Title: Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind 1
1Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind 1
- Dispensing with the given sense data first.
2The project
- Sellars aim here is to sort out his philosophy
of mind while retaining an empiricist
epistemology. - Issues
- The given Sellars rejects the notion that
anything is immediately apprehended in propria
persona there is no transparent awareness of
anything. - Sense-data talk and the relation between our use
of seems and ordinary observation reports. - How induction can be used to justify our claims
(as individuals) to be reliable observers. - Relations between rationalism and empiricism in
our philosophical tradition. Sellars wants to
reconcile these, recognizing the importance of
empirical evidence while also recognizing the
crucial role concepts play in all knowledge.
3The Given
- So what is the given?
- Not just something that we observe directly, i.e.
a claim we accept without inferring it from other
claims weve accepted. - Many things have been said to be given sense
contents, material objects, universals,
propositions, real connections, first principles,
even givenness itself. - A framework that is part of many different
philosophical positions. - Among the first forms to be criticized were
intuited first principles, synthetic necessary
connections. - Sellars aims to root it out entirely, not just
some particular forms of it.
4Why attack the given?
- Cognitive psychology our accounts of what and
how we know need to fit with our natural
understanding of what humans can learn to detect
and discriminate. - The neo-Hobbesian picture of humans that ends
Phenomenalism is incompatible with a view of
knowledge involving an immediate link between a
logically simple subject and some fact about the
world. - All knowledge is expressed in language, and
language can shift and change in many ways. - Our relation to the community and the conceptual
capacities that arise through language
instruction are indispensable elements in any
knowledge we have, no matter how direct (i.e.
non-inferential) it is.
5First target Sense data
- For x to be sensed is for it to be the object of
an act. - A sense content is a possible object for such an
act. - Kinds of sensing may just reduce to the kinds of
sense content that are their objects. - The point of these acts is to serve as a starting
point (foundation) for empirical knowledge. - But sense contents are particulars, the objects
of some sensings (i.e. acts of sensing). - And knowledge is about facts, not particulars.
(Broadly, it needs a subject-predicate form
That this object is characterized in some
particular way.)
6The dilemma
- The SD theorist has to choose between
- Sense contents are particulars, and sensing is
not knowing. - Sensing is a form of knowing facts, not
particulars, are sensed. - Even if she adopts the first, she can still say
that sensory knowledge is logically dependent on
sensings. - But SD theorists typically want to have their
cake and eat it too. - This can be done, with a little slippery move
- To sense a sense content is to sense it as having
a certain character. - When we sense a content as having a certain
character, we know that it has that character. - When we sense a sense content, we can say now
that we know it, without specifying the character
we sense it as having.
7Acquaintance
- This line gets comfort from the familiar fact
that we often do speak of knowing particulars, as
in I know Fred. - But the proposal before us links this to
non-inferential knowledge by the brute force of a
contextual definition To know x (where x is a
sense content) just is to know that x has some
character. - Sometimes this is ignored in accounts of the
givenness of sense contents but if sensings are
analyzable, we can recover the link to knowledge
if the analysis matches that of non-inferential
knowledge of some sensed fact about the sense
content.
8The given part
- Descriptive accounts of sense contents have to
smuggle this link back inAgain, Sellars rejects
any reduction of the normative to the
descriptive. - The main point here is that the sensing of sense
contents is not taken to require any learning,
setting up of associations, etc. It is a
primitive epistemic capacity built into us at the
outset. - As primitive, it is the starting point for the
rest of our knowledge Knowledge is acquired
first in this form, and then extended to wider
sorts of knowledge
9But categorization is acquired
- Theres a strong tendency in the field to regard
knowledge that x is Y requires learning to tell
Ys from non-Ys, the acquisition of the concept
of a Y, perhaps even the use of symbols for Yness
other components of this bit of knowledge. - The triad
- A. x senses red sense content s entails x
non-inferentially knows s is red. - B. The ability to sense sense contents is
unacquired. - C. The ability to know facts of the form x is ?
is acquired.
10The SD theorists choices
- Give up the first (A). Sensings now can be
involved in knowings, but they arent really
knowledge themselves. - Give up the second. Now sensings arent really an
account of sensations, which we can have without
learning - Give up the third. This is to give up the
nominalist proclivities of the empiricist
tradition.
