Title: Lecture 22
1Lecture 22
- Pragmatics and the Analysis of Literature
2A Note on the Readings
- Essential reading for this lecture is
- Chapter 6 of Elizabeth Closs Traugott and Mary
Louise Pratt's Linguistics for Students of
Literature (New York Harcourt, 1980).
3Supplementary readings
- Malcolm Coulthard, An Introduction to Discourse
Analysis 2nd edition (London Longman, 1985)
Geoffrey N. Leech, Principles of Pragmatics
(London Longman, 1983) and Stephen C.
Levinson, Pragmatics (Cambridge CUP, 1983).
4Some Preliminary Observations
- Pragmatics, as you know from your discourse
analysis or text and knowledge course last year,
is quite often contrasted with semantics. - The discipline in fact came into existence due to
the realisation that formal semantics was not a
sufficient instrument for the analysis of meaning
in language.
5Semantics vs Pragmatics
- As some of you may know, semantics is
conventionally taken to be the study of meaning
in language per se, whereas one definition of
pragmatics is is that it is the study of
linguistic meaning in context - However, the distinction between semantics and
pragmatics based on meaning in language and
linguistic meaning in context, is not always
clearcut, and there are some borderline cases
where one is not sure if a meaningful feature of
language should be analysed in terms of semantics
or pragmatics or both.
6Semantics and Pragmatics Divide Some Reservations
- There are also some linguists who believe that
the distinction between semantics and pragmatics
is an unnecessary one, as many of the issues in
pragmatics can be dealt with within semantics,
which to them, should be defined more widely.
7Semantics and Pragmatics Divide Hallidays
Reservations
- Halliday, in spite of his belief that meaning in
language should be analysed in context, holds the
view that a separate pragmatic component in
linguistics is unnecessary, as many of the issues
in pragmatics can actually be dealt with within
the semantic or grammatical framework of his
linguistic approach - Eg. Halliday's treatment of speech acts in
relation to grammatical metaphor, which we have
seen in the previous lecture.
8Pragmatics Further Reservations
- However, some other linguists hold the view that
strictly speaking, pragmatics is not a linguistic
discipline, and linguists, if they are interested
in meaning in language, should thus not study it.
- To them, meaning, if it is to be approached
linguistically, should be analysed within
language, and not in relation either to
extra-linguistic contexts -- as in some branches
of pragmatics -- or to surface structural
features -- as in ethnomethodology.
9Pragmatics and Speech
- A major part of pragmatics has to do with speech
events and speech in general. - Although the pragmatics of written language does
exist, it appears that speech is paradigmatic in
pragmatics, and written language is less
significant.
10Pragmatics and the Interpersonal Metafunction
- As a corollary to the importance of speech, the
interpersonal meta-function of language appears
to be more important than the other
meta-functions.
11Pragmatics and the Other Metafunctions
- However, the other meta-functions also play a
part for example, - The ideational metafunction (when viewed in terms
of the addresser's or addressee's intentions),
although not linguistically or grammatically
realised in the strict sense, does seem to be a
factor in the analysis of both speech acts and
Gricean implicatures - the textual meta-function (in terms of adjacency
or more holistic discoursal patterns) does play a
part in the ethnomethodological approach to
discourse, as this approach puts a high premium
on the structure of discourse, at the expense of
speakers' intentions.
12Pragmatics as the Study of Meaning in Context
- Context is something difficult to pin-point.
- The understanding of literary works may actually
be dependent on cultural contexts which cannot
actually be found in the text - The contexts of meaning in literary works may, in
effect, be more elusive than those of spontaneous
speech.
13Further Difficulty in Literary Works
- Other features which may either be scant or
absent in written literary texts, are the
paralinguistic and kinesic elements or indicators
which may help us to disambiguate or clarify the
more exact meaning of some utterances.
14Intended Meaning
- One reason for trying to look at paralinguistic
and extra-linguistic clues in order to put
meaning in context, has to do with the attempt to
get at the intended meaning of an utterance. - This is a dominant consideration in some
approaches in pragmatics, especially in the
analysis of speech acts and implicatures.
15Intended Meaning Problems
- However, one may face serious philosophical and
linguistic difficulties in trying to arrive at
the intention of what has been uttered - The intended meaning may not have been realised
- in the text,
- or -- perhaps more importantly -- it is not
realised in the minds of the addressees - or -- as in the case of literary works -- in the
minds of the interpreters or readers of the text.
16Authorial Intention
- There may be a disjunction between intended and
realised meanings. - Some literary critics have labelled the attempt
to arrive at the intention of the author the
intentional fallacy.
17Authorial Intention The Intentional Fallacy
- Whether we agree or disagree with the intentional
fallacy, it does appear that the attempt to do a
pragmatic analysis of authorial intention is not
usually a viable task. - It is usually more practical to analyse a
character's or, possibly, the narrator's
intention(s) in the pragmatic analysis of a
literary work.
18Intentions as Realised in the Text
- In relation to character's or narrator's
intentions, one does not usually bother about
completely invisible intentions, but one analyses
those intentions which are at least apparent from
the contexts available from or suggested by the
text.
19Speech Acts
- The first significant work on linguistic
pragmatics was done by the philosopher J. L.
