How close should experiments be to models and why - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 18
About This Presentation
Title:

How close should experiments be to models and why

Description:

Economics experiments tend to resemble formal models. Officially, this allays external ... So problems of causal holism are intertwined with relationality: ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:31
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 19
Provided by: nb6
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: How close should experiments be to models and why


1
How close should experiments be to models and why?
  • Assessing Experimental Economics(??)
  • by N.Bardsley, R.Cubitt, G.Loomes, P.Moffatt,
    C.Starmer and R.Sugden, forthcoming
  • Economics experiments tend to resemble formal
    models
  • Officially, this allays external validity worries
  • Internal validity extent to which the lab
    results inform us about whats happening in the
    lab
  • External validity extent to which the lab
    results inform us about aspects of the world at
    issue
  • Therefore Internal validity is logically prior

2
The Blame the Theory Defence
  • Vernon Smith (1982) what is most important to
    any particular experiment is that it be relevant
    to its purpose. If its purpose is to test a
    theory, then it is legitimate to ask whether the
    elements of alleged unrealism in the experiment
    are parameters in the theory. If they are not
    parameters of the theory, then the criticism of
    unrealism applies equally to the theory and the
    experiment.
  • In other words if we set up experiments to
    resemble economic models, we give theories their
    best chance. So we can ignore external validity
    if our aim is to test a theory.
  • But consider an example from scientist James
    Lovelock

3
Prof. David M. Bice, Department of Geology,
Pennsylvania State University
http//www.carleton.edu/departments/GEOL/DaveSTELL
A/Daisyworld/daisyworld_model.htm
4
Economic Models as Claim-Ready Sets of
Propositions
  • Theory Tx (compound) claim T about aspect of
    the world x
  • Tx mCx where m is (usually) a set of
    propositions with semantic content appropriate to
    x
  • m is expounded as a set of assumptions or
    stipulations, not assertions about the world
  • C is a predicate relating the model to the world
  • C might be realist, as-if, instrumentalist or
    parable-relating
  • C, and therefore Tx, is often oblique or implicit
  • Cf. Lovelocks explicit Daisyworld rationale to
    demonstrate that purposeful action by nature is
    not necessary for life to regulate the Earths
    temperature. This could work by natural
    selection.
  • Daisyworld is a prop for Gaia theory, which does
    not refer to Daisies as a mechanism at all.

5
Consequences
  • To test a theory by physically setting up the
    model is absurd Gaia theory is a parable about
    the Earth!
  • Whiteheads (1925) fallacy of misplaced
    concreteness
  • Whether an experimental environment E tests a
    theory depends whether Tx predicts for it
  • This depends on the presence of x, not m that E
    resembles m says nothing about this.
  • It doesnt require intended instances of x
    reference may be unintended

6
The Validity Problem
  • The artificiality of alteration versus that of
    contamination or isolation (Greenwood 1982)
  • Relationality of social phenomena means Tx
    often does not make predictions for the lab
  • E.g. a jury trial requires a judge, and that
    participants recognise the judges formal
    authorisation etc.
  • The experimenters experiment may diverge from
    the subjects experiment (Orne 62, 73) internal
    (and so external) validity requires that the two
    converge
  • Its the subjects experiment(s) that drives
    behaviour
  • Examples Tax evasion experiments, dictator games

7
Tax Compliance and Evasion
  • pi ei tdi Im(1-di) I 1 or 0
  • e.g. Alm et al. 1992 claims evidence that people
    dont pay taxes out of moral / citizenship
    obligation
  • But a tax is a collection of revenue by the
    government, a specific authority authority is
    relational
  • The data are on monetary gambles nothing else is
    there
  • Ockhams razor alternative for taxation
    (insurance c) inferences
  • Reduction E.g. suppose an experiment finds
    dR/dt gt 0 R tSidi
  • But the real tax-revenue relationship may vary
    with the perceived legitimacy of the government
    or tax
  • Seen as Legitimate dR/dt gt 0 Illegitimate
    dR/dt lt 0
  • So problems of causal holism are intertwined with
    relationality
  • Tax-revenue-government-electorate-citizenship

8
Dictator Game
Bardsley (2008) Dictator Game Giving Altruism or
Artefact? Experimental Economics, 11 (2)
9
Taking Game
Bardsley (2008) Dictator Game Giving Altruism or
Artefact? Experimental Economics, 11 (2)
10
Challenge Demand Characteristics
  • Experimentalists Cant dismiss results of an
    experiment because DCs might be a problem
  • Sceptic DC confounds might be frequent
  • Cf Placebo effects in medicine
  • Observations
  • DCs seem plausible in some cases, not in others
  • Need for theorising about where DCs are likely to
    be (un-)problematic (e.g. inscrutable
    hypothesis?)
  • Need for empirical checking for DCs (à la Orne)

