Issues in Philosophy - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 57
About This Presentation
Title:

Issues in Philosophy

Description:

... as of greater aesthetic value than Girls Aloud's The Promise. ... Some people might get pleasure from Girls Aloud and find Bach to be 'just noise' ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:43
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 58
Provided by: guylon
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: Issues in Philosophy


1
Issues in Philosophy
  • Guy Longworth
  • g.longworth_at_mac.com

2
On the Standard of Taste
  • Humes essay is superficially straightforward,
    but raises questions of interpretation
  • What problem is Hume engaging with?
  • What exactly is Humes view?
  • How does Hume argue for his view?

3
On the Standard of Taste
  • Three guides to interpretation
  • What the author says here.
  • What the author says elsewhere.
  • The principle of charity (the Plato no dummy
    principle).

4
On the Standard of Taste
  • Humes aims
  • To argue that our aesthetic responses are not
    immediate responses to objective value.
  • To specify the nature of our aesthetic responses.
  • To explain how the account in (II) can be
    consistent with the degree of objectivity that we
    take aesthetic value to possess.

5
On the Standard of Taste
  • The basic puzzle
  • We can only give an account of the ordinary
    phenomenology of aesthetic response if we accept
    that aesthetic response is a matter of sentiment
    (feeling), so subjective.
  • (B) Aesthetic response can track aesthetic value
    well or badly (some works are better than others
    and the responses of some critics are better than
    the responses of others), so objective.

6
On the Standard of Taste
  • (A) and (B) seem to be in tension if the
    aesthetic value of a work is a matter solely of
    how it makes you feel (your sentimental
    response), how can there be an objective ranking
    of works, a ranking that your responses might
    fail to track?

7
On the Standard of Taste
  • Two immediate questions
  • Q1. Why does Hume think that aesthetic response
    is a matter of sentiment, rather than immediate
    response to objective aesthetic value?
  • Q2. Why does Hume think that aesthetic value is
    an objective feature (or anyway more objective
    than individual sentimental response)?

8
On the Standard of Taste
  • In effect, Hume deploys an argument from
    queerness
  • (QU1) It is an obvious fact of life that peoples
    aesthetic responses vary (hence the saying its
    a matter of taste).
  • (QU2) Aesthetic response is intrinsically
    motivating (e.g. one wants to look more carefully
    at what one finds beautiful).

9
On the Standard of Taste
  • Weve already considered how such arguments might
    be developed and also how an objectivist about
    value might respond.
  • Humes response to the arguments is to take the
    view that aesthetic response is a matter of works
    of art causing a sentimental response, a feeling,
    in particular a specific sort of pleasure.

10
On the Standard of Taste
  • On this view, whether something is aesthetically
    valuable is in the first instance a matter of
    whether it causes in us a specific form of
    pleasure.
  • Hence, aesthetic value is determined by
    subjective features of appreciators, their
    sentimental responses to artworks.

11
On the Standard of Taste
  • This addresses both elements of Humes argument
    from queerness
  • (QU1) It is an obvious fact of life that peoples
    aesthetic responses vary (hence the saying its
    a matter of taste).
  • Since aesthetic responses are sentimental
    responses, rather than judgmental responses to
    objective features of artworks, and since
    sentimental responses can vary, (QU1) is a
    natural upshot of the account.

12
On the Standard of Taste
  • This addresses both elements of Humes argument
    from queerness
  • (QU2) Aesthetic response is intrinsically
    motivating (e.g. one wants to look more carefully
    at what one finds beautiful).
  • According to Hume, the feeling of pleasure is
    intrinsically motivating (as the feeling of pain
    is intrinsically de-motivating). Hence, the
    account in terms of sentiments has a ready
    explanation of aesthetic motivation.

13
On the Standard of Taste
  • According to Hume, then, we have some reasons for
    indentifying aesthetic value with either the
    power or disposition to elicit a specific type of
    feeling of pleasure or with the ground of that
    power.
  • The most straightforward version of this view
    would be one according to which
  • X is aesthetically valuable iff X is such as to
    elicit a specific type of feeling of pleasure in
    appreciators.

14
On the Standard of Taste
  • X is aesthetically valuable iff X is such as to
    elicit a specific type of feeling of pleasure in
    appreciators.
  • An upshot of the most straightforward view would
    be that anything that is apt to induce that type
    of pleasure in anyone will thereby count as
    aesthetically valuable.
  • An alternative would be
  • X is aesthetically valuable for Y iff X is such
    as to elicit a specific type of feeling of
    pleasure in Y.

