Title: VOTING TO ELECT A SINGLE CANDIDATE
1VOTING TO ELECT A SINGLE CANDIDATE
2Single-Winner Elections
- Election of a unitary executive office.
- Election of a representative from a single-member
district SMD - Election of slate Presidential electors running
on a (winner-take-all) general ticket/slate.
3Binary Voting
- Just two options (so one winner and just one
loser) - Single-winner elections with just two candidates
- straight fight British terminology
- Yes/No voting
- referendums
- parliamentary voting
4Kenneth Mays Theorem
- Choices for voters in straight fight between A
and B - vote for A
- vote for B
- abstain (if indifferent)
- Possible voting outcomes
- A is the winner
- B is the winner
- deadlock (no winner, hung electorate)
5Mays Conditions (Reformulated)
- Anonymity (of voters)
- Neutrality (between options A and B)
- Resoluteness (no deadlock)
- Preliminary Theorem No voting system can be
simultaneously Anonymous, Neutral, and Resolute. - All voting systems considered here are Anonymous
and Neutral.
6Mays Conditions (cont.)
- Almost Resoluteness any deadlock is broken by
any voter changing his vote. - Non-Negative Responsiveness votes dont count
negatively. - Mays Theorem Anonymity Neutrality Almost
Resoluteness Non-Negative Responsiveness ltgt
Simple (Relative) Majority Rule
7Strategyproofness
- Moreover, in a straight fight SMR is
strategyproof - That is, no voter can ever improve the outcome
with respect to his or her true preferences by
misreporting those preferences on a ballot. - Voters will never regret voting sincerely or
honestly. - Sincere voting is Nash Equilibrium.
- However, in this respect SMR is not unusual in
fact all non-negatively responsive voting systems
are strategy-proof in a straight fight.
8Three or More Candidates
- Once the number k of options/candidates exceeds
two, all sorts of problems arise. - Different (reasonable looking) voting
procedures, all satisfying May-like conditions
and equivalent to SMR in a straight fight, may
produce different winners from the same
preference profile. - No voting procedure is strategyproof.
- No voting procedure is spoilerproof.
- This is essentially Arrows Theorem.
- One rationale for a two-party system is that it
typically produces (something very close to)
straight fights and therefore precludes these
problems.
9Preference Profiles
- With more than two candidates (k gt 2), voters
preferences cannot be specified simply by listing
their most preferred (top-ranked) candidates
rather we must specify voters full preference
ordering over all candidates (like the ice cream
flavors). - A collection of preference orderings, one for
each voter is called a preference profile. - We use British party labels to identify three
candidates Labour, Liberal, and Conservative
one of whom is to be elected. While there are
six possible orderings of three candidates, we
first consider a simple profile in which only
three of these orderings are present and we
indicate the popularity of each. - We assume all have strict orderings (no
indifference) and there are no ties.
10Preference Profile 1
- of voters 46 20 34
- 1st pref. Labour Liberal Conserv.
- 2nd pref. Liberal Conserv. Liberal
- 3rd pref. Conserv. Labour Labour
- Simple Plurality Voting (SPV) first past the
post or FPTP - Plurality Ranking
- Candidates Votes Received ( First Preferences)
- Labour 46 votes (winner)
- Conservative 34 votes
- Liberal 20 votes
- Assuming sincere voting, SPV takes account of
first preferences only.
11Plurality vs. Majority Winner
- Given a preference profile with k gt 2
- A plurality winner is a candidate who has more
first preferences than any other candidate. - A plurality winner always exists in the absence
of ties. - A majority winner is a candidate who is the first
preference of a majority of voters. - Every majority winner is also a plurality winner,
but the reverse is not true. - There may not be a majority winner.
12Plurality Plus Runoff (or Instant Runoff Voting
IRV)
- If there is no majority winner, there is a runoff
between the top two candidates in the plurality
ordering. - Under IRV, Profile 1 would produce a runoff
between Labour and Conservative first and second
in the plurality ranking, which Conservative
would win.
