Incompleteness - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

About This Presentation
Title:

Incompleteness

Description:

Incompleteness Constructing H(T,x) Lucas view Lucas view (cont d) Lucas view Encyclopedia article Penrose s view Human mathematical intuition Other ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:32
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 65
Provided by: Davi312
Learn more at: http://www.cs.unc.edu
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: Incompleteness


1
Incompleteness
2
  • Suppose L is a logic and H(T,x) is a statement in
    L expressing that Turing machine T halts on input
    x.
  • Thus H(T,x) is true if and only if T halts on
    input x.
  • Recall -- L is sound and effective. So
  • If H(T,x) is provable in L then it is true so T
    halts on input x.
  • If ?H(T,x) is provable in L then H(T,x) is false
    so T does not halt on input x.

3
  • There is a Turing machine M such that M halts on
    input i if and only if ?H(Ti,i) is provable in L.
  • M can be constructed from a theorem prover for L
  • Let j be such that M is Tj.
  • Claim Tj loops on input j but ?H(Tj,j) is not
    provable in L. (Incompleteness.)

4
  • Proof If Tj halts on input j then by definition
    of M, ?H(Tj,j) is provable in L. Thus Tj loops
    on input j. Contradiction.
  • Thus Tj loops on input j. By definition of M
    this implies that ?H(Tj,j) is not provable in L.
  • Thus ?H(Tj,j) is true but not provable in L.

5
  • The formula ?H(Tj,j) asserts its own
    unprovability
  • If ?H(Tj,j) is true then Tj does not halt on
    input j.
  • This means that ?H(Tj,j) is not provable in L.
  • So if ?H(Tj,j) is true, it is unprovable.
  • If ?H(Tj,j) is provable, L is unsound.

6
  • Let S be the sentence This sentence is false.
  • This is self-referential like ?H(Tj,j)
  • If S is true it is false.
  • If S is false it is true.
  • Either way, HL is contradictory unless this is
    not considered a valid sentence of HL.
  • But which sentences then does HL allow?

7
  • Similar to Russells paradox
  • Let X be S S ? S
  • Then is X ? X?
  • If so X ? X.
  • If not X ? X.
  • Either way set theory is contradictory.
  • So set theory was modified to disallow this set.

8
Constructing H(T,x)
  • Legend
  • tape(i,t) Tape symbol i at time t.
  • state(t) State at time t
  • scan(t) Symbol scanned at time t
  • Transition function of T for (state,symbol)
  • ns(state,symbol) New state
  • wr(state,symbol) Symbol written
  • dir(state,symbol) Direction moved, 0,-1,or 1

9
  • Let A be the conjunction of these formulae
  • (0 lt i lt x) ? tape(i,0) xi.
  • (0 ? i ? i ? x) ? tape(i,0) blank
  • state(0)s (the start state of T)
  • scan(0)0
  • ?t?i (scan(t) ? i ? tape(i,t)tape(i,t1))
  • ?t (state(t1)ns(state(t),tape(scan(t),t)))
  • ?t (scan(t1)scan(t) dir(state(t),tape(scan(t),t
    )))
  • ?t (tape(scan(t),t1) wr(state(t),tape(scan(t),t)
    ))

10
  • Assume ns, wr, and dir are defined in A too.
  • Let Hn(T,x) be A ? (state(n) ?F)
  • F is the set of halting states of T
  • N is the natural numbers 0,1,2,3,
  • Means that T halts in n steps on input x
  • Let H(T,x) be ?n ?N Hn(T,x)
  • Means that T halts on input x
  • H(T,x) is true if T halts on input x
  • H(T,x) is false if T loops on input x

11
  • Note that H(T,x) can be constructed from T
  • Thus if j is known, ?H(Tj,j) can be constructed.
    This formula is true but not provable in L.
  • j can be obtained from a Turing machine M that on
    input i tests if ?H(Ti,i) is provable in L.
  • ?H(Ti,i) can be constructed as above
  • From L a theorem prover for L can be constructed
    and M can be found
  • Thus one can easily construct ?H(Tj,j)

