PH1513 Knowledge and Mind - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 111
About This Presentation
Title:

PH1513 Knowledge and Mind

Description:

2. The link between epistemology and philosophy of mind. 3. Introduction ... First solution: methodism: you start with an answer to the question ... methodism ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:38
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 112
Provided by: irs93
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: PH1513 Knowledge and Mind


1
(No Transcript)
2
PH1513 Knowledge and Mind
  • Tuesday, March 20th 2007

3
PH1513 EpistemologyWeeks 5-12
  • 1. Practical matters.
  • 2. The link between epistemology and philosophy
    of mind.
  • 3. Introduction to epistemology.

4
Practical issues.
  • 1. No classes in week 6.
  • 2. Essay can be either on philosophy of mind or
    on epistemology.
  • 3. Exam questions will be a mix of epistemology
    and philosophy of mind questions.
  • 4. Contact details Martijn Blaauw
  • Office Old Brewery Ground Floor room
    16.
  • Telephone 272798
  • E-mail m.blaauw_at_abdn.ac.uk
  • 5. Office hours Wed, 11-12, Thurs, 12-1.
  • 6. Recording lectures is OK.
  • If you have any questions, dont hesitate to
    contact me!

5
Epistemology and Philosophy of Mind
  • The connection between these two branches of
    philosophy is the notion of belief.
  • To believe something is a mental state as
    such, it is the object of study of philosophy of
    mind.
  • To believe something is usually thought to be
    the core ingredient of knowledge.

6
What is epistemology?
  • Epistemologists are primarily interested in the
    concept knowledge, but also in related concepts
    like belief, truth, justification for
    belief, and rationality.
  • The key question in epistemology is the
    questionWhat is knowledge?
  • This question asks what the correct analysis of
    the concept knowledge is.
  • This raises two questions

7
Two questions
  • I. What type of knowledge do epistemologists
    focus on?
  • II. What is conceptual analysis?
  • In what follows, I will answer these two
    questions.

8
I. What type of knowledge?
  • Four types of knowledge
  • (i) Knowledge-how (ability knowledge)
  • (ii) Knowledge-wh (interrogative knowledge)
  • (iii) Knowledge-Q (direct object knowledge)
  • (iv) Knowledge-that (propositional knowledge)
  • ? We will focus on (iv) knowledge-that.

9
II. What is conceptual analysis?
  • Analysing a concept means providing the
    individually necessary and jointly sufficient
    conditions that must be satisfied in order for
    the concept to be applicable.
  • So we try to decompose the concept into its
    consituent parts.
  • If any one of the parts is missing, the concept
    cannot be applied.

10
Combining I and II The Key Epistemological
Question
  • What is knowledge?
  • Where this question should be understood as a
    request to provide a conceptual analysis of
    propositional knowledge (knowledge-that).

11
Examples
  • John and Jill are in the kitchen. John reads in
    the newspaper that Hilary Clinton is running for
    president? Does he know that Hilary Clinton is
    running for president?
  • Answer Yes.

12
Examples Knowledge implies Belief.
  • John and Jill are in the kitchen. John reads in
    the newspaper that Hilary Clinton is running for
    president. John is a very stubborn man, however,
    and does not believe a word of what the newspaper
    (The Sun) says. What the newspaper says is true
    however Hilary Clinton is running for president.
    Does John know that Hilary Clinton is running for
    president?
  • Answer No.
  • Why not He does not believe it.

13
Examples Knowledge implies Truth.
  • John and Jill are in the kitchen. John reads in
    the newspaper that Mel Gibson is running for
    president. John believes that Mel Gibson is
    running for president. The newspaper has it
    wrong, however. Does John know that Mel Gibson is
    running for president?
  • Answer No.
  • Reason False.

14
Examples Knowledge implies Justification.
  • John and Jill are in the kitchen. John reads in
    the newspaper that Hilary Clinton is running for
    president. This is true, and John believes it to
    be true. However, the reporter wanted to play a
    trick on the readers of the newspaper and wanted
    to deceive them by writing that Hilary Clinton is
    running for president the reporter thought this
    was false. Unbeknownst to the reporter, however,
    it is true. Does John know that Hilary Clinton is
    running for president?
  • Answer NO
  • Reason No justification.