13Approval Voting
- Voters can vote for (approve of) more than one
candidate. - The candidate with the most approval wins.
- Approval voting outcomes are indeterminate.
Presumably a voter casts an approval vote for A
and not for B only if the voters preference
ordering ranks A over B no skipping. - In Profile 1
- Labour wins if all voters cast only one vote.
- Conservative wins if only voters in the middle
bloc cast two votes - Liberal wins if all voters in the right bloc cast
two votes or if all voters cast two votes. - S. Brams and P. Fishburn, Approval Voting
14Borda Point Voting
- Votes rank the candidates on the ballot.
- Candidates are awarded three points for each
ballot on which they are ranked first, two points
for each ballot on which they are ranked second,
and one point for each ballot on which they are
ranked third (if k 3). - In general, m points, m-1 points, etc., when
there are m candidates. - Borda Ranking for Profile 1
- Liberal 220 points (winner)
- Labour 192 points
- Conservative 188 points
15Condorcet Voting
- Votes rank the candidates on the ballot.
- Examine all pairs of candidates and see who wins
each straight fight. - For Profile 1
- Liberal vs. Conservative Liberal wins by 66-34
- Conservative vs. Labour Conservative wins by
54-46 - Liberal vs. Labour Liberal wins by 54-46
- Assemble the Majority (or Condorcet) Ranking
- 1st pref. Liberal (Condorcet Winner)
- 2nd pref. Conservative
- 3rd pref. Labour (Condorcet Loser)
- Precisely opposite of Plurality Ranking (based on
1st prefs. only) and different from Borda Ranking
(also based on full rankings)
16Condorcet Winners
- A Condorcet winner is a candidate who can beat
every other candidate in a straight fight. - A Condorcet loser is a candidate who is beaten by
every other candidate in a straight fight. - A majority winner is always a Condorcet winner,
but the reverse is not true. - A plurality winner may not be a Condorcet winner.
- A Condorcet winner may not be a plurality winner.
- Indeed, a Condorcet winner may have the fewest
first preferences (e.g., Liberal in Profile 1).
17Condorcet Voting (cont.)
- Moreover, Condorcet Voting appears to be
- Strategyproof, because it is built on Simple
Majority Rule, which is strategyproof and - Spoilerproof, because (for example), regard-less
of whether Nader is a candidate or not, Bush is
the Condorcet winner only if he beats Gore in a
straight fight. - So what about Arrows Theorem?
18Problem There may be no Condorcet Winner
- This assertion seems puzzling because every
ranking has a highest ranked element. - But there may be no Majority Ranking.
19Preference Profile 2
- of voters 46 20 34
- 1st pref. Labour Liberal Conserv.
- 2nd pref. Liberal Conserv. Labour
- 3rd pref. Conserv. Labour Liberal
- First preferences are unchanged from Profile 1,
so the plurality winner is unchanged. - As before, there is no majority winner.
- Conservative remains the Plurality Runoff winner.
- Labour becomes the Borda point winner.
- Approval voting remains indeterminate.