11The diagnosis
- Sensings look to be a mongrel concept combining
ideas about sensations (states that play a
critical role in sensory knowledge and are
possible states for us from the outset, but are
not knowings in themselves) with ideas about
non-inferential knowings that are at the heart of
our empirical knowledge about the world around
us.
12Sources of the confusion
- A scientific explanation of the facts of
perception (and misperception) justifies the
postulation of inner states that are normally
brought about by objects with various sensible
characters under normal conditions. But there is
nothing epistemic about such states their role,
thus far, is causal.
13Second source
- The argument from security If our knowledge of
particular matters of fact starts with the things
we normally report as observations (this is red,
thats triangular, etc.) then it starts with
commitments some of which are false there is no
mark we can introspect that separates the
veridical ones from the non-veridical. This
seems to undermine the very idea of empirical
knowledge.
14The slide
- looks or seems talk has an apparent advantage
here. If we want certainty, we can retreat (by
degrees), getting - There is an object over there thats red and
triangular on the facing side. - There is an object over there that looks red and
triangulary on the facing side. - There looks to be an object over there thats red
and triangular on the facing side. - Each is increasingly secure the last seems
almost perfectly so.
15Describing the inner states
- Now it becomes tempting to take the third of
these as a description of ones inner state (its
the sort of state normally produced by objects
that are red and triangular on the facing side). - And this state is harder to be fooled about (its
more intimately linked to our faculty of
judgment than the properties of an external
object). - Further, it just doesnt make sense to talk about
an unveridical sensation. - Heres the key mis-step This implies that they
arent part of the space of reasons at all (they
are causal- we simply have sensations, i.e. they
occur in us and that all). Making them the
foundation of knowledge takes a position, rather
than report what is given to us.
16The sense-datum code
- If we introduce sense datum talk as a code for
seems talk, we need to be very careful not to
treat the code as though it were a language
with internal logical structure that we can
unpack to identify theoretical commitments. - The inferences we make in a sense-datum code must
follow those that are allowed when the code is
translated back into the language it is code for. - Theories are not just codes they are proper
languages, which add content to the assertions
they are linked to by bridge rules.
17A successful code
- If the illuminates our understanding of knowledge
and ordinary things, its because it leads us to
recognize that in fact we can trade in talk of
ordinary objects for seems talk in its most
non-commital sense There looks to be - Then ordinary things turn out to be
constructions out of lookings or appearings. - But this is untenable, says Sellars
18The Logic of looks
- Is looks a relation (between the subject, a
thing and a quality in x looks ? to s)? - Broad something elliptical must be before our
minds when a round penny looks elliptical.
Sense data (which have the characters things look
to have) are an explanation of such appearings. - Some resist such analyses, though, saying that
there need be nothing red involved when something
looks red to someone. - Sellars starts here with the point that, when we
say something looks red, we seem to be using red
in the familiar way, as a property of some
external objects.
19Logical priority
- For Sellars, being red is logically prior to
looking red. - So we cant analyze is red in terms of
looks-red. - But X is red iff X would look red to normal
perceivers under normal conditions is
necessarily true. If this isnt an analysis of
is red in terms of looks-red, what is it? - For Sellars, looks is not a relation (or, its
a relation if you like to say so, but we
shouldnt assumed the inferences that would
follow with other relation words go through for
looks).
20The tie shop
- Another vivid example here, of how someone who
has ordinary colour concepts can come to learn to
use looks talk. - John learns to say it looks green rather than
it is green (and it looks to be blue rather
than it is blue). - But what hes learned to report is not a new kind
of fact about the world. - What does it looks green report?
21Experiences and propositions
- When I report, I see that that is green, I dont
just report an experience I commit to (endorse)
a claim closely related to the experience. - This is to apply the concept of truth to the
experience. - When I say, instead, I seem to see that that is
green, I report the experience but I withhold the
commitment to truth. - One experience can be a seeing that x is green
an intrisically similar experience can be merely
a seeing that x looks green. - See that and looks talk both make the issue
of endorsement explicit.