15
The standard analysis of knowledge
  • Knowledge
  • Justified
  • True
  • Belief.
  • If any one of these is missing, there can be no
    knowledge.

16
Sources of knowledge
  • Perception
  • Reasoning
  • Testimony
  • Memory

17
Summary
  • What you need to take away from this lecture
  • (1) What is conceptual analysis?
  • (2) What different types of knowledge can be
    distinguished?
  • (3) What is the standard analysis of knowledge?
  • (4) What are some standard sources of knowledge?

18
Next week
  • Problems for the traditional analysis of
    knowledge in terms of justified true belief.

19
PH1513 Knowledge and Mind
  • Lecture 2
  • March 1st 2007

20
Structure of the lecture
  • 1. Practical issues
  • 2. Recap of the last lecture
  • 3. Knowledge can not be due to luck
  • 4. The value of knowledge

21
Practical issues
  • 1. No classes in week 6.
  • 2. Essay can be either on philosophy of mind or
    on epistemology.
  • 3. Exam questions will be a mix of epistemology
    and philosophy of mind questions.
  • 4. Contact details Martijn Blaauw
  • Office Old Brewery Ground Floor room
    16.
  • Telephone 272798
  • E-mail m.blaauw_at_abdn.ac.uk
  • 5. Office hours Wed, 11-12, Thurs, 12-1.
  • 6. Recording lectures is OK.
  • If you have any questions, dont hesitate to
    contact me!

22
Recap of previous lecture
  • 1) What is conceptual analysis?
  • (2) What different types of knowledge can be
    distinguished?
  • (3) What is the standard analysis of knowledge?
  • (4) What are some standard sources of knowledge?

23
Sources of knowledge
  • Perception
  • Reasoning
  • Testimony
  • Memory
  • Special sources sensus divinitatis.

24
Knowledge belief and truth
  • Knowledge implies at least belief and truth
  • (a) Knowledge implies belief
  • John and Jill are in the kitchen. John reads in
    the newspaper that Hilary Clinton is running for
    president. John is a very stubborn man, however,
    and does not believe a word of what the newspaper
    (The Sun) says. What the newspaper says is true
    however Hilary Clinton is running for president.
    Does John know that Hilary Clinton is running for
    president?

25
  • (b) Knowledge implies truth
  • John and Jill are in the kitchen. John reads in
    the newspaper that Mel Gibson is running for
    president. John believes that Mel Gibson is
    running for president. The newspaper has it
    wrong, however. Does John know that Mel Gibson is
    running for president?

26
Knowledge and luck
  • Consider the following case
  • Harry forms the belief that the horse Lucky
    Lass will win the next race purely on the basis
    of the fact that the name of the horse appeals to
    him. As it happens, Lucky Lass actually wins the
    race. Did Harry know this?

27
Knowledge and luck
  • Intuitively no.
  • Reason the fact that Harrys belief is true is a
    matter of sheer luck.
  • Compare hitting the bulls-eye by sheer luck
    does not mean you are a skilled archer.

28
Knowledge, luck, and archery
  • Knowledge is just like archery in that it is an
    achievement
  • Beliefs aim at truth, just like the archer aims
    at the bulls-eye. Hitting the truth (the
    bulls-eye) by luck isnt going to make you a
    skilled archer, nor give you knowledge.

29
Luck and the standard analysis
  • One way to characterize the anti-luck condition
    on knowledge would be in terms of justification
    (the third component in the standard analysis of
    knowledge).

30
The value of knowledge
  • Why is knowledge valuable?
  • First way to answer this question
  • Knowledge implies true belief, and true belief is
    instrumentally valuable.
  • (It is better to have true beliefs than false
    beliefs, and true belief can serve certain
    purposes).

31
The value of knowledge
  • Problems with the first answer
  • (1) Some true beliefs are trivial.
  • (2) Explaining the value of knowledge in terms of
    the value of true belief implies that knowledge
    is no more valuable than true belief. But we do
    seem to value knowledge more than mere true
    belief.

32
The value of knowledge
  • Knowledge is more valuable than true belief
    because knowledge is stable.
  • A true belief that also is knowledge is far
    likely to remain fast in response to changing
    circumstances than mere true belief.
  • If you know, you could not easily have been
    wrong. If you have mere true belief, you could
    easily have been wrong.