20Cyclical Majorities
- Re-examine the straight fights
- Liberal vs. Conservative Liberal wins by 66-34
- Conservative vs. Labour Conservative wins by
54-46 - Labour vs. Liberal Labour wins by 80-20
- There is no majority ranking, no Condorcet
Winner, and no Condorcet Loser. - Instead we have a cyclical majority that behaves
like the even stranger ice cream customer. - In general, Condorcet Winners may not exist and
Condorcet Voting is not a proper voting system,
so Arrows Theorem stands. -
21Preference Profile 3
- of voters 35
33 32 - 1st pref. B C D
- 2nd pref. A A A
- 3rd pref. C D B
- 4th pref. D B C
- Example of a socially divided society (e.g.,
Shiites, Sunnis, and Kurds in Iraq) Candidate A
is the alliance (cross-community) candidate. - Candidate A is the Condorcet Winner even though A
has no first preferences. - Candidate A is the Condorcet Winner even though
the is a majority cycle among the other
candidates. - Side point If A, B, C, and D are parties, the
Alliance Party A wins no seats under list-PR. -
22Condorcet Consistency
- A voting rule is Condorcet consistent if, given
sincere voting, it always selects the Condorcet
winner when one exists. - Previous examples showed that, given Profile 1,
Liberal may fail to win under each of the other
voting rules discussed, so none of them is
Condorcet consistent. - Condorcet voting is obviously Condorcet
consistent but, since it is does not always
select a winner, it cannot be deemed a
full-fledged voting rule.
23Parliamentary (Yes/No) Voting
- There are options A, B, C, D, .
- Voting is by a sequence of binary votes taken in
some fixed order (say alphabetical) - (1) A vs. B
- (2) winner of (1) vs. C
- (3) and so forth
- If there is a Condorcet Winner, it can never be
knocked out, so CW wins regardless of the voting
order. - If there is a majority cycle and no CW, winner is
determined by the voting order (later entry is
advantageous).
24Single-Peaked Preferences
- To say that majority cycles may exist is not to
say that they typically are present. - Indeed, if preferences are structured in a simple
way by ideology (or otherwise), cycles cannot
occur. - In British politics, the three major parties are
generally perceived to be ideologically ranked
from left to right in the following manner - More leftwing Labour
- Relatively centrist Liberal
- More rightwing Conservative
25Single-Peaked Preferences (cont.)
- Admissible Orderings Inadmissible
- Leftwingers Centrists
Rightwingers Orderings - 1st pref. Lab Lib Lib Con Con Lab
- 2nd pref. Lib Lab Con Lib Lab Con
- 3rd pref. Con Con Lab Lab Lib Lib
- Why the name single-peaked?
- In diagrams below, L leftist, C centrist, and
R rightist
26Single-Peaked Preferences (cont.)
- Note the strength of the centrist (Liberal)
candidate in the admissible orderings. - While it may be that few voters most prefer the
centrist, no one likes the centrist least. - The centrist candidate must be the Condorcet
Winner unless a majority of voters have the
leftwing or rightwing ordering. - In other words, the centrist candidate fails to
be the Condorcet Winner only if one of the
extreme candidates is a majority winner. - In the general case, if all voters can be ranked
from most leftwing to most rightwing with respect
to their first preferences, - no cyclical majority occurs
- some position on the ideological spectrum is the
Condorcet Winner and - that CW position corresponds to the first
preference of the median voter, such that no more
than half the voters are more leftwing and no
more than half are more rightwing (Duncan Black,
Theory of Committees and Elections. - The Hotelling-Downs theory of electoral
competition (to be discussed later) states that
two competing vote-seeking parties or candidates
achieve equilibrium only when both adopt the
position that corresponds to the first preference
of the median voter.
27Strategic Voting under Plurality Rule
- Any voting rule with three or more candidates may
give some voters incentives to vote otherwise
than sincerely. - Consider Profile 1 again.
- of voters 46 20 34
- 1st pref. Labour Liberal Conserv.
- 2nd pref. Liberal Conserv. Liberal
- 3rd pref. Conserv. Labour Labour
- Labour wins under Plurality Voting if voters are
sincere. - But a majority of 54 voters prefer both other
candidates to Labour. - If they all vote for the same other candidate,
that candidate wins, an outcome they all prefer
to a Labour victory. - But doing this requires some voters among the 54
to vote insincerely, i.e., for their second
preferences. - Thus simple Plurality Voting can encourage what
the British call tactical voting and most
political scientists call strategic voting, i.e.,
non-sincere voting.
28Strategic Voting under Plurality Rule (cont.)
