Title: THE BIOGRAPHY OF THE UNCOVERED SET
1THE BIOGRAPHY OF THE UNCOVERED SET
- Nicholas R. Miller
- April 2007
- Creighton University Talks
2Brief Personal Biography
- Undergraduate government major at Harvard.
- Likes of Gary King, Ken Shepsle, etc,
unimaginable in the Harvard Government Department
of the time. - Two exceptions
- In my sophomore year, I discovered a brand new
book by a Harvard economist Thomas Schelling
Strategy of Conflict, which I found absolutely
fascinating and quite unlike anything I had read
before. - Edward Banfield taught an upper-level/grad course
on Political Economizing with Arrow, Black, and
other on the syllabus. - I sat in on class for first couple of days but
did not take. - Also no math beyond first-year calculus and
analytical geometry, plus some statistics in
latter part of graduate career.
3Brief Personal Biography (cont.)
- Graduate study at Berkeley not Rochester
- There was no formal theory (or methodology)
subfield at the time, and no formal theory course
until 1969. - Nevetheless, I became aware of Arrow, Riker,
Downs, and Buchanan and Tullock within first few
years, and wrote a seminar paper on Downs and
BT. - I hand in mind to write a theoretical
dissertation further developing a theory of party
competition. - After surviving prelims, I undertook a extended
(self-supervised) reading course in formal
political theory - I found the setup of Duncan Blacks Theory of
Committees and Elections especially appealing. - I became very interested in the cyclical majority
phenomenon.
4Brief Personal Biography (cont.)
- In 1968-69, I took the first offering of a course
on Formal Models in Politics, taught by Robert
Axelrod and Michael Leiserson - We read a book by Otomar Bartos (a mathematical
sociologist) on Simple Models of Group Behavior. - It included a chapter on dominance structures
in societies and employed adjacency matrices and
directed graphs and tournaments in particular
to represent and analyze such structures. - A tournament is a complete asymmetric directed
graph.
5Majority Preference Tournaments
- It occurred to me that the eight three-person
dominance patterns also represent the eight
possible majority preference patterns over three
alternatives (e.g., candidates) A, B, and C - By (my) notational convention x is majority
preferred to y (x P y) is indicated by an arrow
from x to y (sometimes the reverse convention is
used). - And by (my) verbal language, x beats y (under
majority rule). - Note that, apart from the labelling of
alternatives, the eight dominance patterns reduce
to just two dominance structures - transitive and cyclical.
- More generally given an odd number of voters with
strong preferences, - a tournament could be used to represent the
majority preference relation, and - some of the that deductions Bartos presented
concerning social dominance structures (many of
which were standard graph-theoretic theorems) had
analogs for majority voting. - In my seminar paper (and prospective dissertation
chapter), I set out to use the tournament
technology to systematize and extend Duncan
Blacks work on committee voting.
6Majority Preference Tournaments (cont.)
- I discovered with some disappointment that
Michael Taylor had already proposed the idea of
applying graph theory to social choice problems. - Nevertheless, the tournament technology allowed
me to make some modest advances in the Black
program. - For example, Black provided an example with three
voters and four alternatives in a cycle of
majority preference showing that, for each
alternative, there was some voting order under
ordinary committee procedure (what we now call
amendment procedure) that would lead to its
winning under sincere voting. - Using the tournament technology, I was able to
extend this result to any odd number of voters
(indeed, the tournament device made it
unnecessary to specify a particular number of
voters) and to any number of alternatives in a
cycle. - This became Proposition 4 in Miller, 1977.
- Michael Taylor, Graph-Theoretical Approaches to
the Theory of Social Choice. Public Choice,
1968. - Nicholas R. Miller, Nicholas R.
Graph-Theoretical Approaches to the Theory of
Voting. American Journal of Political Science,
1977.
7Majority Preference Tournaments
- Clearly, if we have an odd number of voters with
strong preferences over any odd number m of
alternatives, majority preference can be
represented by a tournament with m vertices. - The adjacent figure shows a tournament with eight
vertices. - Moreover, McGarveys Theorem tells us that every
tournament we might construct represents majority
preference for some profile of transitive
preference orderings, one for each of some finite
number of voters. - David McGarvey, "A Theorem on the Construction
of Voting Paradoxes," Econometrica, 1953. - Thus any tournament we might construct represents
a logically possible majority voting situation.
8Majority Voting Tournaments (cont.)
- Since tournament may contain cycles, McGarveys
Theorem also tells us that majority preference
may be cyclical. - In the adjacent figure, it is evident that there
is a cycle of majority preference encompassing
all eight alternatives. - Tournament diagrams drove home a point that I had
not before adequately appreciated - if you arrange four or more points around a
circle and draw arrows around the perimeter so
as to create a cycle encompassing all the points,
this cycle also has an internal structure, - that is, arrows must also extend across the
interior of the circle.
9Majority Voting Tournaments (cont.)
- Moreover, given five points or more, cycles of
given length may have different internal
structures. - Clearly there are a great many other eight-cycles
(with the alternatives remaining in the same
order in the cycles) that have different
interior structures. - These interior structures have important
implications -- in particular, for the covering
relation.
10Condorcet Winners
- An alternative is a Condorcet Winner if and only
if it beats every other alternative. - The previous tournaments, with all-encompassing
cycle, had no Condorcet winners. - But the presence of a Condorcet winner does not
preclude a (less than all-encompassing) cycle in
majority preference.