33
The value of knowledge
  • Knowledge has intrinsic value it is good of
    itself, regardless of whether the knowledge in
    question serves some sort of purpose. (Knowledge
    is like friendship in this regard we value
    friends not because they are useful to us but
    because they are valuable to us of themselves).
  • True belief never is intrinsically valuable but
    only valuable in the instrumental sense.

34
Recap
  • Knowledge excludes luck
  • True belief is instrumentally valuable
  • Knowledge is stable
  • Knowledge can be intrinsically valuable

35
Next lecture
  • Defining knowledge

36
PH1513 Knowledge and Mind
  • Lecture 3
  • Tuesday, March 13th 2007

37
Recap
  • Lecture 1 some introductory issues
  • Lecture 2 knowledge and value
  • This lecture Defining Knowledge

38
The problem of the criterion
  • Two questions in epistemology
  • 1. What is knowledge?
  • 2. How much do we know?
  • These two questions lead to the following puzzle

39
The problem of the criterion
  • We can only answer the first question (What is
    knowledge?) if we already have an answer to the
    second question (What do we know?)
  • We can only answer the second question (What do
    we know?), If we already have an answer to the
    first question (What is knowledge?)
  • We are trapped in a circle.

40
Solving the problem of the criterion
  • First solution methodism you start with an
    answer to the questionWhat is knowledge?
  • Second solution particularism you start with an
    answer to the questionWhat do we know?

41
Problem for methodism
  • It is mysterious how can we give an account of
    the nature of knowledge without appealing to
    instances of what we think to know?

42
Problem for particularism
  • It assumes from the start that scepticism is
    false. But this is not something you can assume,
    it is something you have to argue for. (We will
    return to the problem of scepticism in a later
    lecture).

43
Gettier cases
  • The traditional analysis of knowledge
  • Knowledge Justified True Belief. This is
    supposed to be an analysis of the concept of
    knowledge in three sufficient and necessary
    conditions.
  • Problem for the traditional analysis of
    knowledge Gettier cases. These cases show that
    there is a justified true belief, but no
    knowledge!

44
Example of a Gettier case
  • Stopped clock case
  • Smith and Jones

45
Case 1
  • Suppose that Smith and Jones have applied for a
    certain job. And suppose that Smith has strong
    evidence for the following conjunctive
    proposition
  • d. Jones is the man who will get the job, and
    Jones has ten coins in his pocket.
  • Smith's evidence for (d) might be that the
    president of the company assured him that Jones
    would in the end be selected, and that he, Smith,
    had counted the coins in Jones's pocket ten
    minutes ago. Proposition (d) entails
  • e. The man who will get the job has ten coins in
    his pocket.
  • Let us suppose that Smith sees the entailment
    from (d) to (e), and accepts (e) on the grounds
    of (d), for which he has strong evidence. In this
    case, Smith is clearly justified in believing
    that (e) is true.
  • But imagine, further, that unknown to Smith, he
    himself, not Jones, will get the job. And, also,
    unknown to Smith, he himself has ten coins in his
    pocket. Proposition (e) is then true, though
    proposition (d), from which Smith inferred (e),
    is false.
  • In our example, then, all of the following are
    true (i) (e) is true, (ii) Smith believes that
    (e) is true, and (iii) Smith is justified in
    believing that (e) is true. But it is equally
    clear that Smith does not know that (e) is true
    for (e) is true in virtue of the number of coins
    in Smith's pocket, while Smith does not know how
    many coins are in Smith's pocket, and bases his
    belief in (e) on a count of the coins in Jones's
    pocket, whom he falsely believes to be the man
    who will get the job.

