Title: Toward a Phenomenology of Work
1Toward a Phenomenologyof Work
- Amy Lavender Harris
- Centre for Industrial Relations
- University of Toronto
- 9 November 2005
2- Next, we consider the impact of workforce skill
on the portion of output created with IT support
as shown in the second terms of Equations (2a)
and (2b). First, in simple IT-worker systems,
worker skill beyond the base level is not needed
to operate IT and generate output so that ?psup
1sub 2i/?s 0 holds. In sharp contrast, in
complex IT-worker systems, the speed that a
worker operating IT generates output depends
heavily on the extent that worker skill exceeds
the base level. For example, a highly skilled
engineering specialist may generate more output
volume per unit time from a CAD system than a
lesser skilled worker operating the same
technology. Specifically, while holding constant
the size of the workforce (w), IT accessibility
(x), and the IT choice (i), the volume of output
in a complex IT-worker system is a non-decreasing
function of worker skill (?psup 2sub 2i/?s
0). However, increasing worker skill while
holding other inputs fixed leads to diminishing
returns so that ?sup 2psup 2sub 2i/ ?sup
2S lt 0. - (Napoleon, Karen Cheryl Gaimon, 2004. The
Creation of Output and Quality in Services A
Framework to Analyze Information
Technology-Worker Systems. Production and
Operations Management, 13(3) 245-260)
3- During my discussions with these office workers,
I sometimes asked them to draw pictures that
represented their felt sense of their job
experience before and after the conversion to the
new computer system. Frequently these pictures
functioned as a catalyst, helping them to
articulate feelings that had been implicit and
hard to define. These simple drawings convey
feelings that often elude verbal expression. The
condition of being tied to the machine
represents a new kind of confinement, not just
the spatial confinement of having to sit in one
place for long stretches, but an interior
confinement. These clerks, driven into the
confines of the laboring body, have seen their
tasks shorn of opportunities for using
interpersonal and substantive skills. The
principal challenge of their current jobs is an
effort of endurance. It is a sullen effort,
subtly corrosive, felt in diffuse interior
discomforts, rarely dramatic, but persistent and
inescapable. - (Zuboff, Shoshana, 1988. In the Age of the Smart
Machine The Future of Work and Power. New York
Basic Books. See pages 141-150.)
4A Short Caricature of Empiricism
- the project of empiricism is to make
observations, to classify and order what is
observed and to make general statements about
observed or calculated relations between
observables. (Marsden, 1982 233, after Zubaida
(1974)) - All knowledge is a posteriori, that is, derived
from experience or experiment (many empiricists
deny the legitimacy of a priori knowledge or
knowledge derived through pure reason) - The validity of any claim is measured by the
ability to test it (in this sense, theories are
the second-order products of hypotheses tested in
the field theories subsequently derived are
subject to further testing hence the claim that
a good theory is one we can test empirically) - non-observable and non-measurable phenomena are
generally excluded at its core, empiricism
reflects a materialist orientation - In the sciences and social sciences, rigorous
is generally interpreted to mean empirical the
scientific method is generally equated with an
empirical method and an empiricist orientation
5Criticisms of Empiricism
- There is a world of difference between the terms
empirical and empiricism. The term
empirical refers to a battery of very useful
research methods. The term empiricism refers to
a restrictive methodological doctrine which
claims that researchers may only use empirical
methods. (Mende, 2005189) - IR scholars, among them Richard Marsden (1982)
and John Godard (1989, 1994), have argued that
industrial relations theory and practice is
doctrinally (or at least epistemologically)
empiricist. - According to sociologist Louis Althusser, in
empirical research there are objects (real
things) and essences (abstractions, ultimately
theories) which researchers purport to extract
from them. Yet, these essences are not actually
derived from objects but are themselves products
of thought theoretical objects which
appropriate and conceal the real object.
Knowledge is produced, not discovered the
empiricist production of knowledge always occurs
within an ideology. (viz Marsden, 1982) - In this critique, empiricists might be said to
play a sort of shell game, infusing objects with
the very theories they then pretend to extract
from them. Another way of putting this is to say
that the answers a researcher gets are dependent
upon the questions s/he asks. -
6IR theory faces a dual quandary
- Deficiency A fetish for empirical approaches and
a fixation on description, classification, and
the quantification of the visible has left IR
theory partial, primitive (Adams, 1988 5), and
reliant on uncritical interdisciplinarity.
(Walker (1977 310) - Duplicity The doctrine of empiricism in IR has
concealed its ideological underpinnings (the
theory-ladenness of objects and essences as the
proverbial elephant in the corner), thus posing a
further obstacle to the development of genuinely
critical IR theories.
7Whither IR?