12
  • But ?H(Tj,j) is true but not provable in L
  • Constructing H(T,x) for a particular T and x
  • Consider this TM
  • pass, 1, pass, 1, R
  • pass, 0, pass, 1, R
  • pass, B, del1, B, L
  • del1, 1, del2, B, L
  • del2, 1, stop, B, R
  • Tape B111011B Start state pass

13
  • Let A be the conjunction of these formulae
  • tape(0,0)B tape(1,0)1 tape(2,0)1 tape(3,0)1
    tape(4,0)0 tape(5,0)1 tape(6,0)1 (because x
    B111011)
  • (0 ? i ? i ? 7) ? tape(i,0) B
  • state(0)pass
  • scan(0)0
  • ?t?i (scan(t) ? i ? tape(i,t)tape(i,t1))
  • ?t (state(t1)ns(state(t),tape(scan(t),t)))
  • ?t (scan(t1)scan(t) dir(state(t),tape(scan(t),t
    )))

14
  • ?t (tape(scan(t),t1) wr(state(t),tape(scan(t),t)
    ))
  • ns(pass,1)pass wr(pass,1)1 dir(pass,1)1
  • ns(pass,0)pass wr(pass,0)1 dir(pass,0)1
  • ns(pass,B)del1 wr(pass,B)B dir(pass,B)-1
  • ns(del1, 1)del2 wr(del1, 1)B dir(del1, 1)-1
  • ns(del2, 1)stop wr(del2, 1)B dir(del2, 1)1
  • Let Hn(T,x) be A ? (state(n) stop)
  • For this T and x, H(T,x) is true and T halts on
    input x.

15
  • In general ?H(Tj,j) is true but not provable in L
  • Paradox How do we know that this formula is
    true when L does not know it?
  • What logical system are we in when we think this
    way?
  • We seem to have the ability to get outside of any
    logical system. Thus we must not reason using a
    fixed logical system.
  • Lucas argued on this basis that human thought
    processes cannot be simulated by Turing machines.

16
  • Let HL be human logic
  • If we know HL then we can construct a formula X
    that is true but not provable in HL
  • But we just proved X in HL, contradiction.
  • Possible solutions
  • We can never know HL
  • HL is not sound.
  • HL is not effective. (We excel TM in thought.)
  • We can never know that HL is sound.

17
  • All of these seem strange
  • Dont we even know how we think?
  • Cant we think logically?
  • Can we really exceed Turing machines in reasoning
    power?
  • Is our thought process really so subtle that we
    cannot know it is sound?

18
  • In fact HL does not need to contain all of human
    logic.
  • HL just needs enough logic to be able to show
    that ?H(Tj,j) is true but not provable in L.
  • This restricted HL is known to us and very
    likely free from error.
  • Either this restricted HL goes beyond TM or
    cannot be shown (in HL) to be sound for the
    formula ?H(Tj,j).
  • Pick Peano arithmetic as restricted HL.

19
  • What does restricted HL need to derive to
    obtain the contradiction?
  • It needs to show that Tj halts on input j if and
    only if Tj constructs a proof that Tj does not
    halt on input j.
  • It needs to show that if there is a proof that Tj
    does not halt on input j then in fact Tj does not
    halt on input j.
  • The first part is straightforward.
  • The second part is the problem.

20
  • Thus no sufficiently powerful logic L can derive
    the statement (X is provable in L) implies X.
  • In fact this only has to be derivable for X of
    the form ?H(T,x)
  • Any sufficiently powerful finite logic that can
    do this, is inconsistent (contradictory).
  • But humans use the fact If X is provable in L
    then X all the time.
  • Does this mean our thought processes cannot be
    captured by any logical system?

21
  • If L is a logic such that L can derive the
    statement (X is provable in L) implies X then
    either L is inconsistent (can derive a
    contradiction) or L cannot be represented by a
    Turing machine (L is not effective).
  • We can try to strengthen L.
  • Let L be L with the statement ?T?x(?H(T,x) is
    provable in L) implies ?H(T,x) added.
  • In L one cannot derive the statement
    ?T?x(?H(T,x) is provable in L) implies
    ?H(T,x) !