46
Case 2
  • Let us suppose that Smith has strong evidence for
    the following proposition
  • f. Jones owns a Ford.
  • Smith's evidence might be that Jones has at all
    times in the past within Smith's memory owned a
    car, and always a Ford, and that Jones has just
    offered Smith a ride while driving a Ford. Let us
    imagine, now, that Smith has another friend,
    Brown, of whose whereabouts he is totally
    ignorant. Smith selects three place names quite
    at random and constructs the following three
    propositions
  • g. Either Jones owns a Ford, or Brown is in
    Boston. h. Either Jones owns a Ford, or Brown is
    in Barcelona. i. Either Jones owns a Ford, or
    Brown is in Brest-Litovsk.
  • Each of these propositions is entailed by (f).
    Imagine that Smith realizes the entailment of
    each of these propositions he has constructed by
    (f), and proceeds to accept (g), (h), and (i) on
    the basis of (f). Smith has correctly inferred
    (g), (h), and (i) from a proposition for which be
    has strong evidence. Smith is therefore
    completely justified in believing each of these
    three propositions.  Smith, of course, has no
    idea where Brown is.
  • But imagine now that two further conditions hold.
    First Jones does not own a Ford, but is at
    present driving a rented car. And secondly, by
    the sheerest coincidence, and entirely unknown to
    Smith, the place mentioned in proposition (h)
    happens really to be the place where Brown is. If
    these two conditions hold, then Smith does not
    know that (h) is true, even though (i) (h) is
    true, (ii) Smith does believe that (h) is true,
    and (iii) Smith is justified in believing that
    (h) is true.

47
Gettier cases the problem
  • In all these cases, there is a justified true
    belief. But the belief does not count as
    knowledge nonetheless.
  • In the Gettier cases, something true is inferred
    from something false, and one has justification
    for the false proposition.

48
Gettier cases is there a solution?
  • Not really.
  • Attempts to add a 4th condition (a
    de-Gettierizer) have failed.
  • Attempts to replace the justification condition
    with another condition have failed.

49
Back to the problem of the criterion
  • Moral to draw there is no straightforward
    analysis of the concept of knowledge and so the
    question What is knowledge? Is hard to answer.
  • Problem if knowledge is really such a hard
    concept to analyse, how can it be that we find it
    so easy to determine whether something is a case
    of knowledge or not?

50
PH1513 Knowledge and Mind
  • Thursday, March 15th 2007

51
Recap of previous lecture
  • Problem of the criterion
  • Gettier cases

52
Overview
  • I. The elusiveness of knowledge
  • II. Justification and Gettier cases
  • III. What is justification?
  • IV. Four views on the structure of justification

53
The elusiveness of knowledge
  • We all apply the concept of knowledge in a very
    skilled way. That is to say we are good at
    determining whether someone knows something in a
    given case and also at determining whether
    someone does not know something in a given case.
  • Yet we have so far been unable to give a
    counterexample-free analysis of knowledge in a
    set of necessary and sufficient conditions. For
    every solution to Gettier cases, new
    counterexamples have emerged.
  • What does this show?

54
At least three options
  • (i) Knowledge is conceptually primitive and
    cannot be analysed at all. The only thing we can
    provide is give a useful gloss of this concept.
    This option questions the assumption that
    knowledge can be analysed in necessary and
    sufficient conditions.
  • (ii) Knowledge is a pluralistic concept there
    are multiple analyses of knowledge and they are
    all correct. This option questions the assumption
    that there is only one correct answer to the
    question what is knowledge?
  • (iii) Knowledge is to be analysed in one set of
    conditions. But although we think that we are
    skilled in determining whether there is knowledge
    in a given case, we are not as skilled as we
    think we are we often get it wrong.
  • (iv) We have not been trying hard enough to find
    the correct analysis of knowledge.
  • In what follows, we will play along with option
    (iv).

55
JTB and Gettier Cases.
  • Gettier cases show that defining knowledge in
    terms of justified true belief is inadequate.
    There are cases in which a subject has a JTB
    without knowledge.
  • Still, most people think that even though JTB is
    not sufficient for knowledge, it still is
    necessary.
  • This raises the question what is justification?
    If we want to understand what knowledge is, we
    have ot understand what justification is.

56
Justification
  • So what is justification?
  • Consider an everyday belief the belief that you
    have two hands. What does it mean to say that
    this belief is justified?
  • It could mean that the belief is supported in an
    appropriate way.
  • Supported by what? By adequate reasons or grounds.

57
Example
  • You believe that you have hands.
  • This belief is justified only if it is supported
    by adequate grounds.
  • One such ground could be the further belief that
    you are perceiving your hands.
  • But now a problem arises how is this latter
    belief justified? For it to be justified it has
    to be based on grounds as well. What are they?

