Title: CMSC 671 Fall 2001
1CMSC 671Fall 2001
- Class 13/14 Tuesday, October 16 / Thursday,
October 18
2Todays class
- Inference in first-order logic
- Inference rules
- Forward chaining
- Backward chaining
- Resolution
- Unification
- Proofs
- Clausal form
- Resolution as search
3Inference in First-Order Logic
Some material adopted from notes by Andreas
Geyer-Schulz and Chuck Dyer
4Inference rules for FOL
- Inference rules for propositional logic apply to
FOL as well - Modus Ponens, And-Introduction, And-Elimination,
- New (sound) inference rules for use with
quantifiers - Universal elimination
- Existential introduction
- Existential elimination
- Generalized Modus Ponens (GMP)
5Universal elimination
- If (?x) P(x) is true, then P(c) is true, where c
is any constant in the domain of x - Example
- (?x) eats(Ziggy, x) gt eats(Ziggy, IceCream)
- The variable symbol can be replaced by any ground
term, i.e., any constant symbol or function
symbol applied to ground terms only
6Existential introduction
- If P(c) is true, then (?x) P(x) is inferred.
- Example
- eats(Ziggy, IceCream) gt (?x) eats(Ziggy, x)
- All instances of the given constant symbol are
replaced by the new variable symbol - Note that the variable symbol cannot already
exist anywhere in the expression
7Existential elimination
- From (?x) P(x) infer P(c)
- Example
- (?x) eats(Ziggy, x) gt eats(Ziggy, Stuff)
- Note that the variable is replaced by a brand-new
constant not occurring in this or any other
sentence in the KB - Also known as skolemization constant is a skolem
constant - In other words, we dont want to accidentally
draw other inferences about it by introducing the
constant - Convenient to use this to reason about the
unknown object, rather than constantly
manipulating the existential quantifier
8Generalized Modus Ponens (GMP)
- Apply modus ponens reasoning to generalized rules
- Combines And-Introduction, Universal-Elimination,
and Modus Ponens - E.g, from P(c) and Q(c) and (?x)(P(x) Q(x)) gt
R(x) derive R(c) - General case Given
- atomic sentences P1, P2, ..., PN
- implication sentence (Q1 Q2 ... QN) gt R
- Q1, ..., QN and R are atomic sentences
- substitution subst(?, Pi) subst(?, Qi) for
i1,...,N - Derive new sentence subst(?, R)
- Substitutions
- subst(?, a) denotes the result of applying a set
of substitutions defined by ? to the sentence a - A substitution list ? v1/t1, v2/t2, ...,
vn/tn means to replace all occurrences of
variable symbol vi by term ti - Substitutions are made in left-to-right order in
the list - subst(x/IceCream, y/Ziggy, eats(y,x))
eats(Ziggy, IceCream)
9Automated inference for FOL
- Automated inference using FOL is harder than PL
- Variables can potentially take on an infinite
number of possible values from their domains - Hence there are potentially an infinite number of
ways to apply the Universal-Elimination rule of
inference - Godel's Completeness Theorem says that FOL
entailment is only semidecidable - If a sentence is true given a set of axioms,
there is a procedure that will determine this - If the sentence is false, then there is no
guarantee that a procedure will ever determine
thisi.e., it may never halt
10Completeness of some inference techniques
- Truth Tabling is not complete for FOL because
truth table size may be infinite - Natural Deduction is complete for FOL but is not
practical because the branching factor in the
search is too large (swe would have to
potentially try every inference rule in every
possible way using the set of known sentences) - Generalized Modus Ponens is not complete for FOL
- Generalized Modus Ponens is complete for KBs
containing only Horn clauses
11Horn clauses
- A Horn clause is a sentence of the form
- (?x) P1(x) P2(x) ... Pn(x) gt Q(x)
- where
- there are 0 or more Pis and 0 or 1 Q
- the Pis and Q are positive (i.e., non-negated)
literals - Equivalently P1(x) ? P2(x) ? Pn(x) where the
Pis are all atomic and at most one of them is
positive - Prolog is based on Horn clauses
- Horn clauses represent a subset of the set of
sentences representable in FOL
12Horn clauses II
- Special cases
- P1 P2 Pn gt Q
- P1 P2 Pn gt false
- true gt Q
- These are not Horn clauses
- p(a) ? q(a)
- P Q gt R ? S
13Unification
- Unification is a pattern-matching procedure
- Takes two atomic sentences, called literals, as
input - Returns Failure if they do not match and a
substitution list, ?, if they do - That is, unify(p,q) ? means subst(?, p)
subst(?, q) for two atomic sentences, p and q - ? is called the most general unifier (mgu)
- All variables in the given two literals are
implicitly universally quantified - To make literals match, replace (universally
quantified) variables by terms
14Unification algorithm
- procedure unify(p, q, ?)
