An enactive resolution to Hume's problem of personal identity - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

About This Presentation
Title:

An enactive resolution to Hume's problem of personal identity

Description:

... no simplicity in it at one time, nor identity in different; [...]. The ... repeats several times, there is nothing new about each individual situation. ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:42
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 22
Provided by: lifeandmi
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: An enactive resolution to Hume's problem of personal identity


1
An enactive resolution to Hume's problem of
personal identity
  • Tom Froese
  • Life and Mind 22

2
Outline of the talk
  • Humes problem of personal identity
  • Identity of living bodies
  • Identity of mind
  • Causality
  • The enactive account of identity
  • A phenomenological resolution

3
A bundle theory of identity
  • Hume famously observed that when I turn my
    reflection on myself, I never can perceive this
    self without some one or more perceptions nor
    can I ever perceive any thing but the
    perceptions. Tis the composition of these,
    therefore, which forms the self (THN. App.15).
  • In other words the mind is kind of theatre,
    where several perceptions successively make their
    appearance pass, re-pass, glide away, and mingle
    in an infinite variety of postures and
    situations. There is properly no simplicity in it
    at one time, nor identity in different . The
    comparison of the theatre must not mislead us.
    They are the successive perceptions only, that
    constitute the mind (THN. 1.4.6.4).

4
A psychological account
  • On epistemological grounds Hume rejects the
    existence of a substantial self as a possible
    explanation for why we tend to attribute identity
    to some of our changing perceptions. Thats an
    issue for metaphysicians.
  • For Hume this psychological propensity can only
    be explained in terms of distinct perceptions and
    certain relations, most notably resemblance and
    causation.
  • He is interested in how our belief in identity
    gets formed. Under what circumstances is identity
    disclosed in our experience? How is it
    constituted?

5
Different kinds of identity
  • Hume identifies 3 different kinds of identity
    which are disclosed to our experience
  • The identity of inanimate natural objects
  • The identity of inanimate artificial objects
  • The identity of animate objects
  • The identity of mind (i.e. personal identity)
    most closely resembles that of animate objects
    (i.e. living bodies).
  • How are these different identities constituted?

6
Inanimate natural identity
  • Hume provides a psychological explanation of how
    we come to ascribe an identity to a particular
    subset of the total perceptions which constitute
    the ongoing flow of our experience, leading to a
    belief in an identical object
  • He appeals to the relation of resemblance there
    is a smooth and easy transition between the
    different perceptions so that through our
    imagination we are led to believe that tis
    nothing but continud survey of the same object
    (THN. 1.4.6.8).
  • Nevertheless, if sufficient small changes in such
    an object add up to a considerable change in
    proportion to the whole, the ascription of
    identity ceases.

7
Inanimate artificial identity
  • Hume notes that our propensity to attribute
    identity is increased when the imagination is
    faced with an object where there is a reference
    of the parts to each other, and a combination to
    some common end or purpose (THN. 1.4.6.11).
  • As an example he considers the classic story of
    the ship, which over time has a considerable
    amount of its parts and materials replaced, but
    is still considered to be the same ship.
  • When faced with humanly designed artifacts the
    common end, in which the parts conspire, is the
    same under all their variations, and affords an
    easy transition of the imagination from one
    situation of the body to another (THN.
    1.4.6.11).

8
Identity of living bodies
  • But this is still more remarkable, when we add a
    sympathy of parts to their common end, and
    suppose that they bear to each other, the
    reciprocal relation of cause and effect in all
    their actions and operations. This is the case
    with all animals and vegetables where not only
    the several parts have a reference to some
    general purpose, but also a mutual dependence on,
    and connexion with each other. The effect of so
    strong a relation is, that tho every one must
    allow, in a very few years both vegetables and
    animals endure a total change, yet we still
    attribute identity to them, while their form,
    size, and substance are entirely alterd. (THN.
    1.4.6.12)

9
Mechanisms of identity attribution
  • The 3 different types of identity are ordered in
    increasing propensity for identity attribution
    due to the following mechanisms
  • Inanimate natural object resemblance
  • Inanimate artificial object common end
  • Animate object reciprocal causality
  • What about the identity attributed to mind?