58
The structure of reasons
  • We are thus faced with a problem regarding the
    structure of reasons. If justification means that
    beliefs are based on adequate grounds in the form
    of supporting beliefs, then the question arises
    what supports these supporting beliefs?

59
Four options regarding the structure of reasons
  • 1. The chain of reasons ends with an unsupported
    belief.
  • 2. The chain of reasons ends with a supported
    belief (foundationalism).
  • The chain of reasons goes on without an end
    (infinitism).
  • The chain of reasons circles back on itself
    (coherentism).

60
Infinitism
  • Here the idea is that an infinite chain of
    justification (of supporting grounds) can justify
    beliefs. Most people oppose this view on the
    grounds that it is counterintuitive. But some
    argue (most notably Peter Klein) that besides the
    worry of counterintuitiveness, it is unclear why
    an infinite chain could not justify beliefs.

61
Coherentism
  • This is the view that a circular chain of
    justification can justify a belief.
  • Support for coherentism tends to cite the fact
    that this is the way in which we usually justify
    our beliefs.
  • It can be reasonable to believe something given a
    specific web of beliefs, but unreasonable to
    believe something given another web of beliefs.
  • Metaphor a raft

62
Problem for coherentism
  • Rick the inflexible mountain climber he has a
    coherent set of beliefs that is completely
    unrelated to reality.

63
Foundationalism
  • This is the view that the chain of justification
    ends with a justified belief.
  • The end of the chain is a belief that is
    justified in a basic way it does not derive its
    justification from anything else.
  • Metaphor pyramid

64
Problem for foundationalism
  • It is self-referentially incoherent.
  • How to identify which beliefs can serve as
    foundations. Too strict we dont know much. Too
    narrow we know too much.

65
Next week
  • More on the structure of knowledge.

66
PH1513 Knowledge and Mind
  • Tuesday, March 20th 2007

67
Recap
  • Foundationalism
  • Coherentism
  • Infitinism

68
The use of strange cases in epistemology
  • Epistemologists often use very strange and
    improbably cases to argue for particular
    positions, such as last weeks Rick the
    inflexible mountain climber example. How bad is
    this?

69
Strange cases, continued
  • One answer not bad at all, so long as the cases
    are at least logically possible.
  • Another answer quite bad, since the analysis of
    knowledge one ends up with when taking into
    account all these strange cases will not be
    grounded in the everyday practice of using
    knowledge at all. It is a philosophical
    artefact.

70
Knowledge what is it?
  • Knowledge cannot be equal to Justified True
    Belief.
  • Replace Justification with something else.

71
Reliabilism
  • Knowledge is a cognitive achievement.
  • justification is one way of cashing out this
    element, but this was shown to be vulnerable to
    Gettier cases.
  • reliabilism is another way of specifying what
    it means to say that knowledge is a cognitive
    achievement. This is not vulnerable to Gettier
    cases. Think back to the stopped clock case no
    knowledge because the clock is not reliable.

72
Reliabilism, continued
  • According to reliabilism, knowledge is equal to a
    true belief that results from reliable
    belief-forming mechanisms.
  • reliable here refers to the method used which
    must result in more true beliefs than false
    beliefs.
  • If your belief was reliably formed, then you have
    genuinely achieved something.

73
A Gettier problem for reliablism
  • Thermometer example you look at a broken
    thermometer to determine the temperature in the
    room. The thermometer is broken and it randomly
    fluctuates. The thermometer is also reliable in
    the sense that even though it is broken it
    always gives the correct temperature. The reason
    is that some in the room who is hidden to you is
    adjusting the temperature of the room whenever
    she sees you looking at the thermometer such that
    the room temperature always matches the random
    thermometer readings.
  • No knowledge, but still a reliable true belief!
    Also no cognitive achievement since your beliefs
    do not adapt themselves to match the world.
    Rather, the world adapts itself to your beliefs.

74
Virtue Epistemology
  • Even though reliabilism faces this
    counterexample, there is something right about
    it. Think back to the archery example a skilled
    archer will hit the target in a wide range of
    different conditionsthis is what it means to be
    a skilled archer being reliable.
  • The same goes for the knower, who should not just
    stumble on a true belief, or hit the truth by
    accident, but should hit the truth out of genuine
    skill and, hence, reliability.