- Scan p and q left-to-right and find the
first corresponding - terms where p and q disagree (i.e., p
and q not equal) - If there is no disagreement, return ?
(success!) - Let r and s be the terms in p and q,
respectively, - where disagreement first occurs
- If variable(r) then
- Let ? union(?, r/s)
- Recurse and return unify(subst(?, p),
subst(?, q), ?) - else if variable(s) then
- Let ? union(?, s/r)
- Recurse and return unify(subst(?, p),
subst(?, q), ?) - else return Failure
- end
15Unification Remarks
- Unify is a linear-time algorithm that returns the
most general unifier (mgu), i.e., the
shortest-length substitution list that makes the
two literals match. - In general, there is not a unique minimum-length
substitution list, but unify returns one of
minimum length - A variable can never be replaced by a term
containing that variable - Example x/f(x) is illegal.
- This occurs check should be done in the above
pseudo-code before making the recursive calls
16Unification examples
- Example
- parents(x, father(x), mother(Bill))
- parents(Bill, father(Bill), y)
- x/Bill, y/mother(Bill)
- Example
- parents(x, father(x), mother(Bill))
- parents(Bill, father(y), z)
- x/Bill, y/Bill, z/mother(Bill)
- Example
- parents(x, father(x), mother(Jane))
- parents(Bill, father(y), mother(y))
- Failure
17Forward chaining
- Proofs start with the given axioms/premises in
KB, deriving new sentences using GMP until the
goal/query sentence is derived - This defines a forward-chaining inference
procedure because it moves forward from the KB
to the goal - Natural deduction using GMP is complete for KBs
containing only Horn clauses
18Forward chaining algorithm
19Backward chaining
- Backward-chaining deduction using GMP is complete
for KBs containing only Horn clauses - Proofs start with the goal query, find
implications that would allow you to prove it,
and then prove each of the antecedents in the
implication, continuing to work backwards until
you arrive at the axioms, which we know are true - Example Does Ziggy eat fish
- (?x) eats(Ziggy, x) gt eats(Ziggy, Stuff)
20Backward chaining algorithm
21Completeness of GMP
- GMP (using forward or backward chaining) is
complete for KBs that contain only Horn clauses - It is not complete for simple KBs that contain
non-Horn clauses - The following entail that S(A) is true
- (?x) P(x) gt Q(x)
- (?x) P(x) gt R(x)
- (?x) Q(x) gt S(x)
- (?x) R(x) gt S(x)
- If we want to conclude S(A), with GMP we cannot,
since the second one is not a Horn form - It is equivalent to P(x) ? R(x)
22Resolution
- Resolution is a sound and complete inference
procedure for FOL - Resolution Rule for PL
- P1 ? P2 ? ... ? Pn
- P1 ? Q2 ? ... ? Qm
- Resolvent P2 ? ... v Pn ? Q2 ? ... ? Qm
- Examples
- P and P ? Q, derive Q (Modus Ponens)
- (P ? Q) and (Q ? R), derive P ? R
- P and P, derive False contradiction!
- (P ? Q) and (P ? Q), derive True
23FOL resolution
- Given sentences
- P1 ? ... ? Pn
- Q1 ? ... ? Qm
- where each Pi and Qi is a literal, i.e., a
positive or negated predicate symbol with its
terms, if Pj and Qk unify with substitution list
?, then derive the resolvent sentence - subst(?, P1 ?... ? Pj-1 ? Pj1 ... Pn ? Q1 ?
