Toward a Phenomenology of Work - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

About This Presentation
Title:

Toward a Phenomenology of Work

Description:

... and ontological questions IR must tackle if it is to succeed as a discipline. ... Journal of Humanistic Psychology, 36(4): 80-93. Eldred, Michael, 2000. ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:68
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 21
Provided by: Hon149
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: Toward a Phenomenology of Work


1
Toward a Phenomenologyof Work
  • Amy Lavender Harris
  • Centre for Industrial Relations
  • University of Toronto
  • 9 November 2005

2
  • Next, we consider the impact of workforce skill
    on the portion of output created with IT support
    as shown in the second terms of Equations (2a)
    and (2b). First, in simple IT-worker systems,
    worker skill beyond the base level is not needed
    to operate IT and generate output so that ?psup
    1sub 2i/?s 0 holds. In sharp contrast, in
    complex IT-worker systems, the speed that a
    worker operating IT generates output depends
    heavily on the extent that worker skill exceeds
    the base level. For example, a highly skilled
    engineering specialist may generate more output
    volume per unit time from a CAD system than a
    lesser skilled worker operating the same
    technology. Specifically, while holding constant
    the size of the workforce (w), IT accessibility
    (x), and the IT choice (i), the volume of output
    in a complex IT-worker system is a non-decreasing
    function of worker skill (?psup 2sub 2i/?s
    0). However, increasing worker skill while
    holding other inputs fixed leads to diminishing
    returns so that ?sup 2psup 2sub 2i/ ?sup
    2S lt 0.
  • (Napoleon, Karen Cheryl Gaimon, 2004. The
    Creation of Output and Quality in Services A
    Framework to Analyze Information
    Technology-Worker Systems. Production and
    Operations Management, 13(3) 245-260)

3
  • During my discussions with these office workers,
    I sometimes asked them to draw pictures that
    represented their felt sense of their job
    experience before and after the conversion to the
    new computer system. Frequently these pictures
    functioned as a catalyst, helping them to
    articulate feelings that had been implicit and
    hard to define. These simple drawings convey
    feelings that often elude verbal expression. The
    condition of being tied to the machine
    represents a new kind of confinement, not just
    the spatial confinement of having to sit in one
    place for long stretches, but an interior
    confinement. These clerks, driven into the
    confines of the laboring body, have seen their
    tasks shorn of opportunities for using
    interpersonal and substantive skills. The
    principal challenge of their current jobs is an
    effort of endurance. It is a sullen effort,
    subtly corrosive, felt in diffuse interior
    discomforts, rarely dramatic, but persistent and
    inescapable.
  • (Zuboff, Shoshana, 1988. In the Age of the Smart
    Machine The Future of Work and Power. New York
    Basic Books. See pages 141-150.)

4
A Short Caricature of Empiricism
  • the project of empiricism is to make
    observations, to classify and order what is
    observed and to make general statements about
    observed or calculated relations between
    observables. (Marsden, 1982 233, after Zubaida
    (1974))
  • All knowledge is a posteriori, that is, derived
    from experience or experiment (many empiricists
    deny the legitimacy of a priori knowledge or
    knowledge derived through pure reason)
  • The validity of any claim is measured by the
    ability to test it (in this sense, theories are
    the second-order products of hypotheses tested in
    the field theories subsequently derived are
    subject to further testing hence the claim that
    a good theory is one we can test empirically)
  • non-observable and non-measurable phenomena are
    generally excluded at its core, empiricism
    reflects a materialist orientation
  • In the sciences and social sciences, rigorous
    is generally interpreted to mean empirical the
    scientific method is generally equated with an
    empirical method and an empiricist orientation

5
Criticisms of Empiricism
  • There is a world of difference between the terms
    empirical and empiricism. The term
    empirical refers to a battery of very useful
    research methods. The term empiricism refers to
    a restrictive methodological doctrine which
    claims that researchers may only use empirical
    methods. (Mende, 2005189)
  • IR scholars, among them Richard Marsden (1982)
    and John Godard (1989, 1994), have argued that
    industrial relations theory and practice is
    doctrinally (or at least epistemologically)
    empiricist.
  • According to sociologist Louis Althusser, in
    empirical research there are objects (real
    things) and essences (abstractions, ultimately
    theories) which researchers purport to extract
    from them. Yet, these essences are not actually
    derived from objects but are themselves products
    of thought theoretical objects which
    appropriate and conceal the real object.
    Knowledge is produced, not discovered the
    empiricist production of knowledge always occurs
    within an ideology. (viz Marsden, 1982)
  • In this critique, empiricists might be said to
    play a sort of shell game, infusing objects with
    the very theories they then pretend to extract
    from them. Another way of putting this is to say
    that the answers a researcher gets are dependent
    upon the questions s/he asks.