- But how will the 54 voter majority coordinate
their votes? Will they all vote for Liberal or
for Conservative? - While all 54 voters prefer to see Labour
defeated, they disagree as to how to defeat him,
i.e., by voting Conservative or by voting
Liberal. - It is generally believed that, in practice,
tactical voting in Britain mostly leads Liberal
supporters to shift their votes tactically to
their second-preference (Labour or Conservative)
candidate, because they typically observe
pre-election polls showing Liberal trailing well
behind both other candidates, and they therefore
conclude that a Liberal vote is wasted and that
they should vote for the one of the two leading
(non-Liberal) candidates that they prefer. - This can happen even though Liberal is the
Condorcet winner, reflecting the fact that polls
(almost always) ask only about first preferences
and Liberal's great strength lies in second
preferences. - If Liberal supporters find Labour and
Conservative to be equally objectionable, they
have no incentive to vote tactically. - If pre-election polls show something close to a
tie for second place (or a three-way tie),
tactical voting becomes far more conjectural.
29Strategic Voting under Runoff or IRV
- Preference Profile 1
- of voters 46 20 34
- 1st pref. Labour Liberal Conserv.
- 2nd pref. Liberal Conserv. Liberal
- 3rd pref. Conserv. Labour Labour
- Under Plurality Runoff or IRV, the 46 voters
who most prefer Labour would do better by ranking
Liberal first, as this assures a Liberal victory
(without a runoff), which outcome they prefer to
the Conservative victory that otherwise results.
- Moreover, other voters have no countermoves
available. No strategic vote is available to 34
voters whose first preference is Conservative,
and the 20 voters whose first preference is
Liberal are already getting their first
prefer-ence.
30Strategic Voting Under Borda Point Voting
- Given Profile 1, no voters can change their Borda
score ballots in a way that improves the outcome
for them. - Profile 2
- of voters 46 20 34
- 1st pref. Labour Liberal Conserv.
- 2nd pref. Liberal Conserv. Labour
- 3rd pref. Conserv. Labour Liberal
- Given Profile 2, if the bloc of 20 ranks
Conservative first and the bloc of 34 ranks
Labour third, then Conservative gets the most
Borda points (208 vs. 200 for Liberal and 192 for
Labour), an outcome all 54 such voters prefer to
victory by the sincere Borda winner Labour.
31Strategic Voting Under Borda (cont.)
- Preference Profile 3 4 in Handout
- 46 54
- 1st pref. Labour Conservative
- 2nd pref. Liberal Labour
- 3rd pref. Conservative Liberal
- Labour wins if voting is sincere (demonstrating
that Borda Point Voting can deny victory to a
majority winner). - But the 54 Conservative-preferring voters can
elect Conservative if they (insincerely) push
Labour down to third place on their ballots. - In turn, the 46 Labour-preferring voters can
counteract this by pushing Liberal to the top of
their ballots (the resulting Liberal victory
being preferable to Conservative). - Note that if strategic manipulation stops at this
point (though it need not), Liberal is elected
even though everyone prefers Labor to Liberal. - And things can get worse.
32Borda Strategy Turkey Raising
- There are three candidates a more or less
reasonable Democrat D, a more or less reasonable
Republican R, and a real turkey T. Everyone
one ranks T last, except two deranged T
supporters. The profile is - 50 voters 48 voters 1 voter 1
voter - D R T T
- R D D R
- T T R D
- If everyone votes sincerely, the Borda Point
totals are D249, R247, and T104. - Anticipating this defeat, Republican voters
caucus and notice an interesting feature of Borda
Point Voting it can pay voters to engage in
turkey raising, i.e., to strategically raise
the turkey in their ballot rankings, so as to
push the rival serious candidate down in their
rankings and increase the point spread between
the two. -
33Turkey Raising (cont.)