22What looks come to
- To say that x looks green to s is to say that x
is having an experience which, if endorsed, we
would report by saying s sees x to be green. - But this makes the difference between normal
reports and looks talk a matter of backing
away from commitments that would normally be
associated with the experience being had. - And it puts in doubt the view that looks talk
is a way of describing the experience itself.
23Explaining the link
- Now we can explain the connection between looks
talk and is talk. - X is ? iff X would look ? to standard observers
in standard conditions is necessary because
standard conditions are conditions under which
things look as they are to standard observers. - These conditions are only vaguely specified, but
thats the way it is with ordinary talk - This undermines logical atomism, the idea that
basic concepts are all fundamentally independent
of each other. On this view we need a lot of
other concepts (pertaining to standard
conditions, in particular) before we can have
(e.g.) colour concepts.
24Conditions for knowledge
- We dont have even these very basic empirical
concepts, for Sellars, unless we can not only
report accurately (this is green, that is red,
etc.) but are also aware of, and able to detect
and report, the conditions under which such
spontaneous reports are reliable. - Logical atomists can move to sense data reports
to defend their position. But their commitment
to sense contents is not supported by anything in
Sellars treatment of looks talk, so these folk
will have to haul their own water if they want to
defend this position.
25Looking red
- Can we go from somethings looking red to there
being something red that were aware of? - First challenge Univocity. The red things look
to have is the very red some things do have so
to say that its a sense content that is red
when something looks red to us is peculiar
sense contents are very different from physical
objects, but this line forces on them all the
sensible properties we ordinarily attribute to
physical things.
26Explanations
- If we want to explain why x looks red to s, we
can often do it by saying, well, s is in C
circumstances, and x is orange, and in C
circumstances orange things look red. - But we can give other sorts of explanation, which
bring us closer to the heart of sense content and
sense data talk. - Such an explanation would focus on sensations
(the inner postulated entities Sellars has
already accepted). But this makes the most
non-theoretical items (for sense-data theorists)
into theoretical items, driving the wedge too
early.
27A more sympathetic account
- Experiences can have shared propositional
contents that receive varying degrees of
endorsement (full all the way to none at all). - The shared content of all these is the
descriptive content of this account of an
experience. - But looks talk only specifies this description
of our experience indirectly (as in, if conds
were standard, it would be a seeing that x is
red). - So we have an open question What is the shared
intrinsic character of these experiences?
28Invoking red talk
- The obvious trick here is to invoke talk of red
to describe this content. - But we need to separate red from physical things
to do this. - Here we run into the familiar analogy Sellars has
already invoked in other papers. - The red of experiences here is not the red of
physical things, but it is analogous to it. - Some try to avoid this by separating things from
their surfaces, and invoking wild surfaces in
cases of mere looking. - But we dont really think things have surfaces
as this two-dimensional, detachable account
proposes.
29Impressions and Ideas Logical Concerns
- Ings and eds An experience is often thought
of as a process that occurs in us this is an
experiencing, the having of an experience. - But experiences are also thought of in terms of
what is experienced in them (the object of the
experience). - Sellars is concerned here that we not move too
quickly from a description of an experiencing to
conclusions about what it is that is experienced
in that experiencing. - In particular, what he calls the common (
shared) descriptive component of our
descriptions of experiences may well not be what
is experienced for instance, if a red item is
part of this CDC, we may not in fact have
experienced anything red.
30Names, labels etc.
- So the question arises Do we really have a name
for such experiences? - What about of here? Cant we describe these
experiencings as experiences of red? Cant we
add sensation talk here, and talk about
sensations of red? - An objection if red is always properly read
as a property of physical objects, an experience
or sensation of red demands something red just as
much as a red experience would. - But the of we use in talk of ideas, the
intentional of, doesnt imply the existence of
the thing an idea is of (nor does believes in) - This logical feature shared by sensation of and
believes in does not require further parallels
between sensation talk and intentional contexts. - And this is despite the fact that historically
the assimilation of sensations to ideas was
widely endorsed.