6
IR theory faces a dual quandary
  • Deficiency A fetish for empirical approaches and
    a fixation on description, classification, and
    the quantification of the visible has left IR
    theory partial, primitive (Adams, 1988 5), and
    reliant on uncritical interdisciplinarity.
    (Walker (1977 310)
  • Duplicity The doctrine of empiricism in IR has
    concealed its ideological underpinnings (the
    theory-ladenness of objects and essences as the
    proverbial elephant in the corner), thus posing a
    further obstacle to the development of genuinely
    critical IR theories.

7
Whither IR?
  • Low/middle-range theorizing and
    generalization/hypothesis building Give up and
    accept an atheoretical or thinly theoretical IR
    focused on circumstantial relationships (Dunlops
    systems model, KKMs rational choice model
    industrial relations are).
  • - and/or -
  • Higher-level theorization What should a theory
    of IR look like? Risks carving up IR into
    theoretical territories across which academic
    antagonists wield their warring axiologies in
    infinite regress (e.g., Hymans
    conflict-critical approach (1994 see Hansen,
    2002), feminist/gendered approaches (Hansen and
    others), Marsden (1982), labour process theory,
    Frankfurt school, etc. industrial relations
    is).
  • - and/or -
  • Meta-theory (theory about theory explores
    assumptions underlying any given theoretical
    perspective) One asks, What might a philosophy
    of IR look like?
  • Note the three levels of theorization are
    influenced by Hansen (2002) who credits Hyman
    (1994)
  • Note also the are/is distinction comes from
    Marsden (1982)

8
What might a philosophy of IR look like?
  • It would ask epistemological questions What does
    it mean to know something? Is there any a priori
    knowledge? What are the limits of knowledge? How
    do we get to knowing?
  • It would acknowledge ontological questions
    What is the nature of reality and of being in it?
    How many ways are there of being in the world?
    How many worlds are there?
  • It would seek to uncover world views about the
    nature of knowledge, reality, meaning, and being.
  • It might begin by examining philosophies of work.

9
Philosophies of WorkThe means of production and
the production of meaning
  • A longstanding area of philosophical inquiry that
    is largely overlooked by IR scholars.
  • Many philosophers write about work, but the most
    influential contributions are generally
    attributed to Hegel and Marx.
  • Both held that work is an essential part of human
    existence it is a rational and distinctively
    human activity that creates the way of life of
    the human being and, at the same time, transforms
    the world and human relationships. (Kovacs,
    1986 196)
  • Philosopher of education John White challenges
    the notion of the centrality of work (and the
    inherent work ethic) advanced by thinkers from
    Marx to Hannah Arendt instead, he cites
    Nietzsche and Bertrand Russells critiques of
    industriousness in building his theory of
    autonomous and heteronomous work in relation
    to personal flourishing (White, 1997)
  • The question of alienation is present throughout
    philosophical analyses of work.
  • Yet, missing or poorly developed is a clear
    analysis of the self (particularly with respect
    to autonomy and cooperation) and of the nature
    and meaning of work itself. In other words, an
    ontology of work (and working) is needed.

10
Toward a Phenomenology of Work
  • A phenomenology of work is one element in a
    philosophy of work within IR.
  • A phenomenology of work asks, What is the
    meaning of work? What does it mean to do
    work? How are being and work(ing) related?
    How does alienation characterize the experience
    of work?
  • Kovacs (1996) holds that work is a basic mode of
    being in the world it is a way of self-creation
    and a mode of forming and transforming the world
    and nature. (196). Kovacs also holds that work
    has both personal and social dimensions
    phenomenologically speaking, it is both
    subjective and intersubjective.
  • Research in IRHR applying phenomenological
    methods and approaches includes Shoshana Zuboffs
    well-known In the Age of the Smart Machine
    (1988), Francis Penn on the phenomenology of
    skill (1994), work-nonwork conflict and the
    phenomenology of time (Thompson Bunderson,
    2001), among others.
  • My research begins where these accounts leave
    off. It considers how paying attention to
    phenomenological accounts might alter not only
    how we understand and organize work, but how the
    inclusion of a phenomenological approach might
    alter IR as a whole.