- Suppose the Republicans strategically modify all
their ballots so as to produce the following
ballot profile - 50 voters 48 voters 1 voter 1
voter - D R T T
- R T D R
- T D R D
- The point totals would then be D201, R247, and
T152. - Democrats also notice this feature of Borda
Voting and, concerned that Republicans may engage
in turkey raising, they engage in some turkey
raising of their own in order to counteract the
anticipated Republican stratagem. So the final
ballot profile is - 50 voters 48 voters 1 voter 1
voter - D R T T
- T T D R
- R D R D
- The final point scores are D 201, R 197, and
T 202. May the best turkey win!
34Spoiler Effects
- A sincere electorate using Plurality Voting may
behave exactly the confused ice cream customer. - Preference Profile 1
- of voters 46 20 34
- 1st pref. Labour Liberal Conserv.
- 2nd pref. Liberal Conserv. Liberal
- 3rd pref. Conserv. Labour Labour
- Conservative beats Labour in a straight fight,
but Labour wins if Liberal enters the election.
So Liberal is a spoiler to Conservative. - Likewise, Liberal beats Labour in a straight
fight, but Labour wins if Conservative enters the
election. So Conservative is also a spoiler to
Liberal. - Note that the effect of the spoilers entry is to
elect the last preference of the spoilers
supporters, so the spoilers entry is
self-defeating. - Note that, in this profile, Labour cannot be a
spoiler, because if Labour enters what had been a
Liberal-Conservative straight fight, Labour wins.
35Spoiler Effects (cont.)
- Spoiler effects may be mitigated by strategic
voting. - Duvergers Law Single-Winner elections with
Simple Plurality Voting tend to produce two-party
systems and straight fights Strategic voting to
mitigate spoiler effects is one factor that
drives Duvergers Law. - Dont waste your vote on a hopeless third
candidate. - Candidate entry deterrence is the other,
probably more important, factor that drives
Duvergers Law. - Dont run as a third candidate, you will spoil
the chances of the preferable of the two major
candidates. - Multi-Winner elections no elected executives
with any variant of Proportional Representation
PR sustains multiparty systems. Other half of
Duvergers Law
36Spoiler Effects under IRV
- Plurality Runoff/IRV is sometimes advocated on
the grounds that it precludes the spoiler effects
that characterize Simple Plurality. - Plurality Runoff/IRV is an improvement over
Simple Plurality in this respect. - Under IRV, a single third candidate (such as
Nader) with little first-preference support
cannot act as a spoiler in what is essentially a
straight fight between two major candidates,
because the runoff will become precisely that
straight fight. - However, if there are many candidates and/or
first preferences are dispersed, Plurality
Runoff/IRV is subject to spoiler effects.
37Two Variants of IRV
- There are (at least) variants of IRV.
- They are equivalent if there are just three
candidates but are distinct (and may produce
different winners) if there are more than three
candidates. - The first variant mimics Plurality Runoff.
- If there is no majority winner, all candidates
except the leading and second-place candidate in
the plurality ranking are simultaneously
eliminated. - The ballots of all eliminated candidates are
trans-ferred to one or other surviving candidate
on the basis of lower preferences. - The surviving candidate with the most (original
plus transferred) ballots is elected. -
38Two Variants of IRV (cont.)
- The second variant is distinct from plurality
runoff. - If there is no majority winner, the candidate
with the fewest first preference ballots is
eliminated. - The ballots of the eliminated candidate are
trans-ferred to one of the surviving candidate on
the basis of second preferences. - If there is still no majority winner, the
surviving candi-date with the fewest (original
plus transferred) ballots is eliminated and the
ballots are transferred on the basis of second or
lower preferences. - And so forth until there is a majority winner
(which necessarily occurs once all candidates but
two have been eliminated.
39Two Variants of IRV (cont.)