Austin. - It is to Austin that we must attribute the first
systematic attempt to formally and clearly
pin-point the shortcomings of formal semantics in
the analysis of meaning in language.
20Austins View
- According to Austin, there is quite often
something which lies beyond the superficial
contextless meaning of words, which will give us
a more complete picture of meaning in language.
He calls this the performative, which refers to
some kind of action which is deemed to have been
performed by saying something. - The performative is contrasted to the constative,
which refers to meaning which is viewed in
truth-conditional terms, and which has been the
traditional concern of philosophical semantics.
21Formal vs Functional
- What Austin initiated in the analysis of
language, was the disjunction between the formal
and functional (or preferably perhaps,
performative) approaches to the analysis of
meaning,
22Speech Acts Metaphor
- In Halliday's example, the statement 'I wouldn't
do this if I was you', has the congruent force of
an imperative 'Don't do it!'. - From the perspective of speech act theory
however, viewing the clause 'I wouldn't do this
if I was you' as a declarative, is to view it in
constative terms, whereas the performative
approach will view the statement as having the
force of a command, warning, etc., and not merely
a statement of fact.
23Implicit Explicit Performatives
- One distinction Austin makes in relation to
performatives, is that between - implicit performatives and
- explicit performatives.
- Created by adding in what is called the
performative verb before the clause. If the
clause is not declarative, this will involve its
grammatical conversion into a declarative clause
(or a clause complex with declarative
components) 'I warn you not to do it', 'I order
you not to do it', 'I advise you not to do it'
etc.
24Implicit Performatives
- As performatives are seldom uttered using the
performative verb, it does seem to be the case
that most of the performatives we encounter in
the English language are implicit. - Another and perhaps more frequently encountered
term used for implicit performatives in speech
act theory, is indirect speech acts. - We may add here that the disjunction between
intended and actual illocutionary force is more
likely to occur with indirect speech acts.
25(No Transcript)
26John Searle's classification
- directives,
- commissives,
- expressives,
- representatives, and
- declarations (or declaratives, which we will not
use, as the term may be confused with
declaratives in grammar, which are defined
constatively, and not performatively).
27Stylistic Significance
- The discrepancy, and to a certain extent also,
the consonance, between grammatical clause types
and pragmatic utterance types, may be of
significance in one's stylistic analysis.
28- The room was dull and threadbare, and the
snow outside seemed fairy-like by comparison, so
white on the lawn and tufted on the bushes.
Indoors, the heavy pictures hung obscurely on the
walls, everything was dingy with gloom.
29- Except in the fireglow, where they had
laid the bath on the hearth. Mrs Massy, her black
hair always smoothly coiled and queenly, kneeled
by the bath, wearing a rubber apron, and holding
the kicking child. Her husband stood holding the
towels and the flannels to warm. Louisa, too
cross to share in the joy of the baby's bath, was
laying the table. The boy was hanging on the
door-knob, wrestling with it to get out. His
father looked round.
30Directive
- 'Come away from the door, Jack,' he said
ineffectually. Jack tugged harder at the knob as
if he did not hear. Mr Massy blinked at
him. 'He must come away from the door,
Mary,' he said. 'There will be a draught if it is
opened.' 'Jack, come away from the door, dear,'
said the mother, dexterously turning the shiny
wet baby on to her towelled knee, then glancing
round 'Go and tell Auntie Louisa about the
train.'
31- Louisa, also afraid to open the door, was
watching the scene on the hearth. Mr Massy stood
holding the baby's flannel, as if assisting at
some ceremonial. If everybody had not been
subduedly angry, it would have been
ridiculous. 'I want to see out of the
window,' Jack said. His father turned
hastily. 'Do you mind lifting him on to a
chair, Louisa,' said Mary hastily. The father was
too delicate.
Commissive
Directive
32- When the baby was flannelled, Mr Massy
went upstairs and returned with four pillows,
which he set in the fender to warm. Then he stood
watching the mother feed her child, obsessed by
the idea of his infant. Louisa went on
with her preparations for the meal. She could not
have told why she was so sullenly angry. Mrs
Lindley, as usual, lay silently
watching. Mary carried her child upstairs,
followed by her husband with the pillows. After a
while he came down again.
33Commissive
Directive 2 senses?
- 'What is Mary doing? Why doesn't she come
down to eat?' asked Mrs Lindley. 'She is
staying with baby. The room is rather cold. I
will ask the girl to put in a fire.' He was going
absorbedly to the door. 'But Mary has had
nothing to eat. It is she who will catch cold,'
said the mother, exasperated. Mr Massy
seemed as if he did not hear. Yet he looked at
his mother-in-law, and answered. 'I will
take her something.'
34- He went out. Mrs Lindley shifted on her
couch with anger. Miss Louisa glowered. But no
one said anything, because of the money that came
to the vicarage from Mr Massy. Louisa went
upstairs. Her sister was sitting by the bed,
reading a scrap of paper. 'Won't you come
down and eat?' the younger asked.
Directive
35Commissive
- 'In a moment or two,' Mary replied in a
quiet, reserved voice, that forbade anyone to
approach her. - It was this that made Miss Louisa most
furious. She went downstairs, and announced to
her mother 'I am going out. I may not be
home to tea.'
Commissive/Expressive