22
  • We can also add the statement ?H(Tj,j) to L.
  • But then for the new L, j will be different and
    ?H(Tj,j) will not be derivable for the new j!
  • For a logic L let G(L) be a statement which
    permits ?H(Tj,j) to be derived. G(L) may be the
    statement ?H(Tj,j) itself or G(L) may be the
    statement ?T?x(?H(T,x) is provable in L)
    implies ?H(T,x).

23
  • Then in L ? G(L) one can derive ?H(Tj,j). But
    one cannot derive G(L ? G(L))!
  • Define Li by L0 L and Li1 Li ? G(Li).
  • Let be the limit (union) of all these logics.
  • In L? one still cannot derive G(L? )!
  • Then one can construct L? ? G(L? ) et cetera.
    Related to ordinals.
  • The process never stops.
  • A staircase to infinity.
  • An attempt to reach the inexpressible.

24
  • We can advance farther and farther but there is
    always an infinite distance between us and
    ultimate understanding.
  • Can a Turing machine construct the same sequence
    of logics starting with some sound logic such as
    Peano arithmetic?
  • What would it mean if it could?
  • There is a shortcut to obtain a logic to solve
    the halting problem, but it has a drawback

25
  • Let L be L with all true statements of the form
    ?H(T,x) added.
  • Then L can solve the halting problem.
  • If L is Peano arithmetic (assuming it is
    consistent) L is consistent too.
  • But L is not effective. L does not have a
    theorem prover.
  • No finite logic can solve the halting problem.
  • The question remains Do humans excel Turing
    machines?

26
  • The process of strengthening Peano arithmetic
    using Godels theorem can be made more formal

27
  • Let PA be Peano arithmetic.
  • Let HL be the logic permitting us to apply
    Godels theorem repeatedly to PA and obtain PA,
    PA ? G(PA) and other stronger logics from PA.
  • Write HL ? L to mean that logic L can be
    obtained from PA by such strengthening.
  • Thus HL ? PA.
  • Also if HL ? L then HL ? L ? G(L)
  • Also if HL ? Li for all i and the sequence Li is
    effectively computable then HL ? ?iLi

28
  • Make HL into a logic -- say one can prove
    formula ?H(T,x) if for some logic L, HL ? L and
    ?H(T,x) can be proved in L.
  • Suppose HL ? HL. Then HL ? HL ? G(HL).
    Thus G(HL) is provable in HL. But this is a
    contradiction.
  • Suppose it is not true that HL ? HL. This
    seems strange -- if HL has a finite
    axiomatization then we should be able to write it
    down and reason about it.

29
  • Because PA is (very likely) sound, HL is also
    very likely sound.
  • If HL ? HL then HL does not have a finite
    axiom system and we excel Turing machines.
  • This is a more concrete version of Lucas paradox.

30
  • The essence of consciousness -- awareness of
    ourselves. The ability to view our own thought
    processes as objects from the outside. To
    infer HL ? HL.
  • The ability to formalize any logical system we
    use.
  • Can a computer with sensory input be self-aware
    in this sense?
  • Could it be that a computer with sensory input
    and the ability to see and think about itself,
    excels Turing machines?

31
  • Note that such sensing devices would be able not
    only to observe the machine M but also the
    sensing devices themselves.

32
Lucas view
  • Goedel's theorem must apply to cybernetical
    machines, because it is of the essence of being a
    machine, that it should be a concrete
    instantiation of a formal system. It follows that
    given any machine which is consistent and capable
    of doing simple arithmetic, there is a formula
    which it is incapable of producing as being
    true---i.e., the formula is unprovable-in-the-syst
    em-but which we can see to be true. It follows
    that no machine can be a complete or adequate
    model of the mind, that minds are essentially
    different from machines.

33
Lucasview (contd)
  • Goedel's theorem seems to me to prove that
    Mechanism is false, that is, that minds cannot be
    explained as machines. So also has it seemed to
    many other people almost every mathematical
    logician I have put the matter to has confessed
    to similar thoughts, but has felt reluctant to
    commit himself definitely until he could see the
    whole argument set out, with all objections fully
    stated and properly met.1 This I attempt to do.