31Objective existence
- So for Descartes and many other early moderns,
just as red was said to have objective
existence in the idea of a red triangle, it was
also said to have objective existence in the
sensation (or impression, in Humes terminology)
of a red triangle. - Sensations were simply thought of as more
detailed and specific than the abstract
thoughts we form. - But this is clearly a mistake, and the
non-extensionality that makes it tempting does
not give us any real argument for it.
32Still looking
- So were still looking for an intrinsic
description/label for these experiences. - But historically many have taken the view that
this is just wrong-headed we know exactly what
kind of experience this is, through our
privileged inner awareness of it. - This leads to the problem of other minds, of
course. - But its also a clear instance of the given
this time, what is said to be given is the
kinds to which our sensations belong.
33Two questions
- How do we become aware of the sorts that our
experiences fall under? - How do we communicate/share the categories each
of us has for their experiences? - The view Sellars is criticizing here thinks the
given is an answer to the first, and accepts
that there is no answer to the second. - This answer to the first assumes that our
awareness of the sorts under which our
experiences are to be classified is given, a
feature of immediate experience. - Recall here Sellars earlier invocation of the
empiricist notion that all categorization of
items under sorts requires learning.
34Universals, repeatables and determinables
- For Sellars a universal is a repeatable (this is
the std. view today). - Thus even a very specific/determinate sort of
experience (my current visual fields character,
for instance) can be a universal, since this
arrangement of colours etc. can be repeated in a
later experience. - But the tradition (Locke et al.) thought of
universals as generic, i.e. as abstracting from
these details, and passed over the problem of
repeatables to focus on the formation of such
more general ideas. (Note the nice discussion of
the need for both conjunctive and disjunctive
ideas to cope with the phenomena here.)
35The key point again
- LBH all agree that merely by having sensations we
have the idea of determinate repeatables or
sorts. - A nominalist alternative suppose we think of
the awareness of a red sensation as the awareness
of a red particular, rather than as the awareness
of its being red. - Then the formation of ideas of repeatables would
proceed by the association of words (red) with
a range of resembling particulars. - But the association needs to be handled
carefully If we think of it as grounded on a
prior awareness of the particulars as resembling
or even as red then the myth of the given rises
again. - If we instead reject these, and simply say that
it is the group of particulars that is associated
with the word, then we get a kind of nominalism
it is only from the later point of view, where we
have a language in which to pick out classes of
resembling particulars, that we are aware of
their resemblance before that, all we have are a
range of patterns of response that we can be
trained in.
36The upshot
- This is not Sellars nominalism its pretty
crude, really. - But it does break the link between sensations and
thought-contents, freeing up the direct
perception account according to which words are
directly linked to the external world and its
features, not to our sensations or impressions. - The essential causal role of red sensations is
not undermined by this but it is not an
inferential role in which our awareness of the
immediately available redness of some
sensations provides the facts and ideas out of
which we somehow arrive at the idea of redness as
a feature of physical things.
37The logic of means
- The object here is to provide more material for
Sellars psychological nominalism, the view that
we have no awareness of logical space prior
to/independent of learning a language. - But Sellars rejects the crudely associative view
of how words are linked to the things they apply
to. - On this view, red means what it does because it
has the syntax (grammar) of a predicate and is
a response to red things. - This isnt nearly enough (its too atomistic) for
Sellars. - But it wouldnt even be tempting if it werent
for the naïve word-world view of means contexts.
38Recalling BBK
- Here we find points familiar from BBK means
for Sellars invokes translation (and a rich
normative parallel between the two items joined
by means as in Rot (in German) means red.) - This covers the ground in a way that the more
common view cannot, since it equates the force of
means in - Und means and.
- Rot means red.
39Simple association is not enough
- So the mere invocation of means contexts does
not generate a theory of how a word comes to play
a role sufficiently similar to that of another
for us to say that they have the same meaning. - In fact, this standard is rich and flexible
translation is a complex art, and its demands
vary with our communicative aims/concerns - In particular, understanding red requires quite
a bit more than the grammar of a predicate and an
association with red things. Linguistic
thermometers are not enough to capture meanings.
40Foundations
- A foundation for empirical knowledge, for
Sellars, is a pretty specific thing. - The myth requires that the foundation be facts
that are - Non-inferentially known.