11Top Cycle Sets
- A top cycle set TC(X) is a minimal set of points
such that every point in TC(X) beats every point
outside TC(X). - If TC(X) includes more than one point (if there
is no CW), TC(X) must contain at least three
points and a complete cycle (hence the name). - Every tournament has a unique top cycle set.
- At one extreme, a CW (if it exists) is the TC
set. - At the other extreme, the TC may be
all-encompassing.
12All Possible Tournament Structures with Four
Alternatives.
- Given four alternatives (and apart from their
labelling), there are just four possible
tourna-ment structures - fully transitive
- a Condorcet winner plus a three-element bottom
cycle - a three element top cycle plus a Condorcet
loser and - an all-encompassing four-element cycle.
- Increasing the number of alternatives beyond four
greatly increases the number of distinct
structural possibilities.
13Amendment Procedure
- Amendment Procedure
- vote on two alternatives, then
- pair the winner with a third alternative, and
- so forth until all alternatives have entered the
voting. - The alternative that survives the final vote is
the winner. - Duncan Black called this ordinary committee
procedure. - Though it is not immediately apparent, this type
of voting resembles the kind of amendment
procedure used in Anglo-American legislatures. - See Nicholas R. Miller, Committees, Agendas, and
Voting, 1995, Chapter 2
14Sincere Voting under Amendment Procedure
- Consider this four-element cyclical tournament.
- Apart from the labelling of alternatives, there
is just one such tournament - If the alternatives are voted on under amendment
procedure in the order zyxv, v wins if voting is
sincere. - THEOREM. No point outside of TC(X) can win under
any voting order. - THEOREM. For every point x in TC(X) set, there
is some voting order that makes x the sincere
winner. - PROOF IDEA. Arrange the TC alternatives in a
cyclical fashion, and let the voting order follow
the cycle upstream. - COROLLARY. An alternative wins under every
voting order if and only if it is the Condorcet
Winner.
15The Powell Amendment (1950s)
- Alternatives
- B the unamended bill federal aid to education
- BA the amended bill (no federal aid to
segregated schools - Q the status quo no federal to education
- Preference Profile
- N Dems S Dems Reps
- BA B Q
- B Q BA
- Q BA B
- Three bloc of voters, none a majority.
- Latin Square (non-value restricted) Matrix each
alternative appears once in each rank. - Cyclical majority preference B beats Q, Q beats
BA, and BA beats B.
16Sincere Voting on the Powell Amendment
- Under standard procedure, the first vote would be
on the question of amending the bill implicitly
B vs. BA. - Then a vote would be taken on the question of
passing the bill (as amended or not) implicitly
B vs. Q or BA vs. Q, depending on the outcome of
the first vote. - Sincere voting the bill is amended (BA beats B)
and then the bill fails (Q beats BA). - But remember that B or BA could be passed under
other voting orders (that might arise under other
parliamentary situations, e.g., if the content of
the Powell Amendment was incorporated in the
original bill and/or if the status quo were
different).
17Strategic Voting on the Powell Amendment
- But shouldnt Northern Democrats (knowing
everybodys prefer-ences or at least the M-P
tournament) realize that the Powell Amendment is
a killer amendment that will defeat the bill if
it is so amended, and therefore vote
strategically (contrary to their sincere
preferences) against the amendment on the initial
vote. - Indeed, if they do so and nothing else changes, B
wins. - Are strategic countermoves available to either
Southern Democrats or Republicans to defeat this
Northern Democratic ploy? - It is evident, that on the final (here second)
vote, no one has a strategic reason to vote
otherwise than sincerely, so - strategic issues arise with respect to the first
vote only. - Southern Democrats are now getting their first
preference, so they have no reason to change
their first vote. - Republicans are now being outvoted by Democrats
on the first vote, so changing their first vote
cant change the outcome. - So strategic (as opposed to sincere) voting
apparently changes the outcome from defeat of the
bill (Q) to passage of the unamended bill (B). - As under sincere voting, changing the voting
order would probably change the strategic voting
outcome.
18Strategic Voting (cont.)
- The prior strategic analysis of the Powell
Amendment voting was rather ad hoc. - In a last-minute addendum to my seminar paper, I
made a stab at deriving a Black-style results
under strategic voting. - Using a three-dimensional normal (or strategic or
matrix) form for a voting game, I was able to
show that the same anything in the Top Cycle can
win result held under strategic voting with
three blocs of voters and three alternatives.
19Matrix Form of a Three-Voter, Three-Alternative
Voting Game (Successive Procedure)
20Strategic Voting (cont.)
- I could also show that the voting orders that led
to victory by a given alternative were different
under sincere and strategic voting and - in particular, under sincere voting the last
alternative (e.g., Q) in a three-alternative
cycle to enter the voting wins, but under
strategic voting the first such alternative
(e.g., B) wins. - But I had no good idea as to how to proceed
beyond three voters and three alternatives in the
strategic voting case.
21Strategic Voting Farquharson
- By the winter of 1970, Robin Farquharsons Theory
of Voting had just been published, and I studied
it eagerly. - His Table of Results in Appendix I confirmed my
results for both sincere and strategic (or
sophisticated) voting in the three-voter
three-alternative case. - But I was completely mystified by his statement
in the Preface that these results . . . can be
readily extended to cover any desired number of
voters and/or alternatives, - I had been using essentially the same kind of
strategic form matrix analysis that Farquharson
was manifestly using in the body of his text, and - I had found it to be impossibly burdensome to
extend to a larger number of voters and/or
alternatives.
22Farquharson (cont.)