34
  • For every machine there is a truth which it
    cannot produce as being true, but which a mind
    can. This shows that a machine cannot be a
    complete and adequate model of the mind. It
    cannot do everything that a mind can do, since
    however much it can do, there is always something
    which it cannot do, and a mind can.

35
  • The paradoxes of consciousness arise because a
    conscious being can be aware of itself, as well
    as of other things, and yet cannot really be
    construed as being divisible into parts. It means
    that a conscious being can deal with Goedelian
    questions in a way in which a machine cannot,
    because a conscious being can both consider
    itself and its performance and yet not be other
    than that which did the performance.

36
  • A machine can be made in a manner of speaking to
    "consider" its own performance, but it cannot
    take this "into account" without thereby becoming
    a different machine, namely the old machine with
    a "new part" added. But it is inherent in our
    idea of a conscious mind that it can reflect upon
    itself and criticize its own performances, and no
    extra part is required to do this it is already
    complete, and has no Achilles' heel.

37
  • We can even begin to see how there could be room
    for morality, without its being necessary to
    abolish or even to circumscribe the province of
    science. Our argument has set no limits to
    scientific enquiry it will still be possible to
    investigate the working of the brain. It will
    still be possible to produce mechanical models of
    the mind.

38
  • Only, now we can see that no mechanical model
    will be completely adequate, nor any explanations
    in purely mechanist terms. We can produce models
    and explanations, and they will be illuminating
    but, however far they go, there will always
    remain more to be said. There is no arbitrary
    bound to scientific enquiry but no scientific
    enquiry can ever exhaust the infinite variety of
    the human mind.12

39
Lucas view
  • The arguments I put forward in "Minds, Machines
    and Goedel" and then in Freedom of the Will have
    been much attacked. Although I put them forward
    with what I hope was becoming modesty and a
    certain degree of tentativeness, many of the
    replies have been lacking in either courtesy or
    caution. I must have touched a raw nerve.

40
  • In recent years I have been less zealous to
    defend myself, and often miss articles
    altogether. There may be some new decisive
    objection I have altogether overlooked. But the
    objections I have come across so far seem far
    from decisive.

41
Encyclopedia article
  • Roger Penrose claims that this (alleged)
    difference between "what can be mechanically
    proven" and "what can be seen to be true by
    humans" shows that human intelligence is not
    mechanical in nature. This view is not widely
    accepted, because as stated by Marvin Minsky,
    human intelligence is capable of error and of
    understanding statements which are in fact
    inconsistent or false.

42
  • However, Marvin Minsky has reported that Kurt
    Gödel told him personally that he believed that
    human beings had an intuitive, not just
    computational, way of arriving at truth and that
    therefore his theorem did not limit what can be
    known to be true by humans.

43
Penroses view
  • The famous "incompleteness" theorem of Gödel
    (illustrated by a particularly striking but
    elementary example of it known as Goodstein's
    theorem) tells us that human mathematical
    understanding cannot be encapsulated in any
    (knowably sound) computational procedure. This
    has the implication that there is something
    involved in human understanding that lies beyond
    the actions of any computer. Understanding is a
    particular manifestation of human consciousness,
    so it appears that it is conscious mentality that
    lies outside computational activity.

44
  • Why do I believe that consciousness involves
    noncomputable ingredients? The reason is Gödel's
    theorem. I sat in on a course when I was a
    research student at Cambridge, given by a
    logician who made the point about Gödel's theorem
    that the very way in which you show the formal
    unprovability of a certain proposition also
    exhibits the fact that it's true. I'd vaguely
    heard about Gödel's theorem that you can
    produce statements that you can't prove using any
    system of rules you've laid down ahead of time.

45
  • But what was now being made clear to me was that
    as long as you believe in the rules you're using
    in the first place, then you must also believe in
    the truth of this proposition whose truth lies
    beyond those rules. This makes it clear that
    mathematical understanding is something you can't
    formulate in terms of rules. That's the view
    which, much later, I strongly put forward in my
    book The Emperor's New Mind.