15
On the Standard of Taste
  • X is aesthetically valuable for Y iff Y is such
    as to elicit a specific type of feeling of
    pleasure in Y.
  • A Humean reason for endorsing the second form of
    account would be that it fits better with the
    instrinsic motivating force of appreciation of
    aesthetic value.
  • For instance, I might recognise that X elicits
    aesthetic pleasure in you without that making me
    want to look but if I recognise that X elicits
    pleasure in me, that will be motivating for me.

16
On the Standard of Taste
  • An immediate question at this point is the
    following. The biconditional equivalences weve
    arrived at to this point simply indicate that
    aesthetic value and sentiment run in step. Which
    end, if any, of the biconditional has priority in
    explaining their running in step?

17
On the Standard of Taste
  • The question is a version of Eurythphros
    question (in Plato) about the Gods and ethical
    value
  • Do the Gods value X because X is good, or is X
    good because the Gods value it?
  • Our question
  • Do we value X aesthetically because X has
    aesthetic value, or is X aesthetically valuable
    because we value it?

18
On the Standard of Taste
  • We can distinguish three sorts of answer to this
    type of question
  • Detective (or evidential) Sentiment detects
    aesthetic value, so that aesthetic value is taken
    to explain sentimental response.
  • Constitutive Sentiment constitutes aesthetic
    value, so that sentimental response explains
    aesthetic value.
  • No priority Sentiment and aesthetic value
    constitute each other at the same time (or are
    jointly determined by something else.)

19
On the Standard of Taste
  • One question, then, is whether Hume takes
    sentimental response to detect or to constitute
    aesthetic value.
  • Its not straightforward to answer this question.
    Some of what Hume says fits a detective model and
    some of what he says fits a constitutive model.

20
On the Standard of Taste
  • To this point we have seen elements of Humes
    view according to which our aesthetic responses
    are not immediate responses to objective
    aesthetic value. Rather, something objective
    causes a sentimental response in use.g. a
    specific type of feeling of pleasureand we are
    motivated by our feeling.

21
On the Standard of Taste
  • The straightforward view we have derived to this
    point is one according to which there is no right
    or wrong for aesthetic responses. They are
    subjective episodes that simply happen to us, and
    are not to be assessed on the basis of anything
    external.

22
On the Standard of Taste
  • That gives us one side of the puzzle
  • (A) We can only give an account of the ordinary
    phenomenology of aesthetic response if we accept
    that aesthetic response is a matter of sentiment
    (feeling), so subjective.

23
On the Standard of Taste
  • But Hume thinks that we also ordinarily treat
    aesthetic responses as better or worse or
    rather, that we ordinarily rank the things to
    which we respondartworksas better or worse,
    despite the fact that they induce the same
    feelings of pleasure in at least some
    appreciators.

24
On the Standard of Taste
  • E.g., we might view Bachs Goldberg Variations as
    of greater aesthetic value than Girls Alouds
    The Promise.
  • And that is so even though
  • Both might give some people pleasure.
  • Some people might get pleasure from Girls Aloud
    and find Bach to be just noise.
  • Some people might get more pleasure from Girls
    Aloud than from Bach.

25
On the Standard of Taste
  • Despite the fact that there is wide variance in
    tasteso in sentimental response to artworkswe
    view aesthetic responses as better or worse
    depending upon how well they track the rankings
    we (or critics) accord artworks.
  • This suggests that we view our individual
    aesthetic responses detectively, as tracking or
    aiming to track an independently constituted
    aesthetic reality.

26
On the Standard of Taste
  • That gives us the second part of the puzzle
  • (B) Aesthetic response can track aesthetic value
    well or badly (some works are better than others
    and the responses of some critics are better than
    the responses of others), so objective.

27
On the Standard of Taste
  • Hume writes
  • It is natural for us to seek a Standard of
    Taste a rule, by which the various sentiments of
    men may be reconciled at least, a decision
    afforded, confirming one sentiment and condemning
    another.

28
On the Standard of Taste
  • The idea of reconciling sentiments is the idea
    of finding a way in which our differences can be
    ironed out, at least for certain purposes of
    aesthetic assessment.
  • The idea is that, as well as our individual
    sentimental responses to artworks, there is a
    standard against which those sentimental
    responses can be measured.

29
On the Standard of Taste
  • Another reading of Hume here has him seeking to
    reconcile, not merely our first order sentimental
    responses, but also our second order views about
    those responses, as in the two parts of the
    puzzle
  • We have reason to believe that aesthetic
    response is not simply a matter of taking in the
    layout of objective aesthetic reality. Otherwise,
    we cant explain variation or intrinsic
    motivation.
  • We have reason to believe that aesthetic
    response can be better or worse, and can sustain
    a ranking of artworks.

