then, would require
people to help when there is no substantial cost
to themselveswhere helping would not mean
significant reduction in a persons current level
of happiness.
- Getting ones pants muddy would likely not result
in significant reduction in ones happiness. - Giving up ones savings, ones eye, or ones
kidney would likely result in significant
reduction in ones happiness. - An ideal moral code would probably not look too
much different from our current working code.
12Michael Slote Famine, Affluence, and Empathy
Slotes Virtue Ethics
Virtue Ethics of caring built on the tradition of
18th Century sentimentalism.
- Caring is an overall attitude or motivational
state. - Roughly, an ethics of caring holds that an act is
morally right or permissible if it doesnt
exhibit a lack of caring (not mere neutrality),
and wrong if it does. - When I speak of acts exhibiting a caring
attitude or one inconsistent with caring, the
caring I am speaking of includes attitudes toward
distant and personally-unknown others. (548)
13Slotes Virtue Ethics (contd)
- An ethics of caring will hold that it is
virtuous to be more concerned about near and dear
than about strangers or those one knows about
merely by description but it will also insist
that an ideally or virtuously caring individual
will be substantially concerned about people who
are distant from her. (549) - That we have special or stronger moral
obligations to those who are (physically or
sentimentally) closer to us is commonsensically
appealing.
14Slotes Virtue Ethics (contd)
Rather than sympathy (the word Hume uses in
forming his sentimentalist theory, which today
means, roughly, a favorable attitude toward
someone), Slote is concerned with empathy (the
state or process in which one takes on the
feelings of another).
- Question Is the development of empathy necessary
to ones development of altruistic concern for
others? - Psychology, generally, hypothesizes that caring
works via empathy, and that morally good caring
can be specified in relation to the development
of human empathy.
15Slotes Virtue Ethics (contd)
If we believe that empathy has moral force or
relevance, then we can argue that
- Since it is easier to empathize with another
adult human than with a squidge - It is as such morally worse to harm an adult
human than to do the same to a squidge. - That is, we can say that an action is right or
wrong depending on whether or not such actions
reflect a deficiency of normally or fully-capable
caring motivation. - It would then (other things being equal) be
morally worse to prefer a fetus or embryo to a
born human being because such a preference runs
counter to the flow of developed human empathy
(550) - Contra Singer, then, a failure to save the life
of a distant child (by making a charitable
donation) is not as morally bad as failing to
save the life of a child drowning in front of
you.
16Empathy and Spatial Distance
Singer holds that spatial distance simply cannot
be morally relevant to our obligations to aid
others.
- Empathy gives us a firmer basis than distance for
distinguishing the strength of our obligations in
the cases Singer compares. - Spatial distance and (decreasing) empathy do, in
fact, correlate in a wide variety of cases. - Such a view can not only help to explain why
failing to help in the drowning case seems worse
than a failure to give to famine relief, but it
can also justify that ordinary moral intuition.
17Empathy and Spatial Distance (contd)
- Turning away from someone we see who is in need
seems worse than ignoring someone whom one knows
only by description is in need.
- Our empathic capacities respond to immediacy.
- What makes failing to give aid in the former case
more objectionable than failing to give aid in
the latter is, Slote claims, a failure in ones
empathic response to someone whose need one
directly perceives.
18Empathy and Temporal Distance
The same principle applies to temporal distance
- Given the choice, we would typically feel more
compelled to spend money to aid miners trapped in
a cave-in than to spend that money on shoring up
other mines to save a greater number of lives in
the future. - The danger in the former case engages our
empathic juices in a way that the danger in the
latter case does not the danger is not as
immediate.
In the cases of the miners and of Singers
drowning child vs. famine relief cases, our
negative moral responses to ones choosing to
help in the distant cases rather than the
(proximally or temporally) immediate cases is
explained by some lack of (normal) human empathy
on the part of the agent.
19Obligations and Sacrifice
Current social-psychological research supports
the idea that humans have a substantial capacity
for empathy and for altruistic concerns based on
empathy.
- We are not morally obligated to sacrifice most of
our time and money to aid others, because a
failure to do so doesnt evince an absence of
normal or fully-developed human empathy. - Such a sacrifice would be morally
supererogatorymorally praiseworthy and/or good,
but not (contra Singer) obligatory. - It may be obligatory for individuals like us to
make some substantial contribution towards famine
relief and other causes, but not to the point of
becoming like a Bengali refugee.