- The second variant of IRV is also called the
Alternative Vote. - It is the single-winner special case of a
multi-winner voting system called the Single
Transferable Vote (STV). - STV is used in small multi-member districts
(MMDs). - It produces approximately proportional
representation of groups among the winners, even
if those groups are not political parties. - contrast with List-PR
- STV is used to elect
- the Irish Dail (Parliament)
- the Australian House of Representative
- the Cambridge MA City Council
40Spoiler effects under Plurality Runoff (and 1st
IRV variant)
- When there are many candidates, the Plurality
Runoff and the first variant of IRV are subject
to spoiler effects in precisely the same manner
as Simple Plurality Voting, with respect to the
question of which two candidates will survive
into the runoff. - This is illustrated by the 2002 French
Presidential election (Two Round or Plurality
Runoff).
41- Left splinter candidates spoiled Jospins
chance to get into the second round runoff
against Chirac. - However, if the second AV variant of IRV had
been in used - ballots for left splinter candidates would have
(presumably) transferred to Jospin - few ballot would have transferred to Le Pen and
- Jospin would have gotten into the runoff and
might have won.
42Would Runoff/IRV Lead to a Proliferation of
Presidential Candidates?
43Spoiler Effects under 2nd IRV Variant (AV)
- However, spoiler effects also exist under the
second IRV variant. This is illustrated by
Preference Profile 1 with just three candidates
(in which case the two variants are equivalent) - of voters 46 20 34
- 1st pref. Labour Liberal Conserv.
- 2nd pref. Liberal Conserv. Liberal
- 3rd pref. Conserv. Labour Labour
- Liberal wins a straight fight with Conservative,
but Liberal does not even make it into the runoff
if Labour enters the field. So Labour is a
spoiler to Liberal under IRV. - This is not a distinctive flaw in Plurality
Runoff (or IRV) because, as previously noted, the
problem is unavoid-able with three or more
candidates.
44Negative Responsiveness under Plurality Runoff
(or IRV)
- Plurality Runoff (or IRV) has another flaw that
is distinctive (and avoidable). - Plurality Runoff (or IRV) can respond negatively
when a candidates position in a preference (or
ballot) profile becomes more favorable put
otherwise, it can punish a candidate for gaining
more support. - This sometimes called monotonicity failure.
- It is a violation of Mays Non-Negative
Responsive-ness condition
45Negative Responsiveness under Plurality Runoff or
IRV (cont.)
- Original Preference Profile 4
Revised Preference Profile 4 - 35 10 25 30
35 10 25 30 - A B B
C A A B C - B A C A B
B C A - C C A B
C C A B - Prior to the election, a poll indicates that
voting intentions those shown in Original
Preference Profile 4. Candidate A is pleased
with this information, because it projects that A
and B will go into the runoff, which A will win. - However, A doesnt want to take any chances and
urges his supporters to go out and drum up still
more support for A. As supporters are
successful, transforming the original profile
into the revised profile, in which 10 voters who
previously preferred B to A now prefer A to B.
(No other preferences have changed.) - As a result of this successful campaign, A loses
the election.
46IRV and the No Show Paradox
- Here is a related peculiarity of Plurality
Runoff or IRV. - Preference Profile 5
- 5 6 4 2 B C A A C B B B
A A C C - The preference profile is as shown above, but the
two individuals with the bracketed preference
orderings fail to vote. - The election outcome is determined by the
remaining 15 voters. Candidates B and C are
paired in a runoff, which B wins. - This is somewhat disappointing for the two
individuals who failed to vote, in that their
second preference won. - They regret their failure to get to the polls and
wonder whether their first preference A might
have won if they had not failed to vote. - It can be checked that, if they had gotten to the
polls and voted according to their preferences, C
would have won (so the outcome would have been
worse, not better, for them).
47Clone Candidates
- When I was 12 years old I was nominated to be
treasurer of my class at school. A girl named
Michelle was also nominated. I relished the
prospect of being treasurer, so I made a quick
calculation and nomi-nated Michelles best
friend, Charlotte. In the ensuing election, I
received 13 votes, Michelle received 12, and
Charlotte received 11, so I became treasurer.
