DAVID HUME 17111776 - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 60
About This Presentation
Title:

DAVID HUME 17111776

Description:

Judgements of taste have a foundation in things which we experience, and they ... cases, such as asserting that Stephen King is the equal of Shakespeare and ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:595
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 61
Provided by: JeffSt6
Category:
Tags: david | hume

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: DAVID HUME 17111776


1
DAVID HUME (1711-1776)
2
HUME ON TASTE
  • Taste is a human faculty analogous to the senses
    of hearing and sight.
  • Judgements of taste have a foundation in things
    which we experience, and they can be confirmed or
    refuted by experience.
  • People with the proper organs of perception who
    are mentally sound ought to be able to agree when
    something is beautiful or aesthetic and when it
    is not.

3
JUDGEMENTS OF TASTE
  • For Hume, aesthetic properties depend on
    judgements of taste, but the judgements about
    aesthetic properties are objective.
  • Just as vision can see that an object is red, so
    the faculty of taste can judge that an object is
    aesthetic. Accordingly, the faculty of taste is
    likened by Hume to a faculty of perception.
  • Agreement among people with taste - experts,
    aesthetes - forms the foundation of the objective
    standards of taste.

4
HUME ON JUDGEMENTS AND SENTIMENT I
  • Sentiment df. 1. a feeling 2. emotional
    attitude 3. thought and judgement influenced by
    feeling
  • Hume It is commonly thought that there is a
    difference between judgement and sentiment.
  • Feelings are thought to be always right or not
    disputable, because sentiment feeling has no
    reference to anything beyond itself.
  • But judgements do refer to things beyond
    themselves, and so can be true or false.

5
HUME ON JUDGEMENTS AND SENTIMENT II
  • According to the common opinion which Hume
    opposes, that there is no disputing taste, the
    contrast between judgement and feeling can be put
    like this there is but one correct judgement
    about the chemical composition of water, but of
    any number of different sentiments or feelings
    about something, or of ten different opinions
    about the aesthetic merit of a work of art, no
    one is right or any better than any other.

6
FEELINGS AND JUDGEMENTS ACCORDING TO THE COMMON
SUBJECTIVE VIEW
  • People can disagree about the quality of an
    artwork because the same artwork can produce
    different, conflicting feelings.
  • Where the same object produces different
    feelings, how do we say one is right and one is
    wrong?
  • Hume The common subjective opinion is that
    different sentiments produced by the same object
    are all equally correct. This is what I am
    calling the common subjective view. It is
    common because many people and thinkers hold it
    to be true, and it is subjective because the idea
    is that the perception of beauty is not only
    dependent on the subject, but does not extend
    beyond the subject.
  • And this is because no sentiment represents what
    is really in the object. And something not in
    the object leads to the possibility of
    disagreement.

7
FEELINGS AND OBJECTS ACCORDING TO THE COMMON
SUBJECTIVE VIEW
  • According to the common subjective view which
    Hume rejects, a feeling only marks a certain
    conformity or relation between the object and the
    organs or faculties of the mind.
  • Because of this relation of a feeling to the
    mind, beauty for the common view which Hume
    rejects is no quality in things themselves it
    exists merely in the mind which contemplates
    them and each mind perceives a different
    beauty.
  • This results in the conclusion that all aesthetic
    opinions are equally good.

8
VARIABILITY OF TASTE ACCORDING TO THE COMMON
SUBJECTIVE VIEW
  • That feeling depends on a relation between
    properties of the object and properties of the
    subject leads to the view that beauty is not a
    quality of an object like its shape.
  • Rather, as was seen, beauty is thought to be a
    property of the mind which contemplates an
    object.
  • To talk about the real or objective beauty of an
    object is then not thought to be possible.

9
CAN TASTES BE DISPUTED?
  • Although it is common to say that tastes cant be
    disputed, another position, defended by Hume, is
    that tastes can be disputed.
  • Hume Anyone who maintained the aesthetic
    equality of disproportionate cases, such as
    asserting that Stephen King is the equal of
    Shakespeare and or that the Rolling Stones are as
    musically sophisticated and expressive as Mozart,
    would be as wrong as maintaining that a pond and
    the ocean are equal in size.
  • There may still have a problem in disputing cases
    of near equality - e.g. Mozart and Beethoven -
    but not in the case of things where to maintain
    there equality would be absurd and ridiculous.