- But Farquharson also introduced a device he
called an outcome tree device (a highly
compressed extensive form that well call an
agenda tree) to concisely represent binary
voting games.
23Farquharson (cont.)
- At some point that winter, while staring at such
an agenda tree, I suddenly saw how backwards
induction readily solved binary voting games
when voters are strategic (and know each others
preferences --- or at least the majority
preference tournament). - This logic was later definitively characterized
by McKelvey and Niemi. - Lets see how an agenda tree and backwards
induction can quickly solve the Powell Amendment
strategic voting game. - Richard D. McKelvey and Richard G. Niemi. A
Multistage Game Represen-tation of Sophisticated
Voting for Binary Procedures. Journal of
Economic Theory, 1978.
24Powell Amendment Agenda Treewith Sophisticates
Equivalents
25An Agenda Tree, M-P Tournament, and Backwards
Induction
26Strategic (Sophisticated) Voting
- I now could readily determine the strategic
voting outcome for any number of voters and
relatively many alternatives under any voting
order. - Moreover, it was not even necessary to draw a new
voting tree each time. - I devised an algorithm by which I could quickly
determine the strategic voting outcome for any
M-P tournament and voting order.
27Win Sets
- Note the term win set was introduced in the
early 1980s by Shepsle and Weingast and has
become very standard.
28A Sophisticated Voting Algorithm forAmendment
Procedure
- Label the alternatives x1, x2, . . . , xm
according to the order of voting. - Examine W(xm) if W(xm) is empty, xm is the
winning outcome otherwise, the sophisticated
outcome belongs to W(xm). - Examine TCW(xm) if this top cycle is a
one-element set or has a top element, say xg,
xg is the winning outcome otherwise, the
sophisticated outcome belongs to TCW(xm) and
depends on which alternative in this set comes
last in the voting order designate this
alternative xk. - Alternative xk cannot be the outcome examine the
intersection W(xk) with TCW(xm) and, more
particularly, the top cycle of this intersection
if this top cycle is a one-element set, say xh,
xh is the outcome otherwise, the outcome belongs
to this top cycle and depends on which
alternative in it comes last in the voting order. - And so forth. (Since A is a finite set, and
since the set of possible decisions is reduced at
each stage, the method must terminate at some
stage.) - In many cases, the strategic voting outcome is
identified after applying only the two or three
steps.
29An Anomaly under Strategic Voting
- With these tools in hand, I enthusiastically
began to derive Black-style propositions for
strategic voting. - An apparent anomaly quickly turned up
- when I extended the number of top cycle
alternatives in a cycle from three to four, I
discovered that there was always one alternative
in the cycle that could not win under any voting
order.
30The Anomaly
31The Algorithm Applied
32The Strategic Voting Anomaly
- This was surprising and somewhat disconcerting,
since I expected sincere and strategic voting
results to run in parallel. - Something was preventing one alternative from
winning, regardless of the voting order. - Evidently it had to do with the fact that, when
internal structure is considered, the
alternatives in a four-element cycle (unlike
those in a three-element cycle) occupy distinct
positions in the tournament structure. - But this structural asymmetry did not preclude a
degree of symmetry with respect to sincere voting
outcomes, so the discrepancy remained puzzling. - I further discovered that, given a cycle of five
(or more) alternatives, different internal
structures are possible, some of which made it
impossible for certain alternatives to win while
others did not. - In my subsequent dissertation chapter, I simply
presented the following proposition - Under ordinary amendment procedure, there may
be a motion alternative in the Condorcet top
cycle set that is not the sophisticated voting
decision under any voting order.
33The Origins of the Uncovered Set
- In 1976, I had a revise and resubmit decision on
a paper largely derived from this dissertation
chapter. - My main task was to revise the presentation of
the material (on the basis of wise editorial
guidance provided by AJPS editor Phillips
Shively) rather than its substance. - But in revisiting the analytical issues, I
noticed two additional points concerning the
strategic voting anomaly. - An alternative y that could not win under any
voting order (in the relatively small cyclic
tournaments I was examining) was dominated in a
particularly strong way by some other alternative
x --- namely, - not only did x beat y but also x beat everything
that y beats.
34The Origins of the Uncovered Set (cont.)
- The second point I noticed was that whenever x is
unanimously preferred to y, then x dominates y in
this strong sense. - I incorporated the latter point into the revised
paper. - An alternative x Pareto-inferior is some other
alternative y is unanimously preferred to x. - THEOREM. Under amendment procedure, no
Pareto-inferior alternative can win under
strategic voting - Note that this proposition is not trivial a
Pareto-inferior alternative can win under sincere
voting. - Nicholas R. Miller, Graph-Theoretical Approaches
to the Theory of Voting, American Journal of
Political Science, 1977.
35The Top Cycle Set May IncludePareto-Inferior
Alternatives
36Covering
- I then turned quickly to explore this strong
dominance more thoroughly and discovered that it
had many interesting properties. - Given an arrangement of x, y, and the
alternatives beaten by y into a three-level
structure with x at the top and with
downward-pointing arrows representing majority
preference, in my own mind it seemed natural to
say that x covers y - For better or worse, the terminology stuck.
37The Origins of the Uncovered Set (cont.)
- This exploration led to a paper that I presented
at the 1978 APSA meeting. - It drew almost no attention (probably because it
was one of six papers squeezed into a two-hour
panel, one of which was Kenneth Shepsles early
statement of his structure-induced equilibrium
setup). - Kenneth A. Shepsle, "Institutional Arrangements
and Equilibrium in Multidimensional Voting
Models," American Journal of Political Science,
February, 1979 - It did attract attention once it was published.