11
(No Transcript)
12
A Phenomenological Analysis of Alienation
  • A joining of Heideggerian phenomenology with
    Marxs concept of the alienated worker, read in
    large part through a philosophical analysis of
    technology.
  • I am not the first person to suggest that Marxs
    concept of alienation might be read
    phenomenologically see Kovacs (1986), Eldred
    (2000) nor to suggest that alienation and
    technology are intertwined (see Laing, 1960
    Kateb, 1997).
  • Marxian scholars (e.g., Rinehart, 1996) tend to
    reject any reading of alienation that departs
    from Marxs notions of class consciousness.
  • However, a phenomenological analysis helps deepen
    as well as challenge Marxs views while taking
    the genealogy of IR seriously, and might help
    build a more solid place for a philosophy of work
    within IR.

13
Alienated Labour
  • Concepts of alienation have a long genealogy in
    philosophy and social political thought.
  • Hegel held that the self was a historical and
    social creation and that alienation (and
    self-recovery) was part of a process of growth
    for individuals and society as a whole. Acts of
    work are both alienating to the self and offer
    the possibility of reconciliation.
  • Diverging sharply from Hegel while retaining some
    of the same terms, Marxs concept of alienation
    arises as part of a materialist critique of
    industrial capitalism. In his early work Marx
    identifies five dimensions of alienated labour
    (see Rinehart, 1996)
  • (1) estrangement from the products of ones
    labour
  • (2) estrangement from the work process itself
    (when labour belongs to someone else)
  • (3) self-estrangement (from self-expression and
    self- development)
  • (4) estrangement from ones own essence of
    nature
  • (5) estrangement of individuals from one
    another (e.g., by class)
  • According to Marx, workers share an alienated
    consciousness of the effects of structural
    alienation their class consciousness is what
    will give rise to resistance and (perhaps)
    revolution.

14
Heidegger and Alienation the Question
Concerning Technology
  • Marxs concept of alienation bears striking
    similarity to Heideggers view that the essence
    of technology is the reduction of Beings to
    standing reserve.
  • In The Question Concerning Technology, Heidegger
    distinguishes between techne (the bringing-forth
    of something out of itself, a revealing, in the
    form of the activities and skills of the
    craftsperson but also the work of the fine arts
    the bringing forth of the true into the
    beautiful) and the essence of technology (a
    challenging-forth, in which everything is ordered
    about to stand by and thereby reduced to
    standing reserve).
  • The essence of technology permits only this one
    manner of revealing it buries and denies other
    ways of Being it is a kind of banishment of the
    self.
  • While important differences exist between Marx
    and Heidegger (Heidegger almost never engaged
    with Marx, and Heideggers phenomenology is
    neither materialistic nor ideologically critical
    of capitalism), both raise important questions
    about how technology alters the experience of
    Being.

15
Implications for Research on Work
  • What is work? Is all work alienating? How might
    technologically mediated work exacerbate
    alienation?
  • How is alienation experienced? How is it
    expressed? How is it subverted?
  • Is abolishing alienated labour (e.g., Schwalbe,
    1986) a reasonable goal? As an HR practice? As
    part of a Marxist revolution?
  • How might an understanding of alienation advance
    IR/HR theory? How might it advance its practice?

16
Conclusion
  • A phenomenological analysis of alienation
    contributes to the development of IR/HR theory in
    a variety of ways
  • It provides insight into aspects of work that
    empirical approaches do not (and perhaps cannot)
    account for.
  • It encourages us to take the lived experiences of
    workers seriously to see workers as something
    more than human capital, human resources or
    standing reserve and to think about the
    meanings of work.
  • It requires a re-thinking of the perspectives and
    presumptions that inform our thinking and doing,
    whether as IR/HR practitioners or scholars.
  • It seeks to integrate seemingly disparate corners
    of IR/HR research and thought (e.g., HRM, Marxian
    thought, questions about technology,
    phenomenological method, etc.) and in doing so
    seeks to both challenge and further them.
  • It prompts consideration of the kinds of
    epistemological and ontological questions IR must
    tackle if it is to succeed as a discipline.