T.N. Tideman - Consider the following preference profile, in
which a Republican minority is united behind a
single candidate R but the Democratic majority is
split between the two clone candidates D1 and
D2. - Preference Profile 6
- Democrats Republicans
- 35 25 25 15
- D1 D2 R R
- D2 D1 D1 D2
- R R D2 D1
48Clone Candidates (cont.)
- Clones are candidates who very similar in terms
of their ideology, issue positions, etc. and are
therefore adjacent in all voters preference
rankings. - Simple Plurality is notorious for penalizing
clone candi-dates. - In this case, the Republican candidate wins due
to the Demo-cratic split, even though R is the
Condorcet loser and would be beaten by both D1
and D2 in straight fights. - D1 and D2 are spoilers against each other.
- It is precisely the expectation of such outcomes
under Simple Plurality voting that leads to party
formation and party discipline. - The Democrats and the girls have a huge
incentive to hold a prior nominating convention
or primary to choose between D1 and D2 and then
send just one of the two clones forward against
the Republican. - Given the preference profile above, D1 would win
the nomination and then the general election.
49 Plurality Runoff or IRV and Clones
- Are there voting rules that can reduce,
eliminate, or even reverse the self-defeating
effect of run-ning clone candidates? - Given Profile 6, Plurality Runoff (instant or
other-wise) solves the clone problem. - The first-round election functions as the
(Democratic) primary (except that Republicans
also vote in this primary). - The runoff functions as the general election in
which the Democratic majority gets its way. - If there are four or more candidates, Plurality
Runoff or IRV does not treat clones so well
and, as we have seen, it is subject to other
problems in addition.
50Approval Voting and Clones
- Brams and Fishburn advocate Approval Voting as a
desirable a voting rule that (among other things)
does not punish clones. - In Profile 6, presumably (almost all) Democrats
would vote for both D1 and D2, one of whom would
be elected. - By not penalizing clones, AV does not encourage
party formation or party unity. - For this reason, many political scientists are
more inclined to support AV for primary elections
and non-partisan elections than for partisan
general elections.
51Double-Vote List-PR and Clones
- A variation of one type of party-list PR
(Propor-tional Representation) system is another
voting method that does not penalize clones who
have the same party affiliation. - In a district that elects m candidates, each
voter votes for m candidate, but these vote
counts in two ways - first, as a party vote to determine which party
wins the election and - second, as a candidate vote to determine which
candidate(s) of the winning party is elected. In
the profile above (with m 1), D1 would be
elected.
52Borda Point Voting and Clones
- Perhaps surprisingly, Borda Point Voting actually
rewards the running of clones. - Suppose that there are two candidates and
Republicans are again in the minority. - Preference Profile 7A
- 60 voters 40 voters
- D R1
- R1 D
- With just two candidates, the Borda point rule is
identical to Plurality Voting (and SMR), so the
Republican candidate R1 loses.
53Borda Point Voting and Clones (cont.)
- But, if Borda Voting is in use, the Republicans
can reverse this outcome by nominating an
additional clone candidate R2 whom everyone sees
as identical to R1 with respect to issues and
ideology but inferior with respect to (lets say)
personal qualities. - Preference Profile 8A
- 60 voters 40 voters
- D R1
- R1 R2
- R2 D
- Democrats can counteract this Republican
stratagem by strategi-cally ranking R2 above R1. - Alternatively, they can counteract it by running
their own clone. - Borda voting is highly susceptible to strategic
maneuvers of this sort (which, moreover, have the
effect of expanding the candidate field rather
than winnowing it down in the manner of Plurality
Rule). - Also recall turkey raising under Borda
54Overall Conclusion
- Two-candidate elections (straight fights) are
clean and simple. - Elections with three or more candidates are
complex and inevitably quirky.