75
Virtue Epistemology
  • One way to cash out this idea is in terms of
    epistemic virtues or cognitive capacities.
  • An epistemic virtue is a character trait that
    makes one better suited to hitting the truth /
    hitting more true beliefs than false beliefs.
  • Examples conscientiousness.

76
Virtue Epistemology and the thermometer example
  • This way of cashing out reliabilism in terms of
    epistemic virtues can help to solve the
    thermometer example.
  • One could now say that the subject does not have
    a reliably formed true belief at all. The reason
    is that the belief is true merely because the
    hidden person interferes.

77
Another problem for reliabilism
  • Chicken sexer someone who, by being raised
    around chickens, has developed a highly reliable
    capacity to distinguish male chicks from female
    chicks. Crucially, they tend to have false
    beliefs about the way in which they are
    distinguishing between the sex of the chicks.
  • Some intuit that chicken sexers do not know that
    a particular chick is, for instance, male, even
    though the person has a reliably formed true
    belief that results from an epistemic virtue.

78
Internalism / Externalism
  • Others intuit that the chicken sexer does know
    that the chick is, for instance two different
    epistemic theories internalism and externalism.

79
Internalism
  • In order to know something, one has to be aware
    of the fact that the reasons for the belief are
    good reasons.
  • If this is what is required for Knowledge, then
    the chicken sexer does not know.

80
Externalism
  • In order to know a proposition, it is not
    necessary that the subject is aware of the
    reasons for the belief being good reasons.
  • On this view, the chicken sexer does know.

81
Next lecture
  • More on internalism / externalism

82
PH1513
  • Thursday, March 22nd 2007

83
Practical
  • No lectures in the following three weeks.
  • Lectures/tutorials commence in the week of April
    16th.
  • Worksheets all in one document online.

84
Recap
  • 1. Reliabilism
  • 2. Epistemic Virtues
  • 3. Internalism / Externalism

85
Internalism versus Externalism
  • Two perspectives on what knowledge is
    internalism and externalism
  • These perspectives relate either to justification
    (to the condition that has to be added to true
    belief in order to get knowledge) or to
    knowledge
  • Knowledge internalism/externalism
  • Justification internalism/externalism.

86
Internalism
  • According to internalism, the subject must have
    reflective access to the evidence on which her
    belief that p is based, and must, furthermore, be
    able to determine that the evidence is good
    evidence.
  • Worry for internalism radical scepticism. The
    demands are very stringent.

87
Externalism
  • According to externalism, it is not necessary for
    the subject to be aware of the fact that her
    belief is based on adequate evidence. You can
    know a proposition even if you dont know that it
    is based on good evidence.
  • Worry for externalism is this really knowledge?

88
Illustration chicken sexers
  • Someone who, by being raised around chickens, has
    developed a highly reliable capacity to
    distinguish male chicks from female chicks.
    Crucially, they tend to have false beliefs about
    the way in which they are distinguishing between
    the sex of the chicks.
  • Some intuit that chicken sexers do not know that
    a particular chick is, for instance, male, even
    though the person has a reliably formed true
    belief. The reason is that the subject has no
    reflective access to the evidence on which her
    belief is based.
  • Other intuit that chicken sexers do know that a
    particular chick is, for instance, male, even
    though the subject is not able to determine that
    the evidence is good evidence.
  • The first answer will be given by persons with
    internalist intuitions.
  • The second answer will be given by persons with
    externalist intuitions.

89
Internalism/ExternalismFoundationalism/Coherentis
m
  • Four options
  • 1. Internalist foundationalism
  • 2. Externalist foundationalism
  • 3. Internalist coherentism
  • 4. Externalist coherentism

90
Motivation for internalism
  • Epistemic responsibility
  • Epistemic deontology there are epistemic duties.
  • Examples
  • You should not believe falsehoods.
  • You should only believe the truth.
  • In order for the idea of duties to make sense,
    you should be able to have access to your
    evidence in order to determine whether you should
    indeed believe something. So this seems to imply
    internalism.