30
On the Standard of Taste
  • Three options at this point
  • (O1) Deny the first part of the puzzle actually,
    aesthetic judgments are immediate responses to
    objective aesthetic reality (and deal with Humes
    arguments to the contrary).
  • (O2) Deny the second part of the puzzle
    actually, our view that aesthetic responses can
    be better or worse, and that artworks can be
    ranked, is mistaken.
  • (O3) Compatibilism Deny that the two parts of
    the puzzle are really in tension and explain away
    the appearance that they are.

31
On the Standard of Taste
  • Its plausible that Hume seeks to take the
    compatibilist option.
  • Hume wants to explain how his form of
    subjectivism can be consistent with the degree of
    objectivism sustained by our ordinary view of
    aesthetic appreciation and its objects.

32
On the Standard of Taste
  • Humes account can be approached in two steps
  • Rules of composition general rules governing
    what has been universally found to please in all
    countries and in all ages.
  • True critics individuals whose aesthetic
    responses most closely track the grounds of
    optimal aesthetic response and so provide the
    best observational input to the rules of
    composition.

33
On the Standard of Taste
  • Rules of composition general rules governing
    what has been universally found to please in all
    countries and in all ages.
  • There are rules of optimal composition according
    to which artworks may be ranked.
  • These rules are supposed to be general, so that
    they apply to all artworks, though may be very
    specific so that two otherwise similar artworks
    might be subject to slightly different fully
    specified rules.

34
On the Standard of Taste
  • We dont have immediate access to these rules.
    Rather, like (other?) laws of nature, they must
    be discovered on the basis of observation and
    generalisation over the data provided by
    observation.

35
On the Standard of Taste
  • Crudely, one begins with a set of observations
    about what has induced the specific type of
    feeling of pleasure (perhaps with respect to some
    population or under some specified conditions)
    and on that basis put forward general principles
    that would deliver that pattern of verdicts.
  • We can then test the general principles against
    further sentimental responses and refine the
    principles on the basis of such testing.

36
On the Standard of Taste
  • To this point, then, determining the standard of
    taste is modeled closely on what we might think
    goes on in the natural sciences.
  • The central difference is that in the aesthetic
    case, elicitation of sentiment replaces
    observation (or elicitation of perceptual
    experience).

37
On the Standard of Taste
  • For at least two reasons, restrictions must be
    placed upon the input to this approach to
    determining rules of composition.

38
On the Standard of Taste
  • (R1) If no restrictions are imposed on which
    sentimental responses matter, then the wide
    variation in such responses may well be a barrier
    to the delineation of general principles.
  • (R2) The point of seeking the general principles
    was to sustain the ordinary ranking of aesthetic
    responses and (so?) artworks. Principles aiming
    to generalise over all responses are unlikely to
    achieve this.

39
On the Standard of Taste
  • What appears to be required at this point is some
    restriction on which sentimental responses are to
    count.
  • Either, we need to impose conditions on which of
    any individuals responses are to count, or on
    which individuals responses are to count, or
    both.

40
On the Standard of Taste
  • But now, if the rules of composition are just
    generalisations over this constrained set of
    sentimental responses, they dont appear to add
    anything. Their work might be done simply by
    appeal to the constrained set of responses (as
    long as the required constraints dont mention
    the general rules).
  • Moreover, it is plausible that the constraints on
    the set will mark for us a standard of taste
    sentimental responses meeting the constraints
    will be superior to those not meeting the
    constraints.

41
On the Standard of Taste
  • Returning to our first attempt at connecting
    sentimental response and aesthetic value, we
    might then consider the following adjustment. We
    might replace (I) with (II)
  • (I) X is aesthetically valuable iff X is such as
    to elicit a specific type of feeling of pleasure
    in appreciators.
  • (II) X is aesthetically valuable iff X is such as
    to elicit a specific type of feeling of pleasure
    in appreciators of type F in conditions C.

42
On the Standard of Taste
  • If we specify the F conditions on appreciators,
    and the C conditions on sentimental responses by
    those appreciators, in the right way, we will
    then be able to view sentimental responses
    meeting the conditions as supplying a standard of
    taste.
  • Responses in the right conditions will be
    sufficiently uniform that they can count as
    yielding optimal aesthetic judgments.
  • Responses outside those conditions will not
    yield such judgments and will be counted
    inferior.

43
On the Standard of Taste
  • This sort of approach seems to provide for
    compatibility between subjectivity and
    objectivity as follows.
  • Subjectivity is taken care of because the
    fundamental bases of aesthetic judgments are
    subjective responses, albeit responses subject to
    objective conditions.
  • Objectivity is taken care of because subjective
    responses are counted as better or worse
    depending upon the extent to which they meet
    objective conditions.