- Such that knowledge of them presupposes no other
knowledge. - Such that all knowledge of empirical matters of
fact is ultimately decided by reference to
knowledge of these foundational facts.
41Something emphasized
- Some argue that, if a piece of knowledge depends
on having some other knowledge, it must in fact
depend on inference in some way. - For Sellars this is a mistake, and its part of
the myth. The kind of dependence that his holism
invokes does not make all our knowledge a product
of inference. - But it does make its content dependent on our
grasping its inferential relations to other
claims.
42Details
- Observation reports seem to have authority,
without being inferred from other claims we
already believe. - How shall we understand this authority?
- One key is the link between reports and
circumstances. - This point turns on the distinction between
fact-stating uses of sentences and report-making
uses.
43Token-reflexives
- Words like here, now, this or that are
token-reflexive they link up to their
circumstances of utterance in ways that lead the
same sentence to make different assertions in
different circumstances. - Tensed verbs have much the same effect, since
they are tied to times of utterance too. - Reports regularly, though not necessarily, make
use of these sorts of linguistic device to link
the report made to the circumstances it is a
report about. - A report must have some kind of direct link to
the circumstances it reports about - Fact-stating doesnt depend on circumstances in
the same way.
44Two sources of credibility
- Some sentence tokens are credible because they
are tokens of a type all tokens of which have
authority. - But some sentence tokens are credible because of
how they are linked to the circumstances in which
a token is produced The token came to be
through a certain process under certain
circumstances.
45Authority for sentence types
- Sellars says some sentence types are
intrinsically authoritative some analytic
sentences belong to this group. - Some get authority by inferential links to
others. - But empirical knowledge will not reduce (without
some residue) to these two groups. (No empirical
sentence type has intrinsic authority, and
inferential links to such wont do the trick
either.) - So we need sentence types whose authority comes
from tokens that are produced in the right way
and in the right circumstances.
46The flow of credibility
- These two sources of credibility flow in opposite
directions - Credibility for analytic sentences flows from
types to their tokens, and then via inference to
some other sentence types. - Credibility for observation sentences flows from
tokens to types, and then again via inference to
other sentence types.
47Sellars on Empiricist Dogmas
- Conflating the authority of analytic and
observational sentences An attempt at a unified
theory of credibility leads to trouble. - The idea is to appeal to rules just as the rules
for using the concepts in an analytic sentence
ensure that it must be true, the rules for using
the language involved in an observation report
are such that, if they are followed when the
report is made, the observation report is true.
48Prefatory points
- Reports can be thought of as stripped of their
action and interpersonal aspectsa mere,
spontaneous thinking that p can be a report. - But thinking of them as actions has influenced
the tradition here, which construes the rightness
of a report as a special case of the rightness of
actions (under some system of rules). - When we think of them this way, we have to
construe them as deliberate followings of these
rules (otherwise the rule is a mere
regularity). - That is, we have to judge that the circumstances
were such that the rule requires the report and
make the report for that reason.
49The given again
- This leads directly to the given again, since
these observation-actions are correct only when
they are made in the course of following a rule,
which requires that we be able to judge that the
circumstances are such that the rule
requires/endorses the report. - Such judgments depend on a primitive awareness of
the matters of fact necessary to apply the rules
for using these words. - Recall that we are talking here about the
foundational judgments that are at the root of
all empirical knowledge so there is no escape...
50But is there a way out?
- Begin with mere reliable reporting the
thermometer account. - Now, can we extend this to cover something more
properly like knowledge? - The key question is authoritybut authority for
what? - Actions are not what we need here mere behaviour
of a type that its reasonable to endorse is
enough (action presupposes too much
deliberateness here).
51Being a knower
- The key, however, is the subjects own ability to
recognize that she is in a position of authority
with respect to such reports. - That is, she must be in a position to recognize
that she is a standard observer in standard
conditions, so that her inclination to report
this is green is indeed reliable. - This requires quite sophisticated conceptual
grasp of the place of such reports in the world - It also seems to require a kind of induction.