10
ART, RULES, AND EXPERIENCE
  • Hume There are no a priori rules of composing
    art. Rather, the foundation of artistic
    composition is experience. That is, we cannot
    use reason to deduce principles of artistic
    composition, but must learn what works and what
    doesnt through experiment and artistic insight.
  • Rules of composition are just general
    observations about what has been found to please
    in all countries and in all ages.
  • However, rules are not binding but can be broken.
    And perhaps an artwork can be made better by
    breaking the rules.

11
ARTS AND SCIENCES
  • Hume notes that the arts are different from
    philosophy and the sciences.
  • And he says that, to attempt to reduce art to
    geometrical truth and exactness, would just
    produce bad art.
  • However, he observes that, although art has no
    rules which conform to exact truth, there are
    certain rules of art discovered by genius or
    observation.

12
THE VALUE OF AN ARTWORK
  • For Hume, the test of an artworks worth is
    whether or not it pleases those with educated
    tastes in all countries and in all ages. The
    same Homer who pleased at Athens and Rome two
    thousand years ago, is still admired at Paris and
    at London. All the changes of climate,
    government, religion, and language, have not be
    able to obscure his glory.
  • Bad art may have a temporary audience but it will
    not endure. Only great art lasts, and has a wider
    audience.
  • The longer an artwork lasts, and the more widely
    it is admired, the more its creator is rightly
    held in esteem.

13
ART CRITICISM AND ITS GROUNDS
  • Hume Amidst all the variety and caprice of
    taste, there are certain general principles of
    approbation or blame, whose influence a careful
    eye may trace in all operations of the mind.
  • For Hume, the perception of beauty depends on
    good organs eyes for seeing painting, and ears
    for hearing music.
  • That a number of people with sound organs agree
    about the worth of artworks gives a basis for
    deriving the idea of perfect beauty. If, in the
    sound state of an organ, there be an entire or
    considerable uniformity of sentiment among men,
    we may thence derive an idea of perfect beauty.

14
MINDS AND DEVELOPED TASTES
  • Hume says that some objects are likely to be
    pleasing to all because of the common structure
    of the human mind.
  • However, certain incidents and situations may
    interfere with proper perception of objects, and
    minds can differ by delicacy of imagination.
  • Delicacy of imagination is required for the
    discriminating tastes of aesthetes or experts in
    art. (See Don Quixote passage on p. 486.)

15
BEAUTY AND SUBJECTS AND OBJECTS I
  • Hume says that there is a great resemblance
    between mental and bodily taste. And even more
    than sweet and bitter, Hume says that beauty and
    ugliness are not properties of objects.
  • Rather, beauty and ugliness are like secondary
    properties of objects they are observer
    dependent or have an essential relation to
    percipients.
  • No minds no beauty, no minds no ugliness.

16
BEAUTY AND SUBJECTS AND OBJECTS II
  • However, although beauty depends on subjects,
    there are certain qualities in objects which are
    fitted by nature to produce these particular
    feelings.
  • Therefore, beauty and ugliness depend on
    properties of the object in addition to
    properties of the subject.

17
DELICACY OF TASTE
  • The properties of objects which make them
    beautiful are not always found by ordinary taste,
    but may require a delicacy of taste to discern
    them.
  • Delicacy of taste df. The organs are so fine as
    to allow nothing to escape them, and at the same
    time are so exact as to perceive every ingredient
    in a composition.

18
THE DEVELOPMENT OF GOOD TASTE
  • Hume Acute perception of beauty and deformity
    must be the perfection of our mental taste.
  • Hume The best way to develop taste, or perfect
    our mental taste, is to appeal to those models
    and principles which have been established by the
    uniform consent and experience of nations and
    ages.
  • To acquire good taste in art a person should
    study great art and contemplate different kinds
    of beauty.
  • Experience breeds expertise, and so taste can be
    educated.