- Nicholas R. Miller, A New Solution Set for
Tournaments and Majority Voting, American
Journal of Political Science, 1980. - The joint appearance of these two papers at the
APSA panel previewed two theoretical responses to
majority rule choas, both of which have been
put to extensive theoretical use.
38Two Responses to Chaos
- The cyclical and seemingly chaotic nature of
majority rule revealed by the theoretical work on
voting and social choice of Plott, McKelvey,
Schofield and others suggested that political
processes rarely achieve equilibrium and might
wander all over the place. - But this theoretical conclusion was anomalous
because actual political choice processes appear
to be considerably more stable than the theory
suggested. - In the face of this anomaly, formal political
theorists have pursued two different, though not
mutually exclusive, lines of inquiry. - The first, exemplified most notably by Shepsle,
recognizes that political choice is always
embedded in some kind of institutional structure,
which may constrain processes so as to create
(perhaps rather arbitrary) equilibria that would
not otherwise exist. - The second, in contrast, focuses directly on pure
majority rule and seeks to find some deeper
interior structure and coherence within the
system of majority preference that may constrain
or guide political choice processes, even in the
face of apparent chaos and independently of
particular institutional arrangements. The
uncovered set (and the Banks set) have been
leading contributions of the latter line of
theorizing.
39Covering and the Uncovered Set in the Finite
Alternative Case
- Except for one conjecture, Miller (1980) deals
only with the finite as a opposed to spatial
alternative set. - Moreover, it assumes an odd number of voters with
strong preferences, i.e., a majority preference
tournament. - In this context, covering can be defined simply
- x C y ltgt W(x) is a subset of W(y)
- which implies x P y so the inclusion must be
strict. - If majority rule is fully transitive, x C y ltgt
x P y.
40Covering and the Uncovered Set in the Finite
Alternative Case (cont.)
- x C y is a transitive subrelation of x P y.
- Accordingly, the covering relation has maximal
elements, i.e., the uncovered set UC(X) x y
C x for all y. - If x is uncovered, then for all y either x P y or
there is some z such that x P z P y the
two-step or strategic principle. - If there were no such z, y would cover x.
- UC(X) is a subset (perhaps proper) of TC(X), so
- if there is a Condorcet winner x, UC(X) x.
- Define x UP y x is unanimously preferred to y.
- PO(X) x y UP x for all y Pareto (or
Pareto-optimal) set - UC(X) is a subset of PO(X).
41Covering and the Uncovered Set in the Finite
Alternative Case (cont.)
- In the absence of a Condorcet Winner, UC(X)
includes at least three alternatives in a cycle. - However, UC(X) may be a proper subset of TC(X),
so to that extent UC has some cycle-busting
(anti-chaos) power. - TC(X) always contains a complete cycle but (if
the number alternatives in TC(X) exceeds four)
its degree of cyclicity can vary. - The size of UC(X), relative to TC(X), depends on
the degree of cyclicity TC(X) which depends on
the interior structure of its complete cycle.
42Degree of Cyclicity
- Consider a tournament with m alternatives in a
complete cycle, so X TC(X). - Its degree of cyclicity can be measured by the
proportion of all triples of alternatives that
are cyclic. - A minimally cyclic tournament has m-2 cyclic
triple, - in which case, UC(X) includes just three
alternatives. - In a maximally cyclic tournament, every pair of
alternatives belongs to a cyclic triple, - so no covering exists and UC(X) TC(X).
43A Minimally Cyclic Top Cycle
44Another Minimally Cyclic Top Cycle
45Maximally Cyclic Majority Preference
Distributive Politics not in Miller, 1980
- For every x and y such that y P x, we can form a
cyclic triple, i.e., find some z such that x P z
P y P x. - Pure allocation three voters divide the dollar
game - x x1 x2 x3
S x 1 - y x1 - 2c x2 c x3 c S y
1 - z x1 - c x2 2c x3 - c S
z 1 - x x1 x2 x3
S x 1 - In this case X TC(X) UC(X), where X is the
set of efficient allocations. - Benjamin Ward, "Majority Rule and Allocation,"
Journal of Conflict Resolution, 1961. - David Epstein, "Uncovering some Subtleties of the
Uncovered Set Social Choice Theory and
Distributive Politics" Social Choice and
Welfare, January, 1998.
46The Uncovered Set and Voting Processesfrom
Miller (1980)
- Given strategic voting under an amendment agenda,
every possible voting outcome belongs to the
uncovered set UC(X). - CONJECTURE every alternative in UC(X) is a
possible strategic voting outcome. - If voters bargain among themselves before voting,
they will agree to enact some alternative that
belongs to UC(X). - Given competition between two victory-seeking
political parties/candidates, both propose a
uncovered platform, so the resulting government
policy belongs to UC(X) and indeed to UCu(X).
47Covering Depends on Environment
- The covering relation depends on irrelevant
alternatives. - Suppose m 2 and x P y. Then x C y.
- Now suppose a third alternative z is added to the
tournament. - If x P z, it remains true that x C y.
- But if y P z and z P y, then x no longer covers
y. - Conversely, even if x fails to cover y in a
tournament T, x may cover y in a subtournament of
T.
48The Ultimately Uncovered Set
- The top cycle set is equal to its own closure,
- i.e., TCTC(X) TC(X).