44
On the Standard of Taste
  • Notice that its important to this sort of
    approach that the conditions on optimal responses
    are specified without appeal to whether they
    correctly reflect an independently constituted
    (or anyway independently accessible) aesthetic
    reality.
  • Otherwise, the conditions wouldnt sustain the
    subjectivist side of Humes view, and so deal
    with that part of his puzzle.

45
On the Standard of Taste
  • Humes account of the true critic
  • True critics are those who have overcome five
    obstacles to optimal appreciation of works
  • Insufficient fineness of discrimination.
  • Insufficient practice with works of a given sort.
  • Insufficient comparative appreciation of works.
  • Insufficient application of means-end reasoning.
  • Prejudice.

46
On the Standard of Taste
  • Insufficient fineness of discrimination.
  • Proper appreciation of some works requires that
    one is able to distinguish amongst the parts of
    the work, and note fine details of the work.

47
On the Standard of Taste
  • (2) Insufficient practice with works of a given
    sort.
  • If the only works one has come across are
    paintings, one wont be in an optimal position to
    appreciate musical works.
  • If the only paintings one has come across are by
    Monet, one wont be in an optimal position to
    appreciate works by Vermeer.

48
On the Standard of Taste
  • (3) Insufficient comparative appreciation of
    works.
  • If one hasnt spent time comparing the strengths
    and weaknesses (or anyway features) of various
    works, one will not be in an optimal position to
    appreciate newly presented works.
  • Crucial here is the role of masterworks or
    masterpieces comparison with these enables the
    critic to fine tune their aesthetic responses.

49
On the Standard of Taste
  • (4) Insufficient application of means-end
    reasoning.
  • Some works are produced with particular aims in
    mind, for instance to provoke certain emotional
    responses or to reveal or emphasize certain
    features of a subject matter.
  • Critics who havent carefully assessed a work in
    line with its capacity to meet the ends of its
    production are not in the best position to
    appreciate such works.

50
On the Standard of Taste
  • (5) Prejudice.
  • Some responses to works are driven in part by
    prejudice, perhaps trivial (disliking the colour
    purple) or more substantive (homophobia).
  • Critics subject to prejudice of this sort and who
    allow the prejudice to affect their response to a
    work are not best placed to appreciate that work.

51
On the Standard of Taste
  • Question 1 Would someone be required to overcome
    all of those obstacles in order to become a true
    critic?
  • Question 2 Are there other obstacles that would
    need to be overcome in order to become a true
    critic?

52
On the Standard of Taste
  • Humes account
  • Hume holds that true critics supply the standard
    of taste, through their properly honed
    sentimental responses to works, perhaps
    influenced by hypotheses about the rules of
    composition that govern or elicit those responses.

53
On the Standard of Taste
  • Humes account
  • This is supposed to solve the puzzle in the
    following way
  • The ultimate aim of aesthetic appreciation is
    having valuable sentimental responsesexperiencing
    particular forms of pleasure.
  • We can rank works by appeal to their funding such
    responses amongst the true criticsresponses that
    are not an upshot of subjection to the five
    obstacles.

54
On the Standard of Taste
  • Some concerns
  • 1. Isnt Humes account circular? True critics
    will be identified in part by their engagement
    with, and proper responses to, masterworks. But
    only a true critic is in a position to identify
    the masterworks. So only a true critic is in a
    position to identify a true critic.

55
On the Standard of Taste
  • Some concerns
  • 2. Isnt Humes account too mechanistic to
    underwrite the normative aspects of aesthetic
    appreciation (i) the fact that we think some
    works are better or worse and some responses are
    more or less appropriate? (ii) the fact that
    aesthetic responses are improvable and not simple
    changeable? Isnt the account modeled too closely
    on the sense of taste to capture these aspects of
    aesthetic value?

56
On the Standard of Taste
  • Some concerns
  • 3. Isnt Hume too optimistic about the
    convergence of opinion of true critics? Wont
    there be just as much divergence here as amongst
    ordinary folk?

57
On the Standard of Taste
  • Some concerns
  • 4. Isnt Humes account incompatible with the way
    we are ordinarily motivated by others (critics)
    appreciation of aesthetic value? In particular,
    if all that critics reveal is a set of
    sentimental responses that we would have if we
    were true critics, why should we want those
    responses rather than the responses that we
    already have? Why should we go through the effort
    of attempting to approximate true-critic status,
    rather than sticking with our own sentimental
    responses?
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com