19
TASTE, PREJUDICE, AND INTELLECT
  • Hume notes that, just as prejudice destroys good
    judgement in intellectual matters, so prejudice
    affects good taste and the judgement of beauty.
  • One should use reason to eliminate prejudice in
    matters of taste and in judgements of beauty.
  • It takes thought to comprehend all parts of
    artworks in harmonious relation.
  • And it takes thought to recognize the end or
    purpose of an artwork.
  • And it takes work to establish good taste through
    the study of the arts and their histories.

20
WHY ONE PERSONS TASTE CANT ESTABLISH A STANDARD
FOR ALL
  • A. The faculty of taste, or the organ of internal
    sensation is seldom perfect, but usually has some
    defect.
  • B. A person may lack delicacy of taste. If so,
    then his judgement has no merit.
  • C. A person judging a work may lack expertise
    which must be developed by practice.
  • D. Prejudice may be involved.
  • E. The person may be lacking in good sense.

21
QUALITIES OF A GOOD CRITIC
  • According to Hume, a good critic has a strong
    sense coupled with delicate sentiment. The
    critics skills are improved by practice and
    perfected by comparison.
  • In addition, a good critic has a mind which is
    cleared of all prejudice.
  • Hume acknowledges that we may rightly ask where
    good critics are to be found, and how we are to
    know which critics are good and which are not,
    but he maintains that whether or not a critic is
    good is a question of fact, not of sentiment.
    However, Hume says that all will acknowledge that
    the qualities which make a critic good are good
    qualities to have.

22
TRUE STANDARDS OF TASTE
  • For Hume not all tastes are equal.
  • General standards of taste come from the
    agreement of good critics.
  • Where questions of taste are a matter of dispute,
    Hume says people must use reason and argument to
    attempt to settle the dispute, and must
    acknowledge a true and decisive standard to exist
    somewhere, to wit, real existence and matter of
    fact, and we must further recognize that the
    taste of all individuals is not upon an equal
    footing.
  • Thus, for Hume, questions of taste are questions
    of aesthetic fact, not merely of individual
    taste, and some tastes, namely of the educated
    experts, are better than others.

23
TWO SOURCES OF DIFFERENCE OF TASTE
  • 1. Different temperaments humors of different
    individuals. Hume calls this a difference of
    internal frame.
  • 2. Cultural differences of time and place age
    and country. Hume calls this a difference of
    external situation.
  • However, in spite of these two sources of
    variation, Hume still thinks that the general
    principles of taste are uniform in human nature.
    And where men vary in their judgements there
    is some defect or perversion in the faculties,
    or prejudice, lack of practice, or lack of
    delicacy, and so there is just reason for
    approving one taste and condemning another.

24
CONCLUSION ABOUT SOURCES OF DIFFERENCE OF TASTE
  • However, where disagreements about tastes cannot
    be reconciled because of individual temperaments,
    or because of influences of time and place, then
    in that case a certain degree of diversity in
    judgement is unavoidable, and we seek in vain for
    a standard, by which we can reconcile the
    contrary sentiments.
  • This seems especially applicable to disagreements
    among experts about the superiority of one great
    artist to another, Leonardo to Rembrandt, for
    instance.

25
CURT DUCASSES (1881-1969) DEFINITION OF BEAUTY
  • Beauty is defined as the capacity of an object
    aesthetically contemplated to yield feelings that
    are pleasant.
  • 1. What does Ducasse mean by object?
  • A. Physical?
  • B. Perceptual?
  • C. Mental or intellectual?

26
OBJECTS AND AESTHETIC EXPERIENCE
  • All aesthetic feelings presuppose objects which
    can elicit aesthetic experience. All aesthetic
    experience is reactive, a person cannot will
    herself to have an aesthetic experience, but, as
    reactive, it is dependent on an object to which
    it responds.
  • The objects which aesthetic experience
    presupposes must be perceptual. This is because
    they must be external to the observer or to the
    person whose experience it is, and knowledge of
    external objects is based on sense perception.
  • However, must aesthetic experience be limited to
    perceptual objects? Cannot intellectual objects
    be beautiful or elicit aesthetic experience?