46
Criticism of Penrose
In The Emperor's New Mind Penrose, 1989 and
especially in Shadows of the Mind Penrose,
1994, Roger Penrose argues against the strong
artificial intelligence thesis," contending that
human reasoning cannot be captured by an
artificial intellect because humans detect
nontermination of programs in cases where digital
machines do not. Penrose thus adapts the similar
argumentation of Lucas 1961 which was based on
Goedel's incompleteness results to one based
instead on the undecidability of the halting
problem, as shown by Turing 1936. Penrose's
conclusions have been roundly critiqued, for
example, in Avron, 1998 Chalmers, 1995a
LaForte et al., 1998 Putnam, 1995.
47
In a nutshell, Penrose's argument runs as
follows 1. Collect all current sound human
knowledge about non-termination. 2. Reduce said
knowledge to a computer program. 3. Create a
self-referential version of said program. 4.
Derive a contradiction. The conclusion (by
reductio ad absurdum) is that the second step is
invalid A program cannot incorporate everything
humans know! (The reasoning is that humans can
know that a self-referential version of this
program does not halt, but the computer program
cannot know this.)
48
Human mathematical intuition
Ramanujan had several extraordinary
characteristics which set him apart from the
majority of mathematicians. One was his lack of
rigor. Very often he would simply state a result
which, he would insist, had just come to him from
a vague, intuitive source, far out of the realm
of conscious probing. In fact, he often said
that the goddess Namagiri inspired him in his
dreams. This happened time and again, and what
made it all the more mystifying -- perhaps even
imbuing it with a certain mystical quality -- was
the fact that many of his intuition theorems
were wrong.
49
Mahalanobis Now here is a problem for
you. Ramanujan What problem, tell me? I read out
the question from the Strand Magazine. Ramanujan
Please take down the solution. (He dictated a
continued fraction.) The first term was the
solution I had obtained. Each successive term
represented successive solutions for the same
type of problem as the number of houses in the
street would increase indefinitely. I was
amazed. Mahalanobis Did you get the solution in
a flash? Ramanujan Immediately I heard the
problem, it was clear that that solution was
obviously a continued fraction. I then thought,
Which continued fraction? and the answer came
to my mind. It was as simple as this.
50
Johann Martin Zacharias Dase, who lived from 1824
to 1861 and was employed by various European
governments to perform computations, is an
outstanding example. He not only could multiply
two number each of 100 digits in his head he
also had an uncanny sense of quantity. That is,
he could just tell, without counting, how many
sheep were in a field, or words in a sentence,
and so forth, up to about 30 . Incidentally,
Dase was not an idiot.
51
  • The statement ?H(Tj,j) is true but not provable
    in L.
  • This means that neither H(Tj,j) nor ?H(Tj,j) can
    be proven in L.
  • If A is a statement and neither A nor ?A can be
    proven in L, then A is said to be undecidable in
    L.
  • Goedels theorem gives an undecidable statement
    but other such statements are known.

52
Other undecidable statements
  • The combined work of Gödel and Paul Cohen has
    given concrete examples of undecidable statements
    (statements which can be neither proven nor
    disproven) both the axiom of choice and the
    continuum hypothesis are undecidable in the
    standard axiomatization of set theory. These
    results do not require the incompleteness
    theorem.

53
  • In 1973, the Whitehead problem in group theory
    was shown to be undecidable in standard set
    theory. In 1977, Kirby, Paris and Harrington
    proved that a statement in combinatorics, a
    version of the Ramsey theorem, is undecidable in
    the axiomatization of arithmetic given by the
    Peano axioms but can be proven to be true in the
    larger system of set theory. Kruskal's tree
    theorem, which has applications in computer
    science, is also undecidable from the Peano
    axioms but provable in set theory. Goodstein's
    theorem is a relatively simple statement about
    natural numbers that is undecidable in Peano
    arithmetic.