- But, as we have seen, the uncovered is not in
general equal to its own closure i.e., UC2(X)
UCUC(X) may be a proper subset of UC(X). - Likewise, UC3(X) may be a proper subset of
UC2(X), and so forth. - Given that the number of alternatives is finite,
we must reach some u such that UCu(X) UCu-1(X), - i.e., the ultimately uncovered set.
- Moreover (in the absence of a Condorcet Winner),
at three least alternatives belong to UCu(X).
49The Ultimately Uncovered Set
50The Ultimately Uncovered Set (cont.)
- There was an incorrect theorem in Miller (1980)
- it claimed that TCUC(X) UC(X),
- i.e., that UC(X) always contains a complete
cycle. - A correct theorem says that TCUCu(X) UCu(X).
- Nicholas R. Miller, The Covering Relation in
Tournaments Two Corrections, American Journal
of Political Science, May 1983. - The following example was provided in the
correction.
51The Ultimately Uncovered Set (cont.)
52Precursors of the Uncovered Set
- LANDAUS THEOREM. In a tournament, a point with
maximum score a king chicken beats every
other point in one or two steps, i.e., is
uncovered. - H.G. Landau, On Dominance Relations and the
Structure of Animal Societies, Bulletin of
Mathematical Biophysics, 1953. - Also
- Richard D. McKelvey, and Peter C. Ordeshook,
Symmetric Spatial Games Without Majority Rule
Equilibria, American Political Science Review,
1976 - Peter C. Fishburn, Condorcet Social Choice
Functions, SIAM Journal of Applied Mathematics,
1977. - Ronald A. Heiner, Length and Cycle
Equalization, Journal of Economic Theory, 1981.
53The Banks Set
- Banks was first show that the set of possible
strategic voting outcomes under amendment
procedure could be a proper subset of UC(X). - Making use of a slightly different version of the
sophisticated voting algorithm for amendment
procedure due to Shepsle and Weingast, Banks
showed that - an alternative x is a possible voting outcome if
and only if x is the maximal element in an
externally stable chain. - Kenneth A. Shepsle and Barry Weingast,
"Uncovered Sets and Sophisticated Voting Outcomes
with Implications for Agenda Institutions,"
American Journal of Political Science, 1984. - Jeffrey S. Banks, "Sophisticated Voting Outcomes
and Agenda Control," Social Choice and Welfare,
1985. - Nicholas R. Miller, Bernard Grofman, Scott L.
Feld, "The Structure of the Banks Set," Public
Choice, 1990.
54The Banks Set (cont.)
- Here is an intuitive statement of what this
means - We first pick some alternative x1 from the set of
alternatives. - We next pick a second alternative x2 such that x2
P x1 and put x2 on top of x2 . . - We next pick a third alternative x3 such that x3
P x2 and x3 P x1 and put x3 on top of both x2
and x1. - In this manner, we are creating a chain or a
cycle-avoiding trajectory, i.e., a sequence of
alternatives such that each higher alternative
in the sequence beats all the alternatives
below it. - We continue until we have built the chain with a
top element xk such that we can expand the chain
no further upward. - We have now created an externally stable chain,
- i.e., every alternative outside the chain is
beaten by some alternative in the chain. - If this were not so, we could expand further
upward.
55The Banks Set (cont.)
- The top alternative xk of an externally stable
chain - is a Banks alternative and
- is the strategic voting outcome given by the
voting order reflected in the chain, i.e., x1 is
voted on last, x2 second to last, etc. - Other inocuous may be inserted into the voting
order. - The Banks set is the set of all Banks
alternatives.
56The Uncovered Set in a Spatial Context
- Miller (1980) conjectured that
- in a spatial context, the uncovered set would be
a relatively small subset of the Pareto set,
centrally located in the distribution of ideal
points, and that it would shrink in size as the
number and diversity of ideal points increase. - I also suggested that, given sophisticated voting
under amendment procedure, the covering relation
put important qualifications on McKelveys famous
concluding comments about the implications of his
global cycling theorem for agenda control. - If the Chairman has complete control over the
agenda, he can construct an agenda which will
arrive at any point in the space. - Richard D. McKelvey, Intransitivities in
Multidimensional Voting Models and Some
Implications for Agenda Control, Journal of
Economic Theory, 1976.
57The Uncovered Set in a Spatial Context
58McKelveys demonic Chairman must construct a
(more or less) minimally cyclic agenda, and he
fails to get his way if he must announce his
agenda in advance and voting is sophisticated.
59The Uncovered Set in a Spatial Context
- At the time I did not have the analytical tools
at hand to pursue covering in a spatial context
effectively. - I sent my uncovered set paper to Richard
McKelvey and invited him to apply his expertise
to the problem. - I like to think that this helped lead to McKelvey
(1986). - Richard D. McKelvey, Covering, Dominance, and
Institution Free Properties of Social Choice,
American Journal of Political Science, 1986.
60Review The Covering Relation
- Alternative x covers alternative y iff
- x beats y, and
- x beats every alternative that y beats, so
- W(x) is a proper subset of W(y).
- The covering relation is transitive so
- maximal (uncovered) alternatives exist under
relevant circumstances. - Strategic Property an uncovered point beats
every other alternative in no more than two steps.
61Review The Covering Relation (cont.)
- Given finite alternatives and a majority
preference tournament, UC(X) - coincides with the Condorcet winner (if it
exists) - is a subset of the top cycle set and
- is a subset of the Pareto set.
- The size of UC(X) depends on the degree of
intransitivity in the tournament.
62Review The Covering Relation (cont.)