27
ARTWORKS AND PHYSICAL OBJECTS
  • An artwork is not a mind-independent physical
    object, although it always depends on one.
  • One cannot deduce from a physical description of
    an object that it is a work of art.
  • Artworks are necessarily dependent on objects
    which can be experienced, and so are dependent on
    minds, since there is no experience apart from
    mind.

28
ARTWORKS AND PUBLIC PERCEPTUAL OBJECTS
  • All artworks depend on public perceptual objects,
    although they need not themselves be perceptual.
    An example is Robert Barrys
  • ALL THE THINGS I KNOW
  • BUT OF WHICH I AM NOT
  • AT THE MOMENT THINKING - 136PM JUNE 15, 1969.
  • Notice that on Ducasses definition of beauty, an
    object need not be an artwork to be beautiful,
    but could be a natural object.

29
DUCASSE AND AESTHETIC CONTEMPLATION
  • Beauty is defined as the capacity of an object
    aesthetically contemplated to yield feelings that
    are pleasant.
  • What does aesthetically contemplated mean? To
    take an aesthetic attitude towards an object?
  • George Dickie objects that there is no such thing
    as taking an aesthetic attitude towards an
    object. Rather, we are just attending to the
    object - just contemplating it - and doing so may
    produce aesthetic experience.

30
DUCASSE AND FEELING
  • Beauty is defined as the capacity of an object
    aesthetically contemplated to yield feelings that
    are pleasant.
  • Must aesthetic experience be a feeling? Are
    feelings always emotional, or can aesthetic
    experience be intellectual or at least elicited
    by the minds experience of an intellectual
    object? If elicited by such an object, is the
    feeling different or the same as a feeling due to
    a perceptual object?
  • Can a reaction to an object be called aesthetic
    if it is not a feeling?

31
THE NATURE OF AESTHETIC EXPERIENCE
  • Is aesthetic experience homogeneous or
    heterogeneous?
  • Do all aesthetic experiences have something in
    common in virtue of which they are aesthetic, or
    are they similar in some ways and different in
    others?

32
THE PLEASANTNESS OF AESTHETIC EXPERIENCE
  • Beauty is defined as the capacity of an object
    aesthetically contemplated to yield feelings that
    are pleasant.
  • Can any feeling or reaction which is not pleasant
    be termed aesthetic?
  • Does every part of an artwork have to be pleasant
    for the work to be aesthetic?
  • Could aesthetic experience be neutral rather than
    pleasant, just not bad?
  • Could an unethical action be termed aesthetic?

33
BEAUTY AND SUBJECTS AND OBJECTS
  • According to Ducasse, his definition of beauty is
    not simply objective or subjective.
  • Beauty is objective in the sense that the term
    beautiful is applied only to objects.
  • However, saying that an object is beautiful means
    that it produces pleasant feelings in a subject.
    Thus beauty is subjective in being dependent on a
    subject that can experience beauty.

34
THE RELATIVITY OF BEAUTY
  • Ducasse says that, because seeing an object as
    beautiful depends in part on the constitution of
    a subject, whether or not an object is seen to be
    beautiful will vary with the constitutions of
    subjects.
  • For Ducasse, beauty cannot be objective or
    universal because a) it depends on the
    constitutions of subjects, and b) the
    constitutions of different subjects differ.
  • Different subjects can disagree about an objects
    beauty, and the same subject can find an object
    beautiful at one time and not at another. And
    where disagreement exists about beauty there is
    no means by which the disagreement can be
    resolved, and each judgement is equally valid.

35
WHAT DOES CONSTITUTION INCLUDE?
  • 1. The physical, genetic or developed make-up of
    the brain?
  • 2. The innate structure or developed make-up of
    the mind?
  • 3. The experiential/historical make-up of mind
    and/or brain as developed through experience and
    aesthetic education?
  • 4. The make-up of a person as a combination of
    1, 2, and 3?

36
BEAUTY AND AUTHORITY
  • According to Ducasse, because aesthetic
    experience depends on different constitutions,
    there is no such thing as authoritative opinion
    concerning the beauty of a given object.
  • There are only opinions, not objective or
    authoritative judgements. One need not accept the
    judgement of a so-called connoisseur or
    expert. For Ducasse, for you to accept the
    judgement of an expert with whom you disagree
    means that you are not being true to your own
    feelings.
  • Because there is no absolute standard to which
    one can appeal in order to resolve aesthetic
    disagreement, one opinion is as good as another,
    and beauty is not absolute but relative.

