PHL105Y Introduction to Philosophy Monday, September 18, 2006 - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 32
About This Presentation
Title:

PHL105Y Introduction to Philosophy Monday, September 18, 2006

Description:

If Senator Carbuncle does not support the Budget Amendment, he will lose the ... Senator Carbuncle supports the Budget Amendment. Senator Carbuncle will not ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:36
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 33
Provided by: jennife63
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: PHL105Y Introduction to Philosophy Monday, September 18, 2006


1
PHL105Y Introduction to Philosophy Monday,
September 18, 2006
  • Announcements
  • If you are new in the class today, welcome.
    Please take a syllabus from the desk at the
    front.
  • For Wednesdays class, read chapters 4 and 5 of
    Vaughns Writing Philosophy
  • Philosophy Party Wednesday, September 20, North
    Building Lounge (NB 262) 300-430 pm. All
    philosophy students welcome.
  • Tutorials begin Friday. Your first tutorial
    assignment is due, in hard copy, at the beginning
    of your tutorial.

2
Your first tutorial assignment
  • You are asked to paraphrase a difficult textual
    passage. You may not understand the passage well
    the first time you read it. Do your best with
    it its OK this time if you dont succeed in
    writing a paraphrase that fully conveys the
    meaning of the original passage. In Fridays
    tutorial youll have a chance to go over anything
    you didnt understand.
  • You are also asked to define some key terms
    (validity, etc.) be sure to explain these ideas
    in your own words.

3
Handing in tutorial work
  • Tutorial assignments are not submitted to
    www.turnitin.com (but of course original work is
    still required).
  • Tutorial leaders will collect your written work
    every week.
  • Four times a year, on weeks chosen (randomly) in
    advance, your tutorial work will be given a grade
    out of 10. The 10 of the final grade devoted to
    tutorial written work comes out of these
    assessments.
  • Late tutorial work is not accepted without a
    documented excuse (e.g. MDs note).
  • In an emergency, tutorial written work can be
    handed in by email before your scheduled
    tutorial.

4
Your tutorial leaders
  • David Dedourek TUT201, TUT204, TUT207
  • Catherine Manoukian TUT206, TUT205
  • Suzan Poyraz TUT202, TUT203
  • Contact information on your TAs is available by
    clicking the office hours link on the main
    CCNet menu for the course. http//ccnet.utoronto.c
    a/20069/phl105y5y0201/
  •  
  • TUT201 FR1100-1200NE 297    
  • TUT202 FR1200-1300NE 259     
  • TUT203 FR1000-1100NE 257     
  • TUT204 FR1400-1500NE 269     
  • TUT205 FR1500-1600NE 295     
  • TUT206 FR1200-1300NE 295     
  • TUT207 FR1300-1400NE 297

5
The Structure of Arguments
6
The building blocks of arguments
  • Arguments are composed of statements or
    propositions
  • A statement something that could stand as an
    independent declarative sentence it is the sort
    of thing that can be true or false (unlike a
    question, command or exclamation).

7
The building blocks of arguments
  • There are two kinds of statements in any
    argument
  • 1. Premises statements intended to function as
    reasons in support of a conclusion (ideally, your
    premises should be statements the reader is
    likely to accept already)
  • 2. Conclusions statements intended to follow
    from your premises the aim of any argument is to
    drive the reader to accept the conclusion

8
The building blocks of arguments
  • 1. Premises can be marked with words like
    because, assuming that, since
  • 2. Conclusions can be marked with words like
    therefore, so it follows that, as a result
  • Caution often those marker words are absent you
    have to read the whole passage to get the gist of
    the argument and figure out which statements are
    premises and which are conclusions.

9
Valid Deductive Arguments
  • In a VALID deductive argument, IF the premises
    are true, the conclusion MUST also be true. A
    valid deductive argument CANNOT simultaneously
    have true premises and a false conclusion.
  • In calling an argument valid we are saying that
    IF you accept the premises, you must accept the
    conclusion (a valid argument can have a false
    conclusion, as long as it has at least one false
    premise).
  • If there is any logically possible way that the
    premises could be true, and the conclusion false,
    then the argument is deductively INVALID.

10
SOUNDNESS
  • A SOUND argument is a deductively VALID argument
    with all TRUE premises.
  • Soundness is a higher standard than deductive
    validity all sound arguments are deductively
    valid, but not all deductively valid arguments
    are sound
  • (Which deductively valid arguments are unsound?)

11
Valid Deductive ArgumentsSome basic forms (there
are many others)
  • Modus ponens
  • If p then q
  • p
  • Therefore, q
  • p and q each represent a statement.
  • Modus tollens
  • If p then q
  • Not q
  • Therefore, not p

12
Antecedents and consequents
  • The antecedent is the hypothetical condition of a
    conditional (the statement usually preceded by
    if), the consequent is what will follow (the
    statement preceded by then but sometimes the
    then is just understood and is not explicit)
  • Watch out that in English conditionals can be
    written not only in the form If A then B, but
    also in the form B, if A. Here A is still the
    antecedent, even though it appears after the
    consequent. Example Jane will be angry, if she
    hears the news. This statement is equivalent to
    If Jane hears the news, then she will be angry.
  • Antecedent Jane hears the news.
  • Consequent Jane will be angry.

13
Valid deductive arguments
  • If Roberta is late, she will not meet Henry.
  • Roberta is late.
  • She will not meet Henry.

14
Valid deductive arguments
  • If Roberta is late, she will not meet Henry.
  • Roberta is late.
  • She will not meet Henry.
  • If p then q
  • p
  • Therefore, q
  • Note that p and q might be statements
    containing one or more negations e.g. it is
    not raining She is not unlikely to fail.

