Title: How close should experiments be to models and why
1How close should experiments be to models and why?
- Assessing Experimental Economics(??)
- by N.Bardsley, R.Cubitt, G.Loomes, P.Moffatt,
C.Starmer and R.Sugden, forthcoming - Economics experiments tend to resemble formal
models - Officially, this allays external validity worries
- Internal validity extent to which the lab
results inform us about whats happening in the
lab - External validity extent to which the lab
results inform us about aspects of the world at
issue - Therefore Internal validity is logically prior
2The Blame the Theory Defence
- Vernon Smith (1982) what is most important to
any particular experiment is that it be relevant
to its purpose. If its purpose is to test a
theory, then it is legitimate to ask whether the
elements of alleged unrealism in the experiment
are parameters in the theory. If they are not
parameters of the theory, then the criticism of
unrealism applies equally to the theory and the
experiment. - In other words if we set up experiments to
resemble economic models, we give theories their
best chance. So we can ignore external validity
if our aim is to test a theory. - But consider an example from scientist James
Lovelock
3Prof. David M. Bice, Department of Geology,
Pennsylvania State University
http//www.carleton.edu/departments/GEOL/DaveSTELL
A/Daisyworld/daisyworld_model.htm
4Economic Models as Claim-Ready Sets of
Propositions
- Theory Tx (compound) claim T about aspect of
the world x - Tx mCx where m is (usually) a set of
propositions with semantic content appropriate to
x - m is expounded as a set of assumptions or
stipulations, not assertions about the world - C is a predicate relating the model to the world
- C might be realist, as-if, instrumentalist or
parable-relating - C, and therefore Tx, is often oblique or implicit
- Cf. Lovelocks explicit Daisyworld rationale to
demonstrate that purposeful action by nature is
not necessary for life to regulate the Earths
temperature. This could work by natural
selection. -
- Daisyworld is a prop for Gaia theory, which does
not refer to Daisies as a mechanism at all.
5Consequences
- To test a theory by physically setting up the
model is absurd Gaia theory is a parable about
the Earth! - Whiteheads (1925) fallacy of misplaced
concreteness - Whether an experimental environment E tests a
theory depends whether Tx predicts for it - This depends on the presence of x, not m that E
resembles m says nothing about this. - It doesnt require intended instances of x
reference may be unintended
6The Validity Problem
- The artificiality of alteration versus that of
contamination or isolation (Greenwood 1982) - Relationality of social phenomena means Tx
often does not make predictions for the lab - E.g. a jury trial requires a judge, and that
participants recognise the judges formal
authorisation etc. - The experimenters experiment may diverge from
the subjects experiment (Orne 62, 73) internal
(and so external) validity requires that the two
converge - Its the subjects experiment(s) that drives
behaviour - Examples Tax evasion experiments, dictator games
7Tax Compliance and Evasion
- pi ei tdi Im(1-di) I 1 or 0
- e.g. Alm et al. 1992 claims evidence that people
dont pay taxes out of moral / citizenship
obligation - But a tax is a collection of revenue by the
government, a specific authority authority is
relational - The data are on monetary gambles nothing else is
there - Ockhams razor alternative for taxation
(insurance c) inferences - Reduction E.g. suppose an experiment finds
dR/dt gt 0 R tSidi - But the real tax-revenue relationship may vary
with the perceived legitimacy of the government
or tax - Seen as Legitimate dR/dt gt 0 Illegitimate
dR/dt lt 0 - So problems of causal holism are intertwined with
relationality - Tax-revenue-government-electorate-citizenship
8Dictator Game
Bardsley (2008) Dictator Game Giving Altruism or
Artefact? Experimental Economics, 11 (2)
9Taking Game
Bardsley (2008) Dictator Game Giving Altruism or
Artefact? Experimental Economics, 11 (2)
10Challenge Demand Characteristics
- Experimentalists Cant dismiss results of an
experiment because DCs might be a problem - Sceptic DC confounds might be frequent
- Cf Placebo effects in medicine
- Observations
- DCs seem plausible in some cases, not in others
- Need for theorising about where DCs are likely to
be (un-)problematic (e.g. inscrutable
hypothesis?) - Need for empirical checking for DCs (Ã la Orne)
11Theories and Domains (Cubitt 2005)
Testing Domain
Base Domain
Intended Domain
12Theories and Domains (Cubitt 2005)
Testing Domain
Base Domain
Intended Domain
13Theories and Domains
x in mCx
Testing Domain
Base Domain
Intended Domain
14Reflections on BTT and Falsificationism
- BTT may still be valid if the experiment does
implement x in Tx - E.g. most experiments on individual choice theory
locate the design in the base domain of the
theory, by using well-defined probabilities and
outcomes for choices. Arguably, hyothetical
designs (psychology) do not. - But without induction, we must say that failure
of the theory in the lab is no guide to its
future performance either in the field or the
lab! - Empirical work refines theories. Falsificationism
is blind to this - If we always give the theory its best chance
- 1. We may end up inductively refining our
theories around phenomena that are externally
rare, getting locked into our own little
world(s). - 2. Success of the theory in the lab might be
uninformative about its performance in the field. - Therefore even where BTT is valid for an
individual design there are good reasons to be
doing less model-constrained work.