10
Identity of mind
  • In order to proceed in this manner will not be
    easy, since to explain it perfectly we must take
    the matter pretty deep, and account for that
    identity, which we attribute to plants and
    animals there being a great analogy betwixt it,
    and the identity of a self or person (THN.
    1.4.6.5).
  • tis evident, the same method of reasoning must
    be continud, which has so successfully explaind
    the identity of plants, and animals, and ships,
    and houses, and of all the compounded and
    changeable productions either of art or nature.
    The identity, which we ascribe to the mind of
    man, is only a fictitious one, and of a like with
    that which we ascribe to vegetables and animal
    bodies (THN. 1.4.6.15).

11
Identity as a fiction?
  • Hume often refers to aspects of our experience as
    fictions. These are generally constituted by the
    imagination and strongly compel our belief.
  • In the case of personal identity it is our belief
    in a simple identity even when faced with a
    composite identity.
  • what we call a mind, is nothing but a heap or
    collection of different perceptions, united
    together by certain relations, and supposd, tho
    falsely, to be endowd with a perfect simplicity
    and identity (THN. 1.4.2.39).

12
Identity of mind
  • Hume proposes that, like the identity of living
    bodies, personal identity is a non-substantial,
    non-localized, relational, composite identity.
  • This identity is autonomous and self-organizing.
  • It has the capacity for active constitution and
    generating interaction through simple mechanistic
    principles such as habit/custom and different
    kinds of association.

13
So far, so good?
  • So what is wrong with this account of personal
    identity such that Hume famously disavows it in
    the Appendix to the Treatise?
  • all my hopes vanish, when I come to explain the
    principles, that unite our successive perceptions
    in our thought or consciousness. I cannot
    discover any theory, which gives me satisfaction
    on this head. In short there are two principles,
    which I cannot render consistent nor is it in my
    power to renounce either of them, viz. that all
    our distinct perceptions are distinct existences,
    and that the mind never perceives any real
    connexion among distinct existences. Did our
    perceptions either inhere in something simple and
    individual, or did the mind perceive some real
    connexion among them, there woud be no
    difficulty in the case. (THN. App.20-21)
  • We have already seen why Hume rejects the notion
    of substance identity. But what about the second
    principle?

14
Causality
  • Humes rejection of the real connections needed
    for his account of identity is based on his
    account of how causality is disclosed to us.
  • Imagine event A then event B!
  • In this case all we can know is that B followed
    A. Even if the sequence repeats several times,
    there is nothing new about each individual
    situation. However, if we experience this
    sequence often enough we actually start to
    believe that A causes B.
  • Accordingly, Hume claims that this sense of a
    necessary connection between the events is not
    intrinsic to the sequence but rather constituted
    by our mind through force of habit and then
    projected onto the events. It is therefore
    another fiction of our imagination.
  • Why is this a problem for Humes account of
    personal identity?

15
Humes problem of personal identity
  • We have no philosophical grounds to transfer the
    determination of the thought to external objects,
    and suppose any real intelligible connexion
    betwixt them that being a quality, which can
    only belong to the mind that considers them
    (THN. 1.3.14.27).
  • Now we are in a position to understand Humes
    problem of personal identity as resulting from an
    internal incoherence of his philosophy. Since he
    has rejected the notion of substance while still
    retaining the claim that perceptions are distinct
    from each other, it follows that the perceptions
    of the mind form a whole only by being connected
    together. But no connexions among distinct
    existences are ever discoverable by human
    understanding (THN. App.20).
  • If Hume is unable to resolve this issue then when
    his philosophical framework is applied
    exclusively to the world (including other agents)
    it commits him to the undesirable position of
    idealistic solipsism, and when applied to his own
    personal identity it becomes self-refuting.

16
Enactive account of individuality
  • Hume has been credited with having brilliantly
    formulated the discovery of selfless minds, a
    discovery of fundamental relevance to the human
    situation, but as unable to conceive of a way
    to bring that discovery together with everyday
    experience (Varela, Thompson Rosch 1991, p.
    129-130) through notions such as
    self-organization and emergence.
  • While there is certainly a problem regarding the
    reconciliation of his account of personal
    identity with his own experience, it is not
    because of his discovery of selfless minds as
    such, but rather because he was forced to
    conceive of them as mere powerless fictions.