- Low/middle-range theorizing and
generalization/hypothesis building Give up and
accept an atheoretical or thinly theoretical IR
focused on circumstantial relationships (Dunlops
systems model, KKMs rational choice model
industrial relations are). - - and/or -
- Higher-level theorization What should a theory
of IR look like? Risks carving up IR into
theoretical territories across which academic
antagonists wield their warring axiologies in
infinite regress (e.g., Hymans
conflict-critical approach (1994 see Hansen,
2002), feminist/gendered approaches (Hansen and
others), Marsden (1982), labour process theory,
Frankfurt school, etc. industrial relations
is). - - and/or -
- Meta-theory (theory about theory explores
assumptions underlying any given theoretical
perspective) One asks, What might a philosophy
of IR look like? - Note the three levels of theorization are
influenced by Hansen (2002) who credits Hyman
(1994) - Note also the are/is distinction comes from
Marsden (1982)
8What might a philosophy of IR look like?
- It would ask epistemological questions What does
it mean to know something? Is there any a priori
knowledge? What are the limits of knowledge? How
do we get to knowing? - It would acknowledge ontological questions
What is the nature of reality and of being in it?
How many ways are there of being in the world?
How many worlds are there? - It would seek to uncover world views about the
nature of knowledge, reality, meaning, and being. - It might begin by examining philosophies of work.
9Philosophies of WorkThe means of production and
the production of meaning
- A longstanding area of philosophical inquiry that
is largely overlooked by IR scholars. - Many philosophers write about work, but the most
influential contributions are generally
attributed to Hegel and Marx. - Both held that work is an essential part of human
existence it is a rational and distinctively
human activity that creates the way of life of
the human being and, at the same time, transforms
the world and human relationships. (Kovacs,
1986 196) - Philosopher of education John White challenges
the notion of the centrality of work (and the
inherent work ethic) advanced by thinkers from
Marx to Hannah Arendt instead, he cites
Nietzsche and Bertrand Russells critiques of
industriousness in building his theory of
autonomous and heteronomous work in relation
to personal flourishing (White, 1997) - The question of alienation is present throughout
philosophical analyses of work. - Yet, missing or poorly developed is a clear
analysis of the self (particularly with respect
to autonomy and cooperation) and of the nature
and meaning of work itself. In other words, an
ontology of work (and working) is needed.
10Toward a Phenomenology of Work
- A phenomenology of work is one element in a
philosophy of work within IR. - A phenomenology of work asks, What is the
meaning of work? What does it mean to do
work? How are being and work(ing) related?
How does alienation characterize the experience
of work? - Kovacs (1996) holds that work is a basic mode of
being in the world it is a way of self-creation
and a mode of forming and transforming the world
and nature. (196). Kovacs also holds that work
has both personal and social dimensions
phenomenologically speaking, it is both
subjective and intersubjective. - Research in IRHR applying phenomenological
methods and approaches includes Shoshana Zuboffs
well-known In the Age of the Smart Machine
(1988), Francis Penn on the phenomenology of
skill (1994), work-nonwork conflict and the
phenomenology of time (Thompson Bunderson,
2001), among others. - My research begins where these accounts leave
off. It considers how paying attention to
phenomenological accounts might alter not only
how we understand and organize work, but how the
inclusion of a phenomenological approach might
alter IR as a whole.
11(No Transcript)
12A Phenomenological Analysis of Alienation
- A joining of Heideggerian phenomenology with
Marxs concept of the alienated worker, read in
large part through a philosophical analysis of
technology. - I am not the first person to suggest that Marxs
concept of alienation might be read
phenomenologically see Kovacs (1986), Eldred
(2000) nor to suggest that alienation and
technology are intertwined (see Laing, 1960
Kateb, 1997). - Marxian scholars (e.g., Rinehart, 1996) tend to
reject any reading of alienation that departs
from Marxs notions of class consciousness. - However, a phenomenological analysis helps deepen
as well as challenge Marxs views while taking
the genealogy of IR seriously, and might help
build a more solid place for a philosophy of work
within IR.
13Alienated Labour
- Concepts of alienation have a long genealogy in
philosophy and social political thought. - Hegel held that the self was a historical and
social creation and that alienation (and
self-recovery) was part of a process of growth
for individuals and society as a whole. Acts of
work are both alienating to the self and offer
the possibility of reconciliation. - Diverging sharply from Hegel while retaining some
of the same terms, Marxs concept of alienation
arises as part of a materialist critique of
industrial capitalism. In his early work Marx
identifies five dimensions of alienated labour
(see Rinehart, 1996) - (1) estrangement from the products of ones
labour - (2) estrangement from the work process itself
(when labour belongs to someone else) - (3) self-estrangement (from self-expression and
self- development) - (4) estrangement from ones own essence of
nature - (5) estrangement of individuals from one
another (e.g., by class) - According to Marx, workers share an alienated
consciousness of the effects of structural
alienation their class consciousness is what
will give rise to resistance and (perhaps)
revolution.
14Heidegger and Alienation the Question
Concerning Technology
- Marxs concept of alienation bears striking
similarity to Heideggers view that the essence
of technology is the reduction of Beings to
standing reserve. - In The Question Concerning Technology, Heidegger
distinguishes between techne (the bringing-forth
of something out of itself, a revealing, in the
form of the activities and skills of the
craftsperson but also the work of the fine arts
the bringing forth of the true into the
beautiful) and the essence of technology (a
challenging-forth, in which everything is ordered
about to stand by and thereby reduced to
standing reserve). - The essence of technology permits only this one
manner of revealing it buries and denies other
ways of Being it is a kind of banishment of the
self. - While important differences exist between Marx
and Heidegger (Heidegger almost never engaged
with Marx, and Heideggers phenomenology is
neither materialistic nor ideologically critical
of capitalism), both raise important questions
about how technology alters the experience of
Being.