91
An argument for deontology
  • Maud believes herself to have the power of
    clairvoyance, though she has no reasons for this
    belief. She maintains her belief despite being
    inundated by her embarrassed friends and
    relatives with massive quantities of apparently
    cogent scientific evidence that no such power is
    possible. One day Maud comes to believe, for no
    apparent reason, that the President is in New
    York City, and she maintains this belief, despite
    the lack of any independent evidence, appealing
    to her alleged clairvoyant power. Now in fact the
    President is in New York City, and Maud does,
    under the conditions then satisfied, have
    completely reliable clairvoyant power. Moreover,
    her belief about the President did result from
    the operation of that power. (Bonjour, 1980. p.
    61)

92
  • According to BonJour no knowledge.
  • Reason no justification, because Maud is
    irresponsible in accepting this belief.
  • This suggests a deontological reading of
    justification.

93
A problem for deontology
  • If there are duties, we should be able to choose
    what to believe and what not to believe.
    Otherwise, the idea of a duty does not make
    sense.
  • It is implausible to say that we can choose what
    to believe. We dont have voluntary control.

94
Direct versus indirect voluntary control
  • No direct control.
  • There is indirect control over what we believe.

95
Another argument for internalism
  • You know that p only if you can justify that p.
    But what it means to justify that p is that you
    are able to give justification for p.
  • So the very nature of justification implies that
    this is an internalist notion.
  • Problem young children cannot do this but can
    still be justified.

96
After the Spring Break
  • Sources of knowledge perception, memory,
    testimony, reasoning.

97
Knowledge and Mind
  • Tuesday, April 17th 2007

98
Knowledge and sources of knowledge
  • We have discussed what knowledge is (how the
    concept of knowledge should be analyzed).
  • We have discussed whether knowledge should be
    analyzed in an internalist or externalist way.
  • We have discussed what the structure of knowledge
    is (foundationalism or coherentism).

99
Knowledge and sources of knowledge
  • It is now time to discuss where knowledge
    (whatever it is) comes from.
  • Some standardly recognized sources are
  • Perception,
  • Memory,
  • Reasoning, and
  • Testimony.

100
Sources of knowledge
  • Of these sources, perception, testimony, and
    reasoning can produce knowledge.
  • Memory, however, can not produce knowledge but
    can only retain knowledge that is already present
    (and was produced by either perception,
    testimony, or reasoning).

101
Relations between different sources
  • There are various relations between the sources
    of knowledge.
  • No testimony without perception.
  • No memory without perception.
  • No reasoning without perception (?).
  • No perception without memory (?)

102
Testimony
  • One of the most important sources of knowledge.
  • Much of what we know depends on testimony.
  • Two types of question

103
Testimony two questions
  • 1. What is testimony?
  • 2. How does testimony give justification to a
    belief based on that testimony?

104
1. The Nature of Testimony
  • In which cases do we speak of testimony?
  • Does testimony imply truth? Can you testify
    something if what you say is false?
  • Does testimony imply that you believe that what
    you testify is true? Can you testify something if
    you believe that what you say is false (even
    though it might in fact be true)?

105
The Nature of Testimony
  • Does testimony imply the intention to testify?
  • John is sitting in his room. In the next room,
    his neighbour Jill is talking to herself again.
    She says I really hate my boyfriend. She did
    not have the intention to communicate this
    information to John. Did she testify that she
    hates her boyfriend?

106
The Nature of Testimony
  • Can you testify by manifestation?
  • John is sitting in the park. Next to him, a
    middle-aged lady sitts down. She starts singing
    in a very high voice. John forms the belief that
    she is a soprano. Did the middle-aged lady
    testify that she is a soprano?

107
Testimony and Justification
  • Two types of answer to the question whether
    testimony-based beliefs can be justified.
  • Reductionism
  • Non-reductionism

108
Reductionism
  • Testimony-based beliefs are not justified in
    virtue of being based on testimony. Their
    justification reduces to something
    non-testimonial, for instance perception.
  • There always must be extra, additional, evidence
    for testimony-based beliefs if they are to be
    justified.
  • This is associated with the work of David Hume.

109
Non-reductionism
  • Beliefs based on testimony can have justification
    just in virtue of being based on testimony.
  • No extra, additional, evidence is needed to make
    these beliefs justified.
  • This is associated with the work of Thomas Reid.

110
Problems
  • For reductionism too strict. Many of our beliefs
    that are based on testimony seem justified to us
    without us being able to give extra evidence.
  • For non-reductionism too optimistic. It seems to
    lead to credulism.

111
Next lecture
  • More on testimony.
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com