Qk-1 ? Qk1 ?... ? Qm) - Example
- From clause P(x, f(a)) ? P(x, f(y)) ? Q(y)
- and clause P(z, f(a)) ? Q(z),
- derive resolvent clause P(z, f(y)) ? Q(y) ? Q(z)
- using ? x/z
24A resolution proof tree
25Resolution refutation proofs
- Given a consistent set of axioms KB and goal
sentence Q, show that KB Q - Proof by contradiction Add Q to KB and try to
prove false. - i.e., (KB - Q) ltgt (KB ? Q - False)
- Resolution can establish that a given sentence Q
is entailed by KB, but cant (in general) be used
to generate all logical consequences of a set
sentences - Also, it cannot be used to prove that Q is not
entailed by KB. - Resolution wont always give an answer since
entailment is only semidecidable - And you cant just run two proofs in parallel,
one trying to prove Q and the other trying to
prove Q, since KB might not entail either one
26Procedure
- procedure resolution(KB, Q)
- KB is a set of consistent, true FOL
sentences, Q is a goal sentence - to derive. Returns success if KB -
Q, and failure otherwise - KB union(KB, Q)
- while false ? KB do
- Choose 2 sentences, S1 and S2, in KB
that contain - literals that unify
- if none, return Failure
- resolvent resolution-rule(S1, S2)
- KB union(KB, resolvent)
- return Success
- end
27Refutation resolution proof tree
28Resolution issues
- Resolution is only applicable to sentences in
clausal form, e.g. - P1 ? P2 ?... ? Pn
- where Pis are negated or non-negated atomic
predicates - Issues
- Can we convert every FOL sentence into this form?
- Yes as we will see shortly
- How to pick which pair of sentences to resolve?
- Determines the search strategy of the prover
more later - How to pick which pair of literals, one from each
sentence, to unify? - Again, part of the search strategy
29Example proof Did Curiosity kill the cat?
- Jack owns a dog. Every dog owner is an animal
lover. No animal lover kills an animal. Either
Jack or Curiosity killed the cat, who is named
Tuna. Did Curiosity kill the cat? - The axioms can be represented as follows
- A. (?x) Dog(x) Owns(Jack,x)
- B. (?x) ((?y) Dog(y) Owns(x, y)) gt
AnimalLover(x) - C. (?x) AnimalLover(x) gt (?y) Animal(y) gt
Kills(x,y) - D. Kills(Jack,Tuna) ? Kills(Curiosity,Tuna)
- E. Cat(Tuna)
- F. (?x) Cat(x) gt Animal(x)
30Example proof, cont. Did Curiosity kill the cat?
- Convert to implicative normal form
- A1. True gt Dog(D)
- A2. True gt Owns(Jack,D)
- B. Dog(y) Owns(x, y) gt AnimalLover(x)
- C. AnimalLover(x) Animal(y) Kills(x,y) gt
False - D. True gt Kills(Jack,Tuna) v
Kills(Curiosity,Tuna) - E. True gt Cat(Tuna)
- F. Cat(x) gt Animal(x)
- Add the query
- Q. Kills(Curiosity, Tuna) gt False
31Example proof III Did Curiosity kill the cat?
- The Proof
- G. A1, B, y/D Owns(x,D) gt AnimalLover(x)
- H. A2, G, x/Jack True gt AnimalLover(Jack)
- I. E,F, x/Tuna True gt Animal(Tuna)
- J. C,I, y/Tuna AnimalLover(x) Kills(x,Tuna)
gt False - K. H,J x/Jack Kills(Jack,Tuna) gt False
- L. D,Q True gt Kills(Jack,Tuna)
- M. L,K True gt False
32Curiosity Killed the Cat
33Converting to clausal form
- The canonical (standard) form for resolution is
Conjunctive Normal Form (conjunction of
disjunctions), or equivalently, Implicative
Normal Form (conjunction implies disjunction) - Example If Johns house is big, then it is a lot
of work, unless he has a housekeeper and does not
have a garden - FOL
- Big(h) House(h,j) gt Work(h) ? (Cleans(c,h)
Garden(g,h)) - Implicative Normal Form
- Big(h) House(h,j) gt Work(h) ? Cleans(c,h)
- Big(h) House(h,j) Garden(g,h) gt Work(h)
34Converting sentences to clausal form
- 1. Eliminate all ltgt connectives
- (P ltgt Q) gt ((P gt Q) (Q gt P))
- 2. Eliminate all gt connectives
- (P gt Q) gt (P v Q)
- 3. Reduce the scope of each negation symbol to a
single predicate - P gt P
- (P v Q) gt P Q
- (P Q) gt P v Q
- (?x)P gt (?x)P
- (?x)P gt (?x)P
- 4. Standardize variables rename all variables so
that each quantifier has its own unique variable
name
35Converting sentences to clausal form Skolem
constants and functions
- 5. Eliminate existential quantification by
introducing Skolem constants/functions - (?x)P(x) gt P(c)
- c is a Skolem constant (a brand-new constant
symbol that is not used in any other sentence) - (?x)(?y)P(x,y) gt (?x)P(x, f(x))
- since ? is within the scope of a universally
quantified variable, use a Skolem function f to
construct a new value that depends on the