37
WHAT IS GOOD TASTE?
  • For Ducasse, good taste is either my taste, or
    the taste of people who are to my taste, or the
    taste of those people whose taste I want to
    have.
  • There is no objective test of the goodness or
    badness of taste you either find beauty in an
    object or you do not.
  • The taste of experts does not have to be
    accepted.
  • Contra Hume, for Ducasse, taste cannot be proved
    by consensus of the experts.
  • And contra Hume, for Ducasse, the test of time is
    no guarantee that one taste is better than
    another.

38
PRINCIPLES AND PROOF OF BEAUTY
  • Ducasse says that beauty cant be proved by
    appeal to accepted principles or authoritative
    lists of beautiful objects.
  • The principles of beauty to which a person
    subscribes can change, both my principles and
    that of others.
  • One persons taste can only be praised or
    condemned by another, and there is no proving
    that one is right and another wrong.

39
STANDARDS OF EVALUATION I
  • Ducasse says that standards by which artworks are
    evaluated cannot themselves be evaluated, but can
    only be accepted as correct or rejected as wrong.
    Or if the standards accepted are themselves
    evaluated by a different standard, then that
    standard cannot be independently confirmed, but
    can only be assumed to be correct.
  • The idea is that all arguments for the worth of
    an artwork must rest on value principles which
    must be assumed to be correct and cannot be
    argued for, or we must eventually reach a point
    at which all argument ceases, and rests on points
    which are assumed. This is because, without such
    an assumed starting point, we would be left with
    an infinite regress of arguments.

40
STANDARDS OF EVALUATION II
  • As just seen, one cannot argue for a standard of
    evaluation which one accepts, since any argument
    for the standard will simply assume the
    correctness of the standard accepted for which
    one attempts to argue, or will require an
    additional argument which one accepts without
    argument.
  • For instance, to evaluate art by a standard of
    representation will assume that that standard of
    evaluation is correct, and any attempted argument
    in favor of such a standard will simply assume
    the correctness of the position that no art can
    be valuable which is not representational. Or, if
    we want to argue for the standard of
    representation by saying that art should copy
    reality, then that copy standard must simply be
    assumed or dogmatically laid down to be
    correct.
  • But Ducasse says that different standards of
    evaluation are equally legitimate.

41
ART, RULES, AND BEAUTY
  • Ducasse maintains that there are no rules which
    will guarantee an artworks aesthetic worth.
  • Aesthetic feeling is the final court of appeal,
    and where one person has it another may not, and
    where I did not have it at one time at another
    time I might, or vice versa.
  • Works of art are only to be judged by the
    aesthetic experiences which they actually produce
    or fail to produce, and not by any rules or other
    standards.

42
CAN TASTES BE DEVELOPED?
  • Ducasse says, yes, they can, but that does not
    affect his theory that tastes are subjective.
  • Tastes can be refined and educated, but they can
    also be perverted and deprived.
  • How can we know which is which? Or how can we
    prove philosophically that we are going in one
    direction rather than another?

43
THE PROOF OF TASTE
  • Recall that, for Ducasse, you cant prove that
    one persons taste is better than another.
  • This means the taste of experts or aesthetes
    reflects only one possible position, but it cant
    be said to be the one true or correct taste.
  • Also, the taste of the majority of opinion is not
    proof that it is the correct taste. This is
    because the majority might have either good taste
    or bad taste.

44
MONROE BEARDSLEY (1915-1981) ON DISPUTING TASTES
  • For Beardsley, the chief use of the view that
    tastes cant be disputed is to put an end to
    argument about the aesthetic worth of something
    which is making no progress.
  • To say that there is no disputing tastes is meant
    to sound both profound and democratic profound
    in stating a truth about man in relation to
    certain objects, and democratic in recognizing
    the equality of all tastes none is better than
    or superior to another.
  • If the principle is true, then there would seem
    to be no point to criticizing and discussing art
    but if it is false then criticism and education
    in the arts does have a point.