15Implications for Research on Work
- What is work? Is all work alienating? How might
technologically mediated work exacerbate
alienation? - How is alienation experienced? How is it
expressed? How is it subverted? - Is abolishing alienated labour (e.g., Schwalbe,
1986) a reasonable goal? As an HR practice? As
part of a Marxist revolution? - How might an understanding of alienation advance
IR/HR theory? How might it advance its practice?
16Conclusion
- A phenomenological analysis of alienation
contributes to the development of IR/HR theory in
a variety of ways - It provides insight into aspects of work that
empirical approaches do not (and perhaps cannot)
account for. - It encourages us to take the lived experiences of
workers seriously to see workers as something
more than human capital, human resources or
standing reserve and to think about the
meanings of work. - It requires a re-thinking of the perspectives and
presumptions that inform our thinking and doing,
whether as IR/HR practitioners or scholars. - It seeks to integrate seemingly disparate corners
of IR/HR research and thought (e.g., HRM, Marxian
thought, questions about technology,
phenomenological method, etc.) and in doing so
seeks to both challenge and further them. - It prompts consideration of the kinds of
epistemological and ontological questions IR must
tackle if it is to succeed as a discipline.
17Work \ werk \ n ME werk, work, fr. OE werc,
weorc
- Activity in which one exerts strength or
faculties to do or perform something sustained
physical or mental effort to overcome obstacles
and achieve an objective or result the labour,
task, or duty that is ones accustomed means of
livelihood energy expended by natural phenomena
something that results from the use or
fashioning of a particular material structures
in engineering or mining a place where
industrial labour is carried on the working or
moving parts of a mechanism something produced
or accomplished by effort, exertion, or exercise
of skill something produced by the exercise of
creative talent or expenditure of creative
effort artistic production performance of
moral or religious acts the material or piece
of material that is operated upon at any stage in
the process of manufacture everything
possessed, available, or belonging subjection
to drastic treatment engaged in working
having effect in process of preparation to
bring to pass to set or keep in motion to
solve by reasoning - Source Merriam-Websters Collegiate Dictionary,
10th ed. (2002)
18Sources
- Adams, Roy, 1988. Desperately Seeking Industrial
Relations Theory. The International Journal of
Comparative Labour Law and Industrial Relations,
4(1) 1-10. - Burston, Daniel, 1998. Laing and Heedegger on
Alienation. Journal of Humanistic Psychology,
36(4) 80-93. - Eldred, Michael, 2000. Capital and Technology
Marx and Heidegger. Cologne, Germany Artefact.
Available electronically at http//www.webcom.com/
artefact/capiteen.html - Godard, John, 1994. Beyond Empiricism Towards a
Reconstruction of IR Theory and Research.
Advances in Industrial and Labor Relations, - Godard, John, 1989. Beyond Empiricism
Alternative Philosophies of Science and the Study
of Industrial Relations. Queens University, - Kateb, George, 1997. Technology and Philosophy.
Social Research, 64(3) 1225-1246. - Kleinberg-Levin, David, 2005. The Invisible Hands
of Capital and Labour Using Merleau-Pontys
phenomenology to understand the meaning of
alienation in Marxs theory of manual labour.
Philosophy and Social Criticism, 31(1) 53-67. - Kovacs, George, 1986. Phenomenology of Work and
Self-Transcendence. The Journal of Value Inquiry,
20 195-207. - Marsden, Richard, 1982. Industrial Relations A
Critique of Empiricism. Sociology, 16(2)
232-250.
19- Mende, Jens, 2005. The Poverty of Empiricism.
Informing Science Journal, Volume 8 189-210. - Napoleon, Karen Cheryl Gaimon, 2004. The
Creation of Output and Quality in Services A
Framework to Analyze Information
Technology-Worker Systems. Production and
Operations Management, 13(3) 245-260. - Rinehart, James W., 1996. The Tyranny of Work
Alienation and the Labour Process. 3rd edition.
Toronto Harcourt Brace Canada. - Schwalbe, Michael L., 1986. The Psychosocial
Consequences of Natural and Alienated Labor.
Albany State University of New York Press. - Waugh, William L., Jr., and Wesley W. Waugh,
2004. Phenomenology and Public Administration.
International Journal of Organization Theory and
Behavior, 7(3) 405-432. - White, John, 1997. Education and the End of Work
A New Philosophy of Work and Learning. London
Cassell. - Zuboff, Shoshana, 1988. In the Age of the Smart
Machine The Future of Work and Power. New York
Basic Books.
20Further Information
- This ongoing research is documented on-line at
- http//individual.utoronto.ca/alharris/phenomenolo
gy_of_work.html - See also related phenomenological field research
on life and work at - http//individual.utoronto.ca/alharris/life_and_wo
rk.html