54
  • Gregory Chaitin produced undecidable statements
    in algorithmic information theory and in fact
    proved his own incompleteness theorem in that
    setting.
  • The complexity (or Kolmogorov complexity) of a
    string is the length of the shortest program
    which, when run without any input, outputs that
    string.
  • Chaitin's incompleteness result though we know
    that most strings are complex in the above sense,
    the fact that a specific string is complex can
    never be proven (if the string's length is above
    a certain threshold). The precise formalization
    is as follows.

55
  • Suppose we fix a particular consistent axiomatic
    system for the natural numbers, say Peano's
    axioms. Then there exists a constant L (which
    only depends on the particular axiomatic system
    and the choice of definition of complexity) such
    that there is no string s for which the statement
  • I(s) ? L
  • can be proven within the axiomatic system (even
    though, as we know, the vast majority of those
    statements must be true).
  • Thus there are very many true, unprovable
    statements in any sufficiently strong axiom
    system.

56
Nonstandard Models
  • ?H(Tj,j) is ?n ?N ?Hn(Tj,j)
  • This formula is true but not provable in L
  • It must be false in a nonstandard model
  • Thus there must be a nonstandard integer n such
    that Hn(Tj,j) is true.
  • This must be so in any sound, effective logic
    that can express the integers and Turing
    computations.

57
  • There is no formula A such that A(x) is true if
    and only if x is a standard integer.
  • If there were then the formula ?n ?N (A(n) ?
    ?Hn(T,x)) would hold in all models if and only if
    T did not halt on input x
  • Thus this formula would be provable if and only
    if T does not halt on input x
  • This would provide a solution to the halting
    problem.

58
  • We cant formally describe the integers.
  • Any attempt to do so will also have nonstandard
    models that describe infinite integers
  • Then how do we know what the standard integers
    are?
  • Is this evidence of intuition that goes beyond
    Turing machines?
  • No formal system can even formally describe what
    it means for something to be finite.

59
  • ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ?
    ? ? ? ?????????????????
    ?????? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ?
    ? ? ? ? ? ???????????????????? ?? ?
    ? ?
  • 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9
    10 ?
    nonstandard integers
  • standard integers

60
  • In fact in any formal system there are models of
    the real numbers that have the same size as the
    integers
  • But we know there are more reals than integers (a
    bigger infinity)
  • So no formal system can fully capture the idea of
    an infinity larger than the integers
  • Then what makes us think we know what such
    infinities are if we cant fully describe them?
    Do we excel Turing machines again?

61
  • Gödel's theorem thus shows that there must always
    exist such unusual, unintended interpretations of
    the system as Henkin says, quoted in Turquette
    50
  • We tend to reinterpret Gödel's incompleteness
    result as asserting not primarily a limitation on
    our ability to prove but rather on our ability to
    specify what we mean ... when we use a symbolic
    system in accordance with recursive rules Gödel
    the synthetic a priori.
  • Damjan Bojadziev, Mind versus Gödel, in M. Gams,
    M. Paprzycki and X. Wu (eds.), Mind Versus
    Computer, IOS Press 1997, pp. 202-210.

62
  • Similarly, Polanyi says, though only in
    connection with the second theorem
  • we never know altogether what our axioms mean
    Personal Knowledge, p. 259. We must commit
    ourselves to the risk of talking complete
    nonsense if we are to say anything at all within
    any such system p. 94.
  • (from Mind versus Gödel)
  • Bojadziev concludes that our self awareness is
    limited (we can never know HL)

63
  • Applied to minds, it would translate to some
    principled limitation of the reflexive cognitive
    abilities of the subject certain truths about
    oneself must remain unrecognized if the
    self-image is to remain consistent Hofstadter
    79, p. 696.
  • Conclusion It is not possible to see oneself
    completely, in the literal, metaphorical
    ("seeunderstand"), formal and computational
    sense of the word. Gödel's theorems do not
    prevent the construction of formal models of the
    mind, but support the conception of mind (self,
    consciousness) as something which has a special
    relation to itself, marked by specific
    limitations.

64
  • How many true but unprovable statements are
    there?
  • Are they rare or common?
  • Chaitin showed that they are very common in any
    formal system.
  • Why then does this not cause more of a problem
    for mathematics research?
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com