- In a two-dimensional spatial context (with
Euclidean preferences), the same three properties
hold. - However, the second loses all of its punch, since
(in the absence of Plott symmetry and a
Condorcet winner) the top cycle encompasses the
entire space. - Moreover, while majority rule in a
two-dimensional space is almost always cyclical, - its degree of cyclicity varies with the nature of
the ideal point (preference) configuration, and - it is never maximally cyclic.
- Cyclicity increases with the dimensionality of
the space, and - is maximal when the number of dimensions equals
the number of voters (as in the distributive
case). - However, in a spatial context one additional
bound on the uncovered set was established by
McKelvey.
63In a (two-dimensional Euclidean) spatial context
- In the unlikely event that a Condorcet winner
exists, the uncovered set coincides with it (as
in non-spatial context). - The uncovered set lies within the Pareto set (as
in non-spatial context). - The uncovered set lies within a circle centered
on the yolk with a radius four times that of the
yolk (McKelvey, 1986).
64The Case of Three Voters
- Hartley and Kilgour (1987) established precise
boundaries on the uncovered set for
configurations of three voters with Euclidean
preferences in a two-dimensional space. - In the event ideal points form the vertices of an
equilateral triangle, the uncovered set coincides
with the Pareto set. - Otherwise, the uncovered set excludes portions of
the Pareto triangle in the vicinity of the one
(if the Pareto triangle is acute) or two (if it
is obtuse) relatively extreme ideal points. - An implication of their analysis was that, at
least in the three-voter case, even the
conjunction of the Pareto bound and McKelveys 4r
bound is overgenerous. - Richard Hartley and D. Marc Kilgour, The
Geometry of the Uncovered Set, Mathematical
Social Sciences, 1987. - Scott L. Feld, Bernard Grofman, Richard Hartley,
Marc Kilgour, Nicholas R. Miller, and Nicolas
Noviello, The Uncovered Set in Spatial Voting
Games, Theory and Decision, 1987.
65Uncovered Set with n 3
66Almost Collinear n 3
67The Size of the Yolk
- When the concept was first propounded, there was
a widespread intuition that the yolk - is centrally located relative to the
configuration of ideal points, and - tends to shrink in size as the number and
diversity of voters increases. - However, it was difficult to confirm this
intuition or even to state it in a theoretically
precise fashion. - Feld et al. (1988) took a few very modest first
steps. - Tovey (1990) took a considerably larger step by
showing that, if ideal point configurations are
random samples drawn from a centered continuous
distribution, the expected yolk radius approaches
zero as the number of ideal points increases
without limit. - Scott L. Feld, Bernard Grofman, and Nicholas R.
Miller, Centripetal Forces in Spatial Voting
Games On the Size of the Yolk, Public Choice,
1988. - Craig A. Tovey, The Almost Surely Shrinking
Yolk, Naval Postgraduate School, Monterey,
California, October 1990.
68In Search of the Uncovered Set
- Until recently one major problem pertaining to
the uncovered set in the spatial context
remained. - In the context of spatial voting games of two or
more dimensions, voting theorists have had only
incomplete or rough knowledge concerning the
location, size, and shape of the uncovered set. - This problem motivated Bianco, Jeliazkov, and
Sened BJS to employ a grid-search computational
algorithm to generate pictures of uncovered sets
in a variety of spatial voting scenarios. - William T. Bianco, Ivan Jeliazkov, and Itai
Sened, The Uncovered Set and the Limits of
Legislative Action, Political Analysis, 2004.
69BJS Figure 1 Computing the Uncovered Set
70BJS Figure 5 Computing the Uncovered Set
(cont.)
71BJS Figure 2 Computing the Uncovered Set
(cont.)
72BJSs Theoretical Claims
- Based on the computational results displayed in
their figures, BJS made three theoretical claims
concerning the location and size of the uncovered
set. - The uncovered set can be much larger than our
expectations based on conventional wisdom and
previous work, as all their figures seem to
illustrate. - The uncovered set is not necessarily centrally
located. If ideal points are polarized (as in
the contemporary House), the uncovered set does
not lie in the center of the distribution of
legislators ideal points but is skewed toward
the majority caucus, as illustrated by BJS
Figure 5. - The size, shape, and location of the uncovered
set are very sensitive to the distribution of
ideal points. - With respect to size, this sensitivity is quite
dramatically illustrated by their Figure 2 and is
less dramatically illustrated by comparing panels
in Figure 5. - With respect to location, such sensitivity is
illustrated by the first panel of their Figure 4
and by a comparison of the last two panels of
their Figure 5.
73Observations on BJS Figure 2
- BJS Figure 2 is distinctive in that the uncovered
set appears to have straight line boundaries that
coincide with certain median lines. - Furthermore, in several of the panels the
uncovered set appears to be similar to the
Hartley-Kilgour construction for the three-voter
case in some way, the two additional ideal
points (to the left and right) have no effect on
the size and location of the uncovered set.
74BJS and NRM
- Bianco and I interacted fairly extensively as BJS
put their paper together comments and I was a
referee for several journals. - When it was accepted by Political Analysis, its
editor (Bob Erikson) asked whether I would be
interested in writing a commentary on it.
75NRM and Joseph Godfrey
- Shortly thereafter, I met up with Joseph Godfrey,
who made (an early version of) his CyberSenate
software available to me. - Godfrey modified CyberSenate to incoporate a
procedure (broadly similar to BJSs) to make
uncovered set calculations. - But CyberSenate also has a much wider range of
capabilities. - My commentary on BJS ended up as a substantial
paper that also served to showcase CyberSenate. - Nicholas R. Miller, In Search of the Uncovered
Set, Political Analysis, 2007.