15
Denying a statementwhen double negations cancel
out
  • Where the original statement is negative (e.g. p
    Sarah will not testify against her brother) a
    denial of the statement gives you a double
    negation (so not-p It is not the case that
    Sarah will not testify against her brother.)
    Wed usually simplify that to Sarah will testify
    against her brother.
  • How do double-negations work in the context of
    the argument forms we have learned?

16
Two fallacies to avoid affirming the consequent,
denying the antecedent
  • Affirming the consequent
  • If p then q
  • q
  • Therefore, p
  • Example If Paris steals, then she is breaking
    the law. Paris is breaking the law. Therefore
    she is stealing.
  • Denying the antecedent
  • If p then q
  • Not p
  • Therefore, not q
  • Example if Jane is taking chemistry, then she is
    a student. Jane is not taking chemistry.
    Therefore, Jane is not a student.

17
Test yourself
  • The following arguments are either valid (modus
    ponens, modus tollens) or invalid (affirming the
    consequent, denying the antecedent). Which is
    which?
  • If Morris tells the police what he knows, Jake
    will be arrested. Morris will not tell the
    police what he knows. Jake will not be arrested.
  • If she fired the gun, Lucy will have gunpowder
    residue on her hands. Lucy does not have
    gunpowder residue on her hands. Lucy did not
    fire the gun.
  • If Senator Carbuncle does not support the Budget
    Amendment, he will lose the support of his party.
    Senator Carbuncle supports the Budget Amendment.
    Senator Carbuncle will not lose the support of
    his party.
  • If heterokonts are ancestrally photosynthetic,
    they are chromalveolates. Heterokonts are not
    chromalveolates. Therefore, they are not
    ancestrally photosynthetic.

18
Test yourself
  • The following arguments are either valid (modus
    ponens, modus tollens) or invalid (affirming the
    consequent, denying the antecedent). Which is
    which?
  • If Morris tells the police what he knows, Jake
    will be arrested. Morris will not tell the
    police what he knows. Jake will not be arrested.
    (invalid, DA)
  • If she fired the gun, Lucy will have gunpowder
    residue on her hands. Lucy does not have
    gunpowder residue on her hands. Lucy did not
    fire the gun. (valid, MT)
  • If Senator Carbuncle does not support the Budget
    Amendment, he will lose the support of his party.
    Senator Carbuncle supports the Budget Amendment.
    Senator Carbuncle will not lose the support of
    his party. (invalid, DA)
  • If heterokonts are ancestrally photosynthetic,
    they are chromalveolates. Heterokonts are not
    chromalveolates. Therefore, they are not
    ancestrally photosynthetic. (valid, MT)

19
Inductive arguments
  • In an inductive argument, the premises make the
    conclusion probable if the premises are true,
    the conclusion is likely to be true as well
    (although it is logically possible that the
    conclusion might be false).

20
Types of inductive argument
  • Enumerative induction
  • Example 99 of Canadians watch television at
    least once a week. John is Canadian. John
    probably watches television at least once a week.
  • Q What makes an argument of this type a strong
    argument?

21
Types of inductive argument
  • Argument by analogy
  • Example The wise person does not deprecate life
    nor does he fear the cessation of life. The
    thought of life is no offense to him, nor is the
    cessation of life regarded as an evil. And even
    as people choose of food not merely and simply
    the larger portion, but the more pleasant, so the
    wise seek to enjoy the time which is most
    pleasant and not merely that which is longest.
  • --Epicurus, letter to Menoeceus
  • Q What makes an argument of this type a strong
    argument?

22
Types of inductive argument
  • Inference to the best explanation
  • Example Detectives found blood matching the
    victims on your coat. A shoe print matching
    your known shoe size was found at the scene of
    the crime. Your fingerprints were found on the
    knife. You had a strong motive to kill the
    victim. You are probably the person we are
    looking for in this case.
  • Q What makes an argument of this type a strong
    argument?

23
Evaluating inductive arguments
  • Inductive arguments are evaluated as strong or
    weak.
  • A strong inductive argument with true premises is
    said to be COGENT.

24
Summary
  • Statements are true or false.
  • Deductive arguments are valid or invalid.
  • Some valid arguments are sound some valid
    arguments are unsound.
  • Inductive arguments are weak or strong.
  • Some strong inductive arguments are cogent some
    fail to be cogent.

25
Style and content in philosophical writing
26
Common sense
  • Why avoid highly complex and pretentious ways of
    saying things?

27
How should we speak of Plato?
  • When paraphrasing a famous author, what is the
    appropriate attitude to take towards that author?

28
Fallacies to avoid
  • What is the straw man fallacy?
  • What is the ad hominem fallacy?

29
Fallacies to avoid
  • The straw man fallacy is committed when you
    attack a reduced version of your adversarys
    position instead of the real thing.
  • The ad hominem fallacy is committed when you
    attack the personal characteristics of your
    opponent rather than her position itself.

30
Clarity and coolness
  • To keep your writing clear, it helps to read it
    out loud, and then fix anything that sounds
    awkward.
  • Loaded emotional language is generally avoided in
    philosophy papers. (Why?)
  • The Academic Skills Centre can help you learn to
    write (more) clearly drop in and see them (Room
    2115B, South Building)

31
Assumptions
  • Philosophy often involves raising questions about
    things commonly taken for granted. Be careful
    about letting your argument rest on popular
    sentiments that might not be shared by the
    philosopher you are discussing.

32
The first person
  • Yes, you can use the first person pronoun in your
    philosophy papers in fact, its often very
    useful to mark the boundaries between your
    thought and the ideas of the philosopher you are
    criticizing. (According to Descartes, the idea
    of God is innate in us. In this paper I will
    argue that)
  • Claims you make in the first person still need to
    be backed up by rational argument.
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com