17
A shared problem?
  • The identity of the whole system is not
    substantial but rather emerges out of the
    interactions of the parts, and emergents, of
    course, do not have the status of ontological
    entities (substances) (Varela, Thompson Rosch
    1991, p. 118).
  • The identity of an organism is nonsubstantially
    localized, and yet perfectly able to generate
    interactions (Varela 1997).
  • Maturana claims it is inadequate to attribute
    causal relations to living systems since the
    notion of causality is a notion that pertains to
    the domain of descriptions, and as such it is
    relevant only in the metadomain in which the
    observer makes his commentaries and cannot be
    deemed to be operative in the phenomenal domain,
    the object of description (Maturana Varela
    1980, p. xviii).
  • The enactive account shares Humes problem. Can
    it resolve it?

18
An enactive resolution
  • The strategy pursued here will be to ground our
    notion of causality in the experience of our
    lived body in action rather than following Hume
    in attributing it to the operations of a
    disembodied observer.
  • The evidence of causality in our bodily
    experience is considered by Hume in two footnotes
    in the Enquiry but quickly dismissed for two main
    reasons 1) the limited domain of applicability
    of the experience and the danger of
    anthropomorphism, and 2) the lack of conceptual
    clarity it can afford.
  • Hume models his theory of perception on vision,
    which in its character is the most passive and
    objectifying sense. It is therefore the most
    conducive for knowledge, but easily leads to a
    dismissal of any kind of experiential evidence
    which, being not a datum but an actum,
    cannot be seen, i.e. objectified, but only
    experience from within when exerted or suffered
    (Jonas 1950).

19
The lived body in action
  • If we remove the Cartesian straightjacket, which
    is constraining Humes rudimentary phenomenology,
    and extend his empiricism to include the full
    range of our lived experience, then the primary
    aspect of causality is not regular connection,
    not even necessary connection, but force and
    influence and, more importantly, that these are
    themselves original contents of experience
    (Jonas 1950).
  • the source of this experience is, indeed, not
    sense perception, but our body exerting itself in
    action the source which Hume summarily
    dismisses under the head of animal nisus
    (Jonas 1950).
  • A phenomenological re-conceptualization of
    causality!
  • Note that this move entails (i) that causality is
    no longer just a groundless fiction of the
    imagination, and (ii) that a coherent
    non-substantial account of personal identity is
    now possible.

20
Concluding remarks
  • This solution provides a good reason to follow
    Jonas (1950) in proclaiming that the right of
    extrapolation from this source beyond its
    immediate range of deliverance is a question to
    be studied, without fear of the blame of
    anthropomorphism, by an organic philosophy.
  • Fortunately, the phenomenology of the lived body
    is a central aspect of enactivism (e.g. Thompson
    2007).
  • Moreover, since it already appeals to the
    evidence of our intrinsic teleology in us as a
    part of its account of autonomous agency (Weber
    Varela 2002), it is only a small step to also
    include our lived bodily experience of the
    animal nisus as another source of evidence.

21
References
  • Hume, D. (1739-1740), A Treatise of Human Nature,
    in D.F. Norton M.J. Norton (eds.), Oxford
    Philosophical Texts, Oxford, UK Oxford
    University Press, 2000
  • Hume, D. (1748), An Enquiry Concerning Human
    Understanding, in T.L. Beauchamp (ed.), Oxford
    Philosophical Texts, Oxford, UK Oxford
    University Press, 1999
  • Jonas, H. (1950), Causality and Perception, The
    Journal of Philosophy, 47(11), pp. 319-324
  • Maturana, H.R. Varela, F.J. (1980), Autopoiesis
    and Cognition The Realization of the Living,
    Dordrecht, Holland D. Reidel Publishing Company
  • Thompson, E. (2007), Mind in Life Biology,
    Phenomenology, and the Sciences of Mind,
    Cambridge, MA The MIT Press
  • Varela, F.J. (1997), Patterns of Life
    Intertwining Identity and Cognition, Brain and
    Cognition, 34, pp. 72-87
  • Varela, F.J, Thompson, E. Rosch, E. (1991), The
    Embodied Mind Cognitive science and human
    experience, Cambridge, MA The MIT Press
  • Weber, A. Varela, F.J. (2002), Life after
    Kant Natural purposes and the autopoietic
    foundations of biological individuality,
    Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1, pp.
    97-125
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com