Semantics II - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 23
About This Presentation
Title:

Semantics II

Description:

Meaning2: He is beautiful, and he is a dancer (he might dance poorly) ... of beautiful dancers here. B: Yes, but Mary is the only beautiful beautiful dancer. ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:66
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 24
Provided by: artsands
Category:
Tags: semantics

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: Semantics II


1
Semantics II
  • Interpreting Language (with Logic)

2
Primary Objectives
  • Continue our study of how meanings in natural
    language are
  • Represented
  • Constructed
  • Two examples
  • More on adjectives, sets, etc.
  • How quantification with every, some, etc. is
    represented

3
Background
  • Recall that the guiding principle for studying
    objects larger than single terminals is that
    meanings are built out of their constituent
    parts
  • Principle of Compositionality The meaning of a
    whole is a function of the meaning of the parts
    and of the way they are syntactically combined.
    (associated with Frege cf. Partee reading)
  • Note crucially that there are two components to
    this
  • What the parts mean
  • How the parts are combined
  • We will review these two components with
    reference to some of the adjective examples we
    studied last time

4
The Meaning of the Parts
  • Recall that for some adjectives, we made use of
    the idea that the interpretation of ADJ N
    involved intersection
  • RULE (informal) When an adjective A modifies a
    noun N (A N), the interpretation of this object
    is the set defined by the intersection of As
    meaning with Ns meaning
  • This rule accounts for the interpretation of e.g.
    red book, as the intersection of two sets.

5
Other types of adjectives
  • We saw one type of adjective that is not
    (necessarily) intersective before
  • Larry is a skillful artist.
  • Larry is a chess player
  • Therefore Larry is a skillful chess player.
    (Doesnt work)
  • So one thing that we have to know is what kind of
    adjective we are dealing with
  • In addition, well need to know what syntactic
    structure we have

6
Recall
  • From last time as well
  • Larry is a poisonous snake
  • Larry is a chess player.
  • Therefore Larry is a poisonous chess player
  • The phrase poisonous chess player is ambiguousit
    can also mean that hes not poisonous per se, but
    as a chess player, he is.

7
For example
  • So, with poisonous chess player, it seems that
    some adjectives can be interpreted in either
    fashion. Here its more transparent
  • Larry is a beautiful dancer.
  • Meaning1 He dances beautifully
  • Meaning2 He is beautiful, and he is a dancer (he
    might dance poorly)
  • Question Do these differences involve different
    structures, or just a lexically ambiguous set of
    adjectives??

8
Further considerations
  • Could we have contexts like the following?
  • A There are lots of beautiful dancers here.
  • B Yes, but Mary is the only beautiful beautiful
    dancer.
  • If so, which adjective is the one with the
    dances beautifully interpretation, and which
    carries the is a beautiful person meaning?
  • Consider further
  • John is the only ugly beautiful dancer.
  • John is the only beautiful ugly dancer.
  • Question (for thought) Does this mean that the
    difference is reducible to structure?

9
Still another type
  • Consider a further type of adjective
  • John is a former chess player.
  • Adjectives like former (including alleged,
    counterfeit, etc.) are
  • Not intersective former chess player is not
    the intersection of former and chess
    player
  • Not like skillful type adjectives either
  • skillful chess player is a subset of chess
    player
  • But former chess player is not a subset of
    chess player
  • Aside John is tall/skillful/former
  • All of these things are syntactically Adjectives
    but how they combine to create larger meanings is
    determined in part by how they differ from one
    another
  • How to represent such differences goes beyond
    what well do at this point, we will examine a
    second factor, syntactic structure

10
Structure
  • One simple case illustrating structural
    differences involves adjectives combining with
    nouns either (1) in phrases, vs. (2) in
    compounds.
  • Example
  • Phrase black board. Meaning here it is
    intersective (a thing that is both black and a
    board)
  • Compound bláckboard. Meaning thing that we
    write on with chalk. Not intersective! A
    blackboard could be e.g. green.
  • So how things are put together is crucial.
  • In a sense, this recapitulates what we saw in our
    study of word structure and syntax (remember
    unlockable and fix the car with a wrench)
    the ambiguities correspond to different
    structures

11
Other examples of structure
  • Consider some further examples
  • John hammered the metal.
  • John hammered the metal flat.
  • In the second example, the adjective flat defines
    the state that the metal moves towards by being
    hammered.
  • Now, how about
  • John hammered the metal.
  • John hammered the metal naked.
  • In the second example here, we understand the
    adjective as defining the state that John was in
    when he undertook the hammering of the metal
  • However, the structural position of modifiers
    like the naked adjective is in principle
    compatible with both subject and object
  • John met Bill naked. (John or Bill)

12
However.
  • When things like naked appear in the VP, they can
    be interpreted with either the subject or the
    object, if it makes sense
  • Interestingly Further examples show that the
    flat type adjectives and the naked type are in
    different syntactic positions
  • John hammered the metal flat naked.
  • John hammered the metal naked flat.
  • The second example is deviant because it seems
    that the first of the two adjectives must go with
    the object and in this case, that doesnt make
    sense

13
Interim summary
  • When it comes to building meanings, two primary
    factors must be taken into account
  • What individual elements (e.g. specific classes
    of adjectives in the examples above) mean
  • What syntactic structures these elements appear
    in
  • As we have been noting throughout, there are
    clear correlations between structure and meaning.
    What we have added in this discussion is the
    further idea that what the individual words mean
    can also have an effect on how meanings are
    derived.