45
WHAT DOES IT MEAN TO SAY THAT TASTES ARE OR ARE
NOT DISPUTABLE? I
  • For Beardsley, saying that tastes cannot be
    disputed has two key terms taste and disputed.
  • Taste has both a broad and a narrow meaning.
    Taste in the narrow sense concerns its primary
    sensory meaning, and so concerns preferences for
    and aversions to certain foods and drinks.
    Taste in the broad sense refers to the arts,
    and is not simply sensory, but involves the mind
    of the percipient.
  • A main difference between taste in either sense
    is that not much can be said or argued about
    regarding taste in the narrow sense, but a great
    deal can be said and argued about regarding taste
    in the broad sense.

46
WHAT DOES IT MEAN TO SAY THAT TASTES ARE OR ARE
NOT DISPUTABLE? II
  • What does it mean to dispute about tastes?
    Beardsley says that it doesnt mean that we
    cannot disagree, or differ in taste because both
    ordinary people and experts have different tastes
    and disagree with one another about the aesthetic
    merit of objects.
  • A disagreement is a dispute when reasons are
    given for the disagreement. Without reasons a
    disagreement is simply an opposition of opinion.
  • Beardsley wants to know why, if we can dispute
    about politics and other things, why not art?

47
WHAT DOES IT MEAN TO SAY THAT TASTES ARE OR ARE
NOT DISPUTABLE? III
  • For Beardsley, a disagreement is a disagreement
    about taste in the broad rather than the narrow
    sense when reasons can be given why one taste is
    preferable to another.
  • It may be hard to argue why a person ought to
    prefer squid to bologna, but not why someone
    should like Matisse better than Leroy Nieman, or
    Beethoven better than Madonna.
  • The question, then is whether a preference for
    Picasso or Monteverdi is more like a preference
    for green olives or like a preference for a
    Senatorial candidate is it arguable? can it be
    reasoned?

48
BEARDSLEY ON TASTE AND REASONS
  • Beardsley says then that disputing tastes depends
    on giving reasons why one artwork, style, or
    movement is better than another.
  • If tastes can be disputed, it is because
    aesthetic positions can be argued for.
  • Critics argue for their positions, they give
    reasons why a work, style, or movement is good or
    bad. Such arguments are not simple preference
    statements, as might be given regarding taste in
    the narrow sense. (See Beethoven-Mozart example.)

49
AESTHETIC SKEPTICISM I
  • Beardsleys Aesthetic Skeptic doubts that
    reasons can be given for tastes, or doubts that
    the reasons given are genuine.
  • They are not genuine because, in the end, they
    simply rest on individual preferences sheer
    liking or disliking.
  • Because tastes rest on individual preferences,
    rational arguments cant be given for against
    them. (See the Aesthetic Skeptics response to
    the Beethoven-Mozart example.)

50
AESTHETIC SKEPTICISM II
  • The Aesthetic Skeptic will acknowledge that
    critics can point out features of artworks which
    he thinks makes them good works, but will
    maintain that the critic is simply assuming
    rather than proving that these features are good.
    Instead, the critic is taking for granted, what
    may not be true, that you happen to like those
    features.
  • You cant, says the Skeptic, argue anybody into
    liking something he doesnt like, and thats why
    there is no disputing about tastes all disputes
    are in the end useless.
  • Notice then that the Skeptic assumes all tastes
    are tastes in the narrow rather than the broad
    sense. Beardsley disagrees. However, although he
    thinks that Aesthetic Skepticism is wrong, he
    does not think that it is childish or
    simple-minded.

51
AESTHETIC SKEPTICISM III
  • The Skeptical theory takes peoples likes and
    dislikes as ultimate and unappealable facts about
    them that a personal taste is based on such
    things as genetic constitution, culture, and
    particular history of experience.
  • All argument for Skepticism ends, not in
    conclusions of aesthetic arguments, but in basic
    likes or dislikes. And for Skepticism these are
    ultimate and unappealable.