15Validity of BTT defence
- Naïve Experimental Claim
- Any laboratory environment E in the base domain
of a theory should be presumed to be in the
T-domain - Modified Experimental Claim
- unless there is some difference between E and the
I-domain, which can reasonably be expected to
make behaviour in the I-domain markedly more
consistent with the theory (Cubitt, 2005,
Bardsley et al. 2008). - Proposed further modification
- or in the case of bold, Popperian testing, which
can reasonably be expected to make behaviour in
the I-domain less consistent with the theory
(proposed further modification) - NB E is in base domain only if Tx predicts for E
- Implementation of m is neither necessary nor
sufficient
16Is there a trade-off between EV and IV?
- local vs. broader EV IV?local EV, absent demand
problems - There is a trade-off between internal and
external validity involving conditional
probability - Own little world designs may score highly on IV
and weakly on broader EV - Designs closer to naturally-occurring situations
make internal validity harder to achieve e.g.
free communication erodes statistical
independence. But conditional on achieving it we
may be more confident that the results hold
outside the lab. - This trade-off is about harnessing local EV to
induct to situations of interest. Justifying
claims to broader external validity is
problematic even in the philosophy of natural
science (Bruno Latour, Nancy Cartwright,
Francesco Guala). - Very local EV has no meaning in
model-implementing Applied Economics designs,
literally interpreted.
17Conclusions How close should experiments be to
models and why?
- Theres no requirement for designs to resemble
models for testing, the requirement is for the
theory to predict for the design - Proximity to a model may reduce internal ( so
external) validity, since implementing the model
may miss the target of Tx entirely - Where designs do implement phenomena of interest,
one may wish to give the theory its best chance
by sticking to its base domain - But thats just one experimental strategy, we
need more to break out of own little worlds
let a thousand flowers bloom! - Evidential claims of model-implementing AE
designs are suspect unless couched as
decision-theoretic and analogical - Such analogical claims may be unconvincing
because of their reductive nature, and
differences between human subjects and target
entities
18References
- Alm, J. McClelland, G.H. and Schulze, W.D. 1992.
Why do people pay taxes? Journal of Public
Economics, 48, 21-38. - Bardsley, Nicholas 2008. Dictator game giving
altruism or artefact? Experimental Economics, 11,
122-133. - Bardsley, N., Cubitt, R., Loomes, G., Moffatt,
P., Starmer, C. and Sugden, R. 2008. Assessing
Experimental Economics (working title),
forthcoming. - Cubitt, Robin P. 2005. Experiments and the domain
of economic theory, Journal of Economic
Methodology, 12, 197-210. - Greenwood, J.D. 1982. On the relation between
laboratory experiments and social behaviour
causal explanation and generalisation, Journal of
the Theory of Social Behaviour, 12, 225-249. - Lovelock, J. 2005. Gaia Medicine for an Ailing
Planet. Gaia books. - Orne, M.T. 1962 On the social psychology of the
psychological experiment with particular
reference to demand characteristics and their
implications, American Psychologist, 17, 11,
776-783. - Orne, M.T. 1973 Communication by the total
experimental situation in P. Pliner, L.Krames and
T. Alloway (eds.) Communication and Affect, 2nd
edition, 157-191, New York Academic Press. - Smith, V.L. 1982. Microeconomic systems as an
experimental science, American Economic Review,
72, 923-955. - Whitehead, A.N. 1925 (1919). An Enquiry
concerning the Principles of Natural Knowledge
2nd ed. Cambridge University Press.