14
Quantifiers More Ambiguities
  • Thus far we have seen different ways in which an
    ambiguity may arise
  • Structural ambiguity
  • Unlockable un lock able or un lockable
  • Fix the car with a hammer PP modifies VP, or PP
    modifies NP
  • Lexical ambiguity (from homophony/polysemy)
  • The pool made the party a lot better.
  • swimming pool
  • game of pool
  • entertaining rain puddle
  • Another type of ambiguity is found in (certain)
    sentences with more than one quantifier (like
    every, etc.)
  • Every student read some book.

15
The ambiguity
  • Every student read some book.
  • Reading1 Every student read some book or other
    (different books)
  • Reading2 Every student read the same book
  • Such ambiguities arise in other cases as well
    consider
  • A student is certain to solve this problem.
  • Reading1 Some student or other is going to
    solve this problem
  • Reading 2 A particular student is going to solve
    this problem (e.g. Mary)
  • (think about it)
  • These are often called scope ambiguities see
    below
  • In order to explain the nature of this ambiguity,
    we will look at some simple logic

16
Interpreting Quantifiers
  • Understanding the nature of the problem here
    requires some assumptions about quantifiers.
  • In logical analysis, quantifiers are interpreted
    with respect to some domain think of this as a
    world. Well introduce a restricted world below.
  • Quantifiers dont seem to refer to things in the
    way that things like cat do. Consider
  • No students went to the library.
  • What would no students refer to??
  • In order to see how quantifiers are interpreted,
    it is useful to have a small domain (think of it
    like a model) to look at what our logical
    statements mean
  • I choose.

17
A restricted domain
  • Lets illustrate with respect to a simple domain
    how the quantifiers work.
  • We have a domain (in this example, a set of
    characters from Sesame Street)

Bert couldnt make it.
18
Back to reality some basic logic
  • In our logic, we need names for individuals
  • ernie ? Ernie
  • bb ? Big bird
  • elmo ? Elmo
  • Etc
  • We also need predicates, which are sets of
    individuals e.g., red, blue, googly-eyed these
    apply to one argument (see below)
  • These predicates represent sets, like in our
    adjective examples in this world
  • blue grover, cookie monster
  • googly-eyed cookie monster
  • Etc.
  • We can then write simple statements, and judge
    whether or not they are true with respect to our
    model

19
Example statements
  • Some things that we could say (with truth value)
  • Blue(cm) cookie monster is blue true
  • Red(bb) big bird is red false
  • And so on
  • We can also have predicates with two places e.g.
    Taller(x,y) for x is taller than y
  • Taller(bb,cm) true (big bird is taller than
    cookie monster)
  • Within this system, we can also define and,
    or, not, ifthen e.g. blue(cm) AND
    red(elmo)
  • How are we going to say things like some things
    are red, no thing is an NBA player, and so on?
    This is where we need a way of representing
    quantifiers

20
Two quantifiers
  • Quantifiers come with variables, presented here
    as x, y, etc.
  • Existential Quantification
  • This is written with a backwards E
  • It is read as there exists an x such that
  • Example ?x BLUE(x)
  • This means there exists an x such that x is
    blue
  • In our model, this is true we can find
    individuals in the denotation of BLUE
  • The other quantifier we need is one that says
    every

21
Universal Quantification
  • Universal Quantification Represents in logical
    the meaning of every or all
  • This is written with an upside-down A
  • Example (let the predicate Ses be is a Sesame
    Street character)
  • ?x Ses(x)
  • This is read as for all x, x is a Sesame Street
    character
  • This is true in our model, but not in other
    models, e.g. the real word.
  • Meanings like no involve the quantifiers above
    and negation

22
Now, Returning to two Quantifiers
  • Remember that we launched into this investigation
    of logic in order to understand the two meanings
    of examples like Every student read some book.
    Simplifying
  • Every student read some book.
  • To simplify, well look at
  • Everyone saw someone
  • Which has the same ambiguity
  • In our logic, the two readings have unambiguous
    statements

23
Representing the readings
  • Reading1 Everyone saw some person or other
  • ? x ?y (Saw(x,y))
  • Read as For all x, there exists some y such
    that x saw y
  • Reading 2 Everyone saw the same person.
  • ?y ? x (Saw(x,y))
  • Read as There exists a y such that for all x, x
    saw y
  • The question for research in natural language
    semantics is how a single sentence/structure like
    that of Everyone saw someone can have or
    correspond to these distinct logical
    representations
  • That is, why is it that the single sentence, with
    someone as object, can correspond to a meaning
    in which the existential quantifier is outside of
    the universal?
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com