52
BEARDSLEYS RESPONSE TO AESTHETIC SKEPTICISM
  • Beardsley acknowledges that you cant change a
    disliking into a liking simply by arguments,
    however that doesnt imply that you cant
    change it at all, or that we cannot argue whether
    or not it ought to be changed.
  • Rather, one can give reasons why a person would
    be better off if he could enjoy music or painting
    that he now abhors, and tastes can be changed
    and improved by study and enlarged experience.

53
BEARDSLEY ON TASTE I
  • For Beardsley, there are not just individual
    tastes, but better and worse tastes.
  • Tastes can be developed into higher forms through
    education and experience of great works of art.
  • Also, I can say that some artworks are better or
    worse than others without claiming that I know
    for certain which are which.

54
BEARDSLEY ON TASTE II
  • For Beardsley, taste matters, whereas taste does
    not seem to matter to the Aesthetic Skeptic.
  • It matters because good taste will determine
    which artworks get shown, which works of music
    are played, which books get published, and so
    forth. Good taste will also determine what good
    artists will produce, or if they produce at all.
  • Further, the kind of experiences that can only
    be obtained by access to the greatest works is an
    important ingredient of the richest and most
    fully developed human life.
  • Because this is the case, giving reasons why some
    works are better than others is of the greatest
    importance to culture.

55
DONT I HAVE A RIGHT TO MY TASTE?
  • Beardsley says that the Aesthetic Skeptic may
    think it unfair or undemocratic to try to educate
    tastes, since this may be taken to interfere with
    each persons right to his or her own taste.
    However, Beardsley says that it is no invasion
    of a persons right, if he is willing to
    consider the problem, to try to convince him that
    he should try to like other things that appear to
    deserve it.
  • Would you want to attend a university which had
    you study inferior works of art because they are
    easy or popular, or should you rather assume that
    professors of art, music, and literature are
    experts in a manner analogous to that of
    professors of physics and mathematics?

56
EDUCATION AND THE ARTS
  • Beardsley Works of art are complicated.
  • Ergo, you may have to study and think about them
    in order to appreciate and understand them.
  • Why should our assessment of the value of an
    artwork have to be immediate? Cant tastes can be
    educated as much as our minds? Cant we be
    educated in the arts as much as in any other
    subject? Does Aesthetic Skepticism invite a
    certain laziness in art education?
  • Strayer There is an inverse relation between
    knowledge of art and opinion about art the
    weaker the knowledge the stronger the opinion.

57
ART CRITICISM
  • Critics give reasons in favor of their opinions
    about artworks, but are not being dogmatic when
    they deny that its all a matter of taste.
  • Instead, They believe that some true and
    reasonable judgement of an artwork is in
    principle possible, and that objective critics,
    given time and discussion, could in principle
    agree, or come close to agreeing on it.
  • But they do not need to claim infallibility
    people can be mistaken about art as they can
    about anything else.

58
JUDGING WORKS OF ART
  • Beardsley says that an artwork must be judged on
    its own terms We must keep our eye on the
    object the painting, the novel, the quintet.
  • An artists personal life is irrelevant to
    judging the merit of an artwork by her.
  • A work of art, whatever its species, is an
    object if some kind something somebody made.
  • The preceding remark recognizes implicitly that
    we cannot produce aesthetic experiences
    internally, or at will. Aesthetic experience can
    only be reactive - it presupposes an object which
    elicits it. It also recognizes that artworks are
    objects produced by intentional actions.

59
ART AND AESTHETIC EXPERIENCE I
  • And the question is whether it the artwork was
    worth making, what it is good for, what can be
    done with it.
  • For Beardsley, an artwork is a means of
    producing aesthetic experience. He calls artworks
    consumption goods things which we consume
    perceptually and intellectually in order to
    afford certain valuable kinds and degrees of
    aesthetic experience.
  • And it must be recognized that artworks do not
    yield aesthetic experience to those who cannot
    understand them . . .

60
WHEN ARE ARTWORKS GOOD?
  • According to Beardsley, works of art are good
    when they elicit aesthetic experience.
  • However, one may have to learn how to approach a
    work to get the experience it is capable of
    providing.
  • Tastes can be developed through aesthetic
    education.
  • Developed tastes are superior to undeveloped
    tastes.
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com