76CYBERSENATE
- CyberSenate was developed by Joseph Godfrey of
the WinSet Group, LLC. - It can create configurations of ideal points
- by point and click methods,
- generate them by Monte Carlo methods, or
- derive them from empirical data.
- Indifference curves, median lines, Pareto sets,
win sets, yolks, cardioid bounds on win sets,
uncovered set approximations, and other
constructions can be generated on screen. - CyberSenate produced some of the preceding and
many of the following figures.
77CyberSenate for me is a dream come true --
compare the figures below with those that follow.
78Reminder The One-Dimensional Case
- In the one-dimensional cases, there is no chaos
to be straightened out by covering. - In a one-dimensional context with (standard
assumptions about preferences), - (strict) majority preference is fully transitive
- if x beats y, W(x) is always a subset of W(y) so
- covering is identical to (strict) majority
preference. - If the number of voters is odd, a Condorcet
Winner always exists. - It corresponds to the median ideal point in the
one-dimensional space. - This is Duncan Blacks Median Voter Theorem.
- Duncan Black, On the Rationale of Group
Decision-Making, Journal of Political Economy,
1948. - Duncan Black, The Theory of Committees and
Elections, Cambridge University Press, 1958.
79Theory of Two-Dimensional Spatial Voting
- In the spatial context, we refer to alternatives
as points. - The set X of all alternatives is the set of all
points in the space. - There is a finite odd number n gt 3 of voters with
Euclidean preferences. - Each voter i
- has an ideal point xi in the space, and
- prefers any point closer to his ideal point to
one that is more distant. - This implies that the set of points Pi(x) that i
prefers to x is the set of points bounded by a
circle that is centered on xi and passing through
x. - Indifference curves are concentric circles around
ideal points). - The Pareto set is the convex hull of voter ideal
points.
80The Pareto Set
81Theory (cont.)
- If some majority of m (n1)/2 voters prefers x
to y, I say x beats y. - The win set W(x) is the set of all points in X
that beat x. - The set of points that a particular majority of
voters prefers to x is the intersection of all
sets Pi(x) such that i belongs to that majority.
- W(x) is the union all such majority preference
sets. - Thus the boundary of a win set is everywhere
demarcated by segments of individual voter
indifference curves (segments of circles in the
Euclidean context). - In a spatial context, x beats essentially all
points not in W(x). - There are some majority preference ties but, in
order to simplify exposition, I overlook
technical issues pertaining to points that lie on
the boundaries of sets.
82Indifference Curves and the Win Set of a Point
Inside the Pareto Set
83Indifference Curves and the Win Set of a Point
Outside the Pareto Set
84Ditto with Five Ideal Points
85Collinearity
- A configuration of ideal points diverse if no two
ideal points precisely coincide. - A key feature of a spatial voting game is whether
the configuration of ideal points exhibits
collinearities - that is, whether three or more ideal points lie
precisely on the same straight line. - Collinearity always exists when ideal points
coincide but clearly may be found in diverse
configurations as well. - Non-diversity and collinearity may both be deemed
exceptional in the sense that, if hypothetical
ideal points were randomly thrown into a policy
space, non-diversity and collinearity would
almost never occur. - Of course, we can (and will) deliberately
contrive non-diverse and collinear configurations
e.g., BJS Figure 2. - In empirical work, where ideal point locations
estimated from interest group rating scales or
similar data are typically expressed in whole
numbers, it is likely that several legislators
have identical scores on a given dimension,
producing non-diversity and other collinearities. - Collinearity produces a variety of peculiarities
in particular, the invisible voter phenomena
discussed in the next section.
86Median Lines
- A any straight line L partitions the set of voter
ideal points into three subsets - those that lie on one side of L,
- those that lie on the other side of L, and
- those that lie on L itself.
- If it partitions the ideal points so that no more
than half of the ideal points lie on either side,
L is a median line, which we henceforth label M.
- Every ideal point lies on some median line and,
- if n is odd,
- every median line M passes through some ideal
point, - fewer than half of the ideal points lie on either
side of M, and - no other median line is parallel to M.
87A (Non-Limiting) Median Line
88Limiting Median Lines
- If n is odd, a typical median passes through just
one ideal point. - A limiting median line passes through two or more
ideal points. - Typically pairs of limiting median lines pass
through a given ideal point, with non-limiting
median lines sandwiched them. - A median line that passes through the three or
more (necessarily collinear ideal points) is a
stand-alone limiting median line in which the
sandwich of non-limiting median lines is
reduced to zero thickness.
89A Limiting Median Line
90Limiting and Non-Limiting Median Lines
91A Stand-Alone Limiting Median Line
92Induced Ideal Points
- Each voter i has an induced ideal point, i.e., a
most preferred point, on any line L. - Given Euclidean preferences, voter is induced
ideal point is the point on L closest to xi,
i.e., the intersection of L with the line through
xi perpendicular to L. - The n induced ideal points appear on L in some
(possibly weak) order and (since n is odd) we can
identify the median induced ideal point(s) on L. - Voter is induced preferences over L have the
standard Euclidean property.
93Induced Ideal Points
94The Median Line Perpendicular to L
- The perpendicular line through the median induced
point on L is itself the unique median line
perpendicular to L. - By standard Euclidean median voter logic, a point
x on L is beaten by another point y on L if and
only if y lies in the interval between x and its
reflection point x' such that x and x' are
equidistant from the median induced ideal point
on L. - In the event that x coincides with the median
induced ideal point, x beats every other point on
L.