universally quantified variable - f must be a brand-new function name not occurring
in any other sentence in the KB. - E.g., (?x)(?y)loves(x,y) gt (?x)loves(x,f(x))
- In this case, f(x) specifies the person that x
loves
36Converting sentences to clausal form
- 6. Remove universal quantifiers by (1) moving
them all to the left end (2) making the scope of
each the entire sentence and (3) dropping the
prefix part - Ex (?x)P(x) gt P(x)
- 7. Put into conjunctive normal form (conjunction
of disjunctions) - (P Q) ? R gt (P ? R) (Q ? R)
- (P ? Q) ? R gt (P ? Q ? R)
- 8. Split conjuncts into a separate clauses
- 9. Standardize variables so each clause contains
only variable names that do not occur in any
other clause
37An example
- (?x)(P(x) gt ((?y)(P(y) gt P(f(x,y)))
(?y)(Q(x,y) gt P(y)))) - 2. Eliminate gt
- (?x)(P(x) ? ((?y)(P(y) ? P(f(x,y)))
(?y)(Q(x,y) ? P(y)))) - 3. Reduce scope of negation
- (?x)(P(x) ? ((?y)(P(y) ? P(f(x,y)))
(?y)(Q(x,y) P(y)))) - 4. Standardize variables
- (?x)(P(x) ? ((?y)(P(y) ? P(f(x,y)))
(?z)(Q(x,z) P(z)))) - 5. Eliminate existential quantification
- (?x)(P(x) ?((?y)(P(y) ? P(f(x,y))) (Q(x,g(x))
P(g(x))))) - 6. Drop universal quantification symbols
- (P(x) ? ((P(y) ? P(f(x,y))) (Q(x,g(x))
P(g(x)))))
38Example
- 7. Convert to conjunction of disjunctions
- (P(x) ? P(y) ? P(f(x,y))) (P(x) ? Q(x,g(x)))
- (P(x) ? P(g(x)))
- 8. Create separate clauses
- P(x) ? P(y) ? P(f(x,y))
- P(x) ? Q(x,g(x))
- P(x) ? P(g(x))
- 9. Standardize variables
- P(x) ? P(y) ? P(f(x,y))
- P(z) ? Q(z,g(z))
- P(w) ? P(g(w))
39Resolution TP as search
- Resolution can be thought of as the bottom-up
construction of a search tree, where the leaves
are the clauses produced by KB and the negation
of the goal - When a pair of clauses generates a new resolvent
clause, add a new node to the tree with arcs
directed from the resolvent to the two parent
clauses - Resolution succeeds when a node containing the
False clause is produced, becoming the root node
of the tree - A strategy is complete if its use guarantees that
the empty clause (i.e., false) can be derived
whenever it is entailed
40Breadth-first search
- Level 0 clauses are the original axioms and the
negation of the goal - Level k clauses are the resolvents computed from
two clauses, one of which must be from level k-1
and the other from any earlier level - Compute all possible level 1 clauses, then all
possible level 2 clauses, etc. - Complete, but very inefficient
41Strategies
- There are a number of general (domain-independent)
strategies that are useful in controlling a
resolution theorem prover - Well briefly look at the following
- Breadth first
- Set of support
- Unit resolution
- Input resolution
- Ordered resolution
- Subsumption
42Set of support
- At least one parent clause must be the negation
of the goal or a descendant of such a goal
clause (i.e., derived from a goal clause) - Complete (assuming all possible set-of-support
clauses are derived) - Gives a goal-directed character to the search
43Unit resolution
- Prefer resolution steps in which at least one
parent clause is a unit clause, i.e., a clause
containing a single literal - Not complete in general, but complete for Horn
clause KBs
44Input resolution
- At least one parent must be one of the input
sentences (i.e., either a sentence in the
original KB or the negation of the goal) - Not complete in general, but complete for Horn
clause KBs - Linear resolution
- Extension of input resolution
- One of the parent sentences must be an input
sentence or an ancestor of an input sentece - Complete
45Ordered resolution
- Search for resolvable sentences in order (left to
right) - This is how Prolog operates
- Resolve the first element in the sentence first
- This forces the user to define what is important
in generating the code - The way the sentences are written controls the
resolution
46Subsumption
- Eliminate all sentences that are subsumed by
(more specific than) an existing sentence to keep
the KB small - Like factoring, this is just removing things that
merely clutter up the space and will not affect
the final result - E.g., if P(x) is already in the KB, adding P(A)
makes no sense P(x) is a superset of P(A) - Likewise adding P(A) ? Q(B) would add nothing to
the KB
47Proof tree that West is a criminal
48A failed proof tree
49Sketch of a completeness proof for resolution