52The threat of a regress
- The idea is that to make a report that expresses
observational knowledge, one would have to know
that such overt verbal performances are reliable
indicators of the facts reported. - And this means that all observational knowledge
depends on a fair bit of knowledge that. In
fact, we need to know things like X is a
reliable symptom of Y. - So observations dont stand on their own feet
individually. - Worse, it seems to run counter to the empiricist
notion that the sort of general knowledge we have
when we know X is a reliable symptom of Y depends
on having a lot of knowledge of particular cases
where X is correlated with Y.
53Responding to the regress
- This seems to be a regress- before we can
actually know, by observation, that we have a
case of Y, we need to know that X is a reliable
symptom of Y. - But we need to know cases of Y (and cases of X)
to justify the claim that X is a reliable
symptom of Y. OUCH! - But when we classify an episode or event as a
case of knowing, we are locating it in a
normative space. Its possible to establish the
normative status of an episode retrospectively.
The regress dissolves (p. 169).
54Rejecting the foundation
- Sellars rejects the idea of observational
responses that are both direct and immediate. - Such observations would be self-authenticating,
that is, they would stand on their own but they
are, at root, non-verbal, internal episodes. - And this authority is transmitted to linguistic
acts (reports) because of an awareness of the
rules governing how these episodes are to be
characterized in words. - Once we have the force of these episodes cast in
linguistic terms, inference connects them to
other sentences, so that these episodes become
the foundation for all our empirical knowledge.
55Launching the constructive phase
- The point of the rest of the paper is to explain
Sellars own views on the nature and role of
inner episodes. - The sense in which they are non-verbal does not
(says Sellars) lend any support to the idea of
the given. - But Sellars rejection of this particular view of
the foundation of empirical knowledge is not a
rejection of the broader idea that there are
observation-reporting sentences that serve as the
touchstone for empirical knowledge. It is aimed
at the idea of the given (which is related to the
demand that the foundation be locked in and
independent of any other knowledge). - The active element of self-correction is crucial
here.
56Philosophy of science
- Sellars is concerned about the effects of
specialization in particular, the recognition of
philosophy of science as a distinct
specialization in philosophy. - The worry seems to be that specialization may
lead other philosophers to leave science to the
philosophers of science, and lose track of the
need for all philosophers to respond to the
development of the scientific world view. - Science is the flowering of an aspect of
discourse that is part of the ordinary world
view, and which may be lost sight of if we dont
attend to science and how it works in our
philosophical thinking.
57Evaluation
- To evaluate features of our conceptual frameworks
requires an appreciation of science as revealing
standards of evaluation and alternative
frameworks that may well do better in terms of
those standards. - This needs care the tendency to say things like
physical objects are not really coloured is a
confused way of recognizing that a framework that
includes such objects has deficiencies that are
put right in a different framework, now under
construction in the scientific enterprise. - On these questions, science is the measure.
58The given as a barrier here
- If we take some aspect of the manifest image as
given then this kind of critique is blocked a
framework anchored in the given is one were
stuck with (we can alter it in various ways, but
the basics are fixed). - This anchor is sometimes thought of as an
ostensive tie linking the concepts of the
framework to a aspect of reality. But consider
the oddity of the idea of an inner ostension. - This goes with the idea that science is not a
complete framework in its own right, but a mere
auxiliary.
59As if
- The suggestion is that the unquestionable nature
of the given locks us into any framework that
it arises in. - The upshot is that an alternative framework which
outperforms the given framework must be treated
in terms of as if, that is, the things of the
given framework can be thought of as behaving as
if some other framework were true but we can
never dispense with the given framework in favour
of this new (and superior) one.
60The other error
- The other barrier to what Sellars sees to a
correct appreciation of the scientific framework
is the reification of a methodological
distinction between theoretical and
non-theoretical discourse into a substantive
distinction. - The contrast
- Science as a peninsular offshoot of ordinary
discourse vs. - Science as an expression of a fundamental aspect
of discourse which is central and ultimately
transformative.
61Private episodes
- We still have no take on how it is that the
experience that is a seeing that x over there is
green is similar to one that is merely a seeing
that x over there looks green. - Two routes
- Introduce inner episodes as theoretical posits
and develop an account of the similarity within
that theory. - Posit these similarities as given.
- The second is now ruled out, so we need to turn
to the first, however peculiar it may seem.