17
Work \ werk \ n ME werk, work, fr. OE werc,
weorc
  • Activity in which one exerts strength or
    faculties to do or perform something sustained
    physical or mental effort to overcome obstacles
    and achieve an objective or result the labour,
    task, or duty that is ones accustomed means of
    livelihood energy expended by natural phenomena
    something that results from the use or
    fashioning of a particular material structures
    in engineering or mining a place where
    industrial labour is carried on the working or
    moving parts of a mechanism something produced
    or accomplished by effort, exertion, or exercise
    of skill something produced by the exercise of
    creative talent or expenditure of creative
    effort artistic production performance of
    moral or religious acts the material or piece
    of material that is operated upon at any stage in
    the process of manufacture everything
    possessed, available, or belonging subjection
    to drastic treatment engaged in working
    having effect in process of preparation to
    bring to pass to set or keep in motion to
    solve by reasoning
  • Source Merriam-Websters Collegiate Dictionary,
    10th ed. (2002)

18
Sources
  • Adams, Roy, 1988. Desperately Seeking Industrial
    Relations Theory. The International Journal of
    Comparative Labour Law and Industrial Relations,
    4(1) 1-10.
  • Burston, Daniel, 1998. Laing and Heedegger on
    Alienation. Journal of Humanistic Psychology,
    36(4) 80-93.
  • Eldred, Michael, 2000. Capital and Technology
    Marx and Heidegger. Cologne, Germany Artefact.
    Available electronically at http//www.webcom.com/
    artefact/capiteen.html
  • Godard, John, 1994. Beyond Empiricism Towards a
    Reconstruction of IR Theory and Research.
    Advances in Industrial and Labor Relations,
  • Godard, John, 1989. Beyond Empiricism
    Alternative Philosophies of Science and the Study
    of Industrial Relations. Queens University,
  • Kateb, George, 1997. Technology and Philosophy.
    Social Research, 64(3) 1225-1246.
  • Kleinberg-Levin, David, 2005. The Invisible Hands
    of Capital and Labour Using Merleau-Pontys
    phenomenology to understand the meaning of
    alienation in Marxs theory of manual labour.
    Philosophy and Social Criticism, 31(1) 53-67.
  • Kovacs, George, 1986. Phenomenology of Work and
    Self-Transcendence. The Journal of Value Inquiry,
    20 195-207.
  • Marsden, Richard, 1982. Industrial Relations A
    Critique of Empiricism. Sociology, 16(2)
    232-250.

19
  • Mende, Jens, 2005. The Poverty of Empiricism.
    Informing Science Journal, Volume 8 189-210.
  • Napoleon, Karen Cheryl Gaimon, 2004. The
    Creation of Output and Quality in Services A
    Framework to Analyze Information
    Technology-Worker Systems. Production and
    Operations Management, 13(3) 245-260.
  • Rinehart, James W., 1996. The Tyranny of Work
    Alienation and the Labour Process. 3rd edition.
    Toronto Harcourt Brace Canada.
  • Schwalbe, Michael L., 1986. The Psychosocial
    Consequences of Natural and Alienated Labor.
    Albany State University of New York Press.
  • Waugh, William L., Jr., and Wesley W. Waugh,
    2004. Phenomenology and Public Administration.
    International Journal of Organization Theory and
    Behavior, 7(3) 405-432.
  • White, John, 1997. Education and the End of Work
    A New Philosophy of Work and Learning. London
    Cassell.
  • Zuboff, Shoshana, 1988. In the Age of the Smart
    Machine The Future of Work and Power. New York
    Basic Books.

20
Further Information
  • This ongoing research is documented on-line at
  • http//individual.utoronto.ca/alharris/phenomenolo
    gy_of_work.html
  • See also related phenomenological field research
    on life and work at
  • http//individual.utoronto.ca/alharris/life_and_wo
    rk.html
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com