95The Median Induced Ideal Point on L
96A Condorcet Winner in Two-Dimensional Space
- This last consideration implies that, if a point
x lies off any median line M, x is beaten by
points on M. - It follows that a point x in the space is
unbeaten (and a Condorcet winner) if and only if
it lies on every median line, - which is possible if and only if all median lines
intersect at the single point x (which itself
must be an ideal point). - This in turn can hold only in the presence of a
sufficient (and unlikely) degree of Plott
symmetry in the configuration of ideal points. - Such a Condorcet winner is structurally
unstable. - Charles R. Plott, A Notion of Equilibrium and
Its Possibility Under Majority Rule, American
Economic Review, 1967. - James M. Enelow and Melvin J. Hinich, On Plott's
Pairwise Symmetry Condition for Majority Rule
Equilibrium, Public Choice,1983.
97Full Plott Symmetry (Showing Limiting Median
Lines)
98Sufficient Plott Symmetry(with Non-diverse Ideal
Points)
99The Yolk
- The yolk is the set of points bounded by the
smallest circle that intersects every median
line. - The location of the yolk is given by its center
c, which indicates the generalized center (in the
sense the median) of the configuration of ideal
points. - The size of the yolk is given by its radius r,
which indicates the extent to which the
configuration of ideal points departs from one
exhibiting a degree of Plott symmetry sufficient
for the existence of a Condorcet winner. - The yolk circle is inscribed within the yolk
triangle formed by three median lines to which
the circle is tangent. - Typically, but not always due to Tovey
anomalies, these are limiting median lines.
100A Yolk with Zero Radius
101A Yolk with Small Radius
102A Yolk with Large Radius
103Win Sets in Two-Dimensional Space
- To get a preliminary sense of the size, shape,
and location of a win set W(x) in the spatial
context, consider the special case in which there
is only one voter i. - In this event, the center of the yolk is xi,
- the yolk radius is zero,
- and W(x) coincides with Pi(x),
- which (given Euclidean preferences) is the circle
with a center at c and a radius of d, where d is
the distance from x to c. - Whenever the yolk has zero radius, W(X) Pi(x),
where i is the central voter.
104A Win Set with a Single Voter
105Plott Symmetry and a Circular Win Set
106Bounds on Win Sets
- In the general case of multiple voters with
diverse ideal points and for a point x outside
the yolk, the boundary of W(x) is approximated by
the same circle centered on c with a radius of
d. - The accuracy of this approximation depends on the
size of the yolk, as given by its radius r,
according to this 2r Rule - point x beats all points more than d 2r from
the center of the yolk, and x is beaten by all
points closer than d - 2r to the center of the
yolk - put otherwise, the boundary of W(x) everywhere
falls between two circles centered on the yolk
with radii of d 2r and d - 2r respectively (the
inner constraint disappears if d lt r and the two
circles coincide if r 0) - Tighter bounds on W(x), especially in the
vicinity of x itself, are provided by the outer
and inner cardioids, originally described in
Ferejohn et al. (1984). - John A. Ferejohn, Richard D. McKelvey, and Edward
W. Packel, Limiting Distributions for
Continuous State Markov Voting Models, Social
Choice and Welfare, 1984.
107The Circular Bound on a Win Set
108Circular Bound on a Win Set (d lt 2r)
109Cardioid Bound on a Win Set
110Global Cycling
- For any point x, construct the circle with its
center at c that passes through x. - The previous figures (and the next ones)
illustrate the following proposition (Miller et
al., 1989. - THEOREM. In the absence of Plott symmetry, for
any point x there is some other point y that both - beats x, and
- is further from c than x is.
- Indeed, the boundary of a win set intersects the
cardioid bound at three points. - Nicholas R. Miller, Bernard Grofman, and Scott
L. Feld, The Geometry of Majority Rule,
Journal of Theoretical Politics, 1989.
111W(x) Intersects the Cardioid at Three Points
112In the Absence of Plott Symmetry, All Win Sets
Are At Least Slightly Chaotic
113Even Slightly Chaotic Win Sets Produces Global
Cycling
- However, the majority preference path from a
centrally located point to an extreme one may
take many steps. - The distance outwards take at each step cannot
exceed 2r (by the 2r Rule). - The number of steps required therefore depends on
the size yolk, i.e., the yolk radius r. - Put otherwise, it depends on the extent to which
the configuration of ideal points deviates from
Plott symmetry.
114Orderly Win Sets
- In two dimensions, a win set W(x) is orderly if
it is a subset of some open half space about x. - This implies that there is some voter i such
that, within the vicinity of x, W(x) is a subset
of Pi(x), and likewise for the win sets of other
points in the vicinity of x. - This guarantees that majority preference, while
(almost always) globally cyclical, is transitive
(being consistent with is preferences) in the
vicinity of x. - This also implies that local covering operates
in the vicinity of x. - That is, if y and z are both in the vicinity of
x, and y P z, then - W(y) U N(x) is a subset of W(z) U N(x), where
N(x) is a small area surrounding x (a
neighborhood of x). - However, outside of N(x), there may be points
that z beats but beat y, - so y does not (globally) cover z.
115An Orderly Win Set with Locally Transitive
Majority Preference
116Local Covering vs. (Global) Covering
117Disorderly Win Sets
- A win set W(x) is disorderly if it is not a
subset of any half space about x, but rather has
multiple small petals that point in all
directions from x.