62Applying the critique of the given
- red etc. apply to physical objects first, so
while we tend to describe these experiences using
such words, this use of those words cannot be
univocal. - If we just use these words to link the
experiences to standard occasions on which such
experiences occur, then we have a definite
description of such experiences that picks them
out, but nothing to say about what they are
really like. - To be able to notice a certain kind of thing (as
being of that kind) is already to have a concept
of that kind of thing. (176) - One central puzzle The combination of privacy
(only I can report my inner states) with
intersubjectivity (others can know about them in
other ways/ inferentially). Sellars says we can
have both! - But before dealing with sensations, Sellars turns
to consider thoughts.
63Thoughts
- Even if we take the view that thoughts are
linguistic, the number of cases where overt
linguistic behaviour accompanies behaviour that
it seems to explain is too few the sorts of
behaviour that we explain in terms of thoughts
are often unaccompanied by any overt linguistic
behaviour. - And when that behaviour is not habitual (more or
less automatic), we can hardly resist invoking
thoughts to explain it. - The classical account holds that there are inner
episodes called thoughts, and linguistic
behaviours are meaningful insofar as they express
those thoughts. Further, these episodes are
introspectible and even transparent (self-
revealing/ known whenever they are had).
64The core of the notion
- We each have a stream of these inner episodes.
- We have privileged, but not infallible or
complete, access to them. - They occur, sometimes, without overt verbal
behaviour. - We dont need a performance to be going on that
we perceive inwardly here. - Thoughts are a sort of linguistic episode, that
is, they are modeled on over speech.
65The Ryleans
- Here we imagine our ancestors, speaking a
somewhat limited language. - The language describes external objects in terms
of their sensible features. - Sellars also supposes that it has semantic
concepts so they can speak of meanings (read
in terms of the roles of words phrases) - The aim is to explore how a language like this
can come to have the means to talk of inner
episodes.
66On semantics again
- The force of semantic talk includes implications
about the typical causes and effects of certain
utterances. - But it is not exhausted by these implications.
- More importantly here, having semantical talk
allows us to say a lot of things about utterances
that are also commonly said about thoughts (that
they are about, or refer to, something, etc.) - We could try, then, to capture thoughts just by
appeal to a conditional/hypothetical link to
overt language and its semantics.
67The Alternative?
- Inner episodes (rather than conditional/hypothetic
al speech). - The classical notion also makes these episodes
the primary vehicles of meaning but Sellars will
reject this aspect of the classical view. - So the challenge is to combine a speech first
view of meaning with an account of thoughts as
real inner episodes.
68Theories and Models
- Here we encounter the philosophy of science
again, which Sellars will draw on to explain his
view of the status of these inner episodes. - We typically develop a theory by positing certain
entities and certain postulates about how they
behave. - These are then linked to some observable
phenomena (regularities or empirical laws) in
effect, we propose that the phenomena are as they
are because they involve these items in a certain
way. - But in fact theories are typically developed in a
very different way. - We generally draw on known behaviours of familiar
objects (waves, for example), and present these
as a model of what is going on with respect to
some phenomena. - Such models are qualified (we dont propose that
electromagnetic waves are just like waves in
water, but that they are similar in some
respects, while different in others.)
69Continuity
- Further, common-sense is not limited to
induction. (Unlike the idealized MI, it can
invoke postulated entities too and for Sellars,
the MI does contain fossilized posits, despite
its limitation to inductive methods.) - So our Ryleans will have the ability to develop
postulational explanations for similarities and
differences in the behaviour of physical things.
70Behaviourism
- Note that this was a major influence in
psychology when Sellars was writing EPM. - Sellars rejects narrow forms of behaviourism,
while being perfectly happy with methodological
behaviourism. - This does not require that psychological concepts
be analyzable into behavioural terms, but only
that assertions in our new, scientific
psychological language be justified by
behavioural evidence. - So, while we introduce these concepts by means of
their links to behaviour, we do not suppose that
their meaning is exhausted by this link to
behaviour they can be fully fledged theoretical
concepts.
71Expectations
- Of course we expect any such theory to link up to
our physiological understanding of the nervous
system and its role in behaviour. - But this does not mean that the behaviourists
concepts are physiological at the outset - It does mean that our concepts are both linked to
behaviour and linked to our expectations of how
they will fit in with other aspects of our
understanding of the world.