11
Theories and Domains (Cubitt 2005)
Testing Domain
Base Domain
Intended Domain
12
Theories and Domains (Cubitt 2005)
Testing Domain
Base Domain
Intended Domain
13
Theories and Domains
x in mCx
Testing Domain
Base Domain
Intended Domain
14
Reflections on BTT and Falsificationism
  • BTT may still be valid if the experiment does
    implement x in Tx
  • E.g. most experiments on individual choice theory
    locate the design in the base domain of the
    theory, by using well-defined probabilities and
    outcomes for choices. Arguably, hyothetical
    designs (psychology) do not.
  • But without induction, we must say that failure
    of the theory in the lab is no guide to its
    future performance either in the field or the
    lab!
  • Empirical work refines theories. Falsificationism
    is blind to this
  • If we always give the theory its best chance
  • 1. We may end up inductively refining our
    theories around phenomena that are externally
    rare, getting locked into our own little
    world(s).
  • 2. Success of the theory in the lab might be
    uninformative about its performance in the field.
  • Therefore even where BTT is valid for an
    individual design there are good reasons to be
    doing less model-constrained work.

15
Validity of BTT defence
  • Naïve Experimental Claim
  • Any laboratory environment E in the base domain
    of a theory should be presumed to be in the
    T-domain
  • Modified Experimental Claim
  • unless there is some difference between E and the
    I-domain, which can reasonably be expected to
    make behaviour in the I-domain markedly more
    consistent with the theory (Cubitt, 2005,
    Bardsley et al. 2008).
  • Proposed further modification
  • or in the case of bold, Popperian testing, which
    can reasonably be expected to make behaviour in
    the I-domain less consistent with the theory
    (proposed further modification)
  • NB E is in base domain only if Tx predicts for E
  • Implementation of m is neither necessary nor
    sufficient

16
Is there a trade-off between EV and IV?
  • local vs. broader EV IV?local EV, absent demand
    problems
  • There is a trade-off between internal and
    external validity involving conditional
    probability
  • Own little world designs may score highly on IV
    and weakly on broader EV
  • Designs closer to naturally-occurring situations
    make internal validity harder to achieve e.g.
    free communication erodes statistical
    independence. But conditional on achieving it we
    may be more confident that the results hold
    outside the lab.
  • This trade-off is about harnessing local EV to
    induct to situations of interest. Justifying
    claims to broader external validity is
    problematic even in the philosophy of natural
    science (Bruno Latour, Nancy Cartwright,
    Francesco Guala).
  • Very local EV has no meaning in
    model-implementing Applied Economics designs,
    literally interpreted.

17
Conclusions How close should experiments be to
models and why?
  • Theres no requirement for designs to resemble
    models for testing, the requirement is for the
    theory to predict for the design
  • Proximity to a model may reduce internal ( so
    external) validity, since implementing the model
    may miss the target of Tx entirely
  • Where designs do implement phenomena of interest,
    one may wish to give the theory its best chance
    by sticking to its base domain
  • But thats just one experimental strategy, we
    need more to break out of own little worlds
    let a thousand flowers bloom!
  • Evidential claims of model-implementing AE
    designs are suspect unless couched as
    decision-theoretic and analogical
  • Such analogical claims may be unconvincing
    because of their reductive nature, and
    differences between human subjects and target
    entities

18
References
  • Alm, J. McClelland, G.H. and Schulze, W.D. 1992.
    Why do people pay taxes? Journal of Public
    Economics, 48, 21-38.
  • Bardsley, Nicholas 2008. Dictator game giving
    altruism or artefact? Experimental Economics, 11,
    122-133.
  • Bardsley, N., Cubitt, R., Loomes, G., Moffatt,
    P., Starmer, C. and Sugden, R. 2008. Assessing
    Experimental Economics (working title),
    forthcoming.
  • Cubitt, Robin P. 2005. Experiments and the domain
    of economic theory, Journal of Economic
    Methodology, 12, 197-210.
  • Greenwood, J.D. 1982. On the relation between
    laboratory experiments and social behaviour
    causal explanation and generalisation, Journal of
    the Theory of Social Behaviour, 12, 225-249.
  • Lovelock, J. 2005. Gaia Medicine for an Ailing
    Planet. Gaia books.
  • Orne, M.T. 1962 On the social psychology of the
    psychological experiment with particular
    reference to demand characteristics and their
    implications, American Psychologist, 17, 11,
    776-783.
  • Orne, M.T. 1973 Communication by the total
    experimental situation in P. Pliner, L.Krames and
    T. Alloway (eds.) Communication and Affect, 2nd
    edition, 157-191, New York Academic Press.
  • Smith, V.L. 1982. Microeconomic systems as an
    experimental science, American Economic Review,
    72, 923-955.
  • Whitehead, A.N. 1925 (1919). An Enquiry
    concerning the Principles of Natural Knowledge
    2nd ed. Cambridge University Press.
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com