72Back to Jones
- Jones proposes a theory of inner episodes,
modeled on overt speech. - These explain intelligent behaviour that goes on
even when no overt commentary accompanies it. - The episodes carry the semantic force of the
speech acts they are modeled on. - And they are taken as the real, proximate
causes of intelligent behaviour, even when
accompanied by an overt explanatory discourse. - Think here of how we accompany demonstration with
commentary when instructing people in how to do
something
73More details
- The commentary follows, explaining the parallels
between speech and thought and where the two
differ. - One important point Nothing in the theory
requires that we have thoughts first and language
second the ability to have thoughts may depend
on learning a language. - Another The theory does not imply that thoughts
are the truly semantic items, with utterances
only semantic in a derivative sense, as
expressing certain thoughts. - Finally, these inner episodes need not be
construed as immediate experiences no perceptual
model of them is implied here.
74Introspection
- Having been taught to use this theory, people
find that they can sometimes report their
thoughts without relying on the overt behavioural
evidence others need to reach the same
conclusion. - Now the theoretical language has a reporting
role, and its one that recognizes a kind of
privileged access. - But the concepts involved are still public, and
their link to behaviour is still part of their
meaning so the privacy involved here is not
absolute or incorrigible.
75Inner perceptual episodes
- Now were ready for Jones second theory inner
episodes modeled on the perceptible features of
objects, which are invoked to explain illusions
and related perceptual phenomena. - This provides us with a theory in which we really
do have a description of the inner episode that
is the same when we see a red triangle, see a
triangle that looks red, see something that looks
like a red triangle and merely seem to see a red
triangle. - The price, of course, is to accept that these
inner states are postulated, not given.
76Details
- These are episodes (goings-on) not particulars.
- They should not be construed in
perceptual/epistemological terms The model is
not, a seeing of a red triangle but a red
triangular surface. - In general, we have the occurrence of inner
replicas a matter of a description of whats
going on in us, not normative matter at all. - The terms the theory provides give us a
substantive description of these states, rather
than the mere definite descriptions used so far.
77The content of the description
- The content of the description is a matter of the
theoretical language and the inferences it
supports. - Thus we know that the relations of compatibility,
incompatibility, etc. grounded in the ways
objects sensible properties can be arranged are
shared by these theoretical predicates describing
our impressions/sensations. - But the limits of the parallel are not clearly
specified yet, and can be worked out/explored in
a pretty open-ended way.
78Contentless form?
- Sellars objects to the view that such concepts
(characterized by their internal inferential
relations and by a link to certain
observational circumstances) are themselves
contentless. - For him they are no more contentless than any
other theoretical predicate, - And the view that all such predicates are formal/
contentless is a part of the myth of the given
(according to which only the predicates that are
part of the given have real (ostensive) content.
79Expectations
- What is the relation between these states of
perceivers and physiological models of ourselves?
- In the long run we expect them to fit together,
giving a physiological account of these states. - But our present physiology does not have the
resources to do this (homogeneity again). - And Sellars doesnt believe that the physics of
non-living things has the resources either
something unique to organisms (ones sufficiently
like us) needs to turn upwe need a micro theory
of sentient organisms, he says, to find the
micro-states corresponding to these posited molar
states.
80The tradition and the sequel
- The modern view that objects arent really
coloured, and colour is in the mind of the
perceiver, is a confusion of this scientific
anticipation with a feature of the manifest
image. - The upshot of Jones work is that we have a
notion of both thoughts and impressions that
allows introspection (individuals are the
reporters for their own states) but also makes
the link with observable behaviour (and thus
training by our linguistic seniors as we grow up)
part of the meaning of this language.
81The order of things
- The language of impressions is no more the result
of antecedent noticings of impressions than the
language of molecules is the result of antecedent
noticings of molecules. - The phenomenologist, in describing these states,
fails to recognize her own creative role - She takes herself to be analyzing human knowledge
as it already was, when she is actually
contributing to an entirely new body of knowledge
whose projected links to a scientific
micro-theory of sentient organisms point towards
a unified science including impressions.