Title: History of Philosophy Lecture 18 John Stuart Mill: Utilitarianism
1History of PhilosophyLecture 18John Stuart
Mill Utilitarianism
2Mill
- John Stuart Mill (1806-1873)
- He was the greatest 19th century defender of
Utilitarianism. - He was a child prodigy.
- Defended womens suffrage.
- His text Utilitarianism was published in 1861.
3Utilitarianism
- The greatest happiness principle
- Actions are right in proportion as they tend to
promote happiness, - wrong as they tend to produce the reverse of
happiness. - Or
- Always do whatever will produce the greatest
happiness for the greatest number.
4Utilitarianismits two parts
- Any version of Utilitarianism (including Mills
version) is composed of two other views - Consequentialism
- We determine whether an act is right or wrong by
looking at its consequences. - Hedonism
- This tells us what makes for a better or worse
consequence. - Good what promotes pleasure
- Bad what promotes pain.
5Consequentialism
- Consequentialism To determine whether or not an
action is right - weigh the good consequences of doing the action
against the bad consequences of doing it. - And weigh the good consequences of not doing the
action against the bad consequences of not doing
it. - Do whatever will have the best overall
consequences. - Sorting good from bad Thus, to determine whether
or not an action is right - One must be able to sort the good consequences
from the bad consequences. - The meaning of good and bad
- Defining the good then the Right Thus,
Consequentialist moral theories, like
Utilitarianism, - define the good, I.e. what they want to promote,
then define what is right by simply calculating
what will best promote that good.
6Consequentialism
- Other ways to define Consequentialism
- Between two actions, perform the one that has
better consequences. - One determines whether an act is right or wrong
by looking solely at its consequences. - The end justifies the means.
- The consequences of an action can justify the
action itself. - Thus, if harming someone will somehow cause more
good overall than bad, one ought to harm that
person.
7Hedonism
- Hedonism says that a good thing is one that adds
to the sum total of human happiness. - Happiness pleasure and the absence of pain.
- Unhappiness pain and the absence of pleasure.
- Hedonism Happiness
- What makes something, anything and not just life,
good is the amount of happiness it produces. - Happiness is the only non-derivative good
- It is the only thing that is good as an end in
itself. - Derivative goods money, knowledge, fulfilling
personal relationships, etc.
8Calculating Pleasures
- Jeremy Bentham, who with Mill created the
Utilitarian theory, took it upon himself to
provide a way to calculate pleasures and pains - A calculus of pleasures and pains
- He first lists the various pleasures and pains
- Those of sense, of wealth, of skill, of a good
name, of piety, power, happy memories, etc. - He then highlights the ways in which pleasures
and pains can differ - Intensity
- Duration
- Certainty or uncertainty
- Propinquity or remoteness
- Fecundity
- Purity
- Extent
- So Pleasures and Pains can be quantified.
- We have a mathematical formula for determining
what actions we ought to perform. This is a
science of pleasures and pains.
9Mills argument for Hedonism
- The non-derivative good is what people want
non-derivatively - Mill thinks that a non-derivatively good thing
must be what all people want non-derivatively
what people want for itself, as an end, not as a
means to something else. - So Mill thinks we should define good as
whatever people desire in itself. - But, Mill says, the production of pleasure and
the absence of pain is what everyone desires. - And not only this, pleasure is the only thing
people desire in itself. - His evidence for this look around!!!
- What people do desire is just the production of
pleasure and the absence of pain. - Mill says just look around think about yourself
10The form of Mills argument
- The form of Mills argument
- 1. A non-derivatively good thing is one that
people want for itself. - 2. Happiness is the only thing that people want
for itself. - 3. Thus, happiness is the only non-derivative
good. - Is this argument sound?
- Premise 1
- Premise 2?
- What about the move to the conclusion?
11Objection to Hedonismthe life of the beasts
- Some people object that hedonism is degrading.
- It makes the best life the life of the beasts.
- If a pig can live a life completely satisfied,
while a morally concerned and thoughtful man like
Socrates cannot ever be so satisfied, isnt the
life of the pig preferable? - Mills reply
- It is better to be Socrates dissatisfied than a
fool satisfied - Human beings have faculties more elevated than
the animal appetites, and when once made
conscious of them, do not regard anything as
happiness which does not include their
gratification.
12Mills reply
- The form of Mills reply
- 1-There are higher and lower pleasures.
- 2-Any amount of higher pleasure is preferable to
any amount of lower pleasure. - His evidence anyone who has experienced higher
pleasures would prefer them, on reflection, to
lower pleasures. - Higher pleasures
- any use of the mind including reflection or
thought, - Lower pleasures
- All pleasures not as a result of using the mind.
- 3-Since the life of the beast produces only lower
pleasures, the life of the beast isnt the best
life at all.
13The life of virtue
- Objection wouldnt you rather be virtuous than
happy. - Selling out
- Often we have the opportunity to sell out, to
get something that will make us happy at the cost
of doing bad. - Many people would rather not do that.
- Mills reply
- The life of virtue is an important part of being
happy. - You wouldnt really be happy if you sold out.
- Selling out is usually a matter of trading
virtue for something that is only derivatively
good, like money.
14Who counts?
- Objection it is difficult to determine just who
we include in our calculation of utility? - Do we include all persons whose interest may be
affected? - Only those in our own state? Our own community?
Our own family? - What about non-human sentient beings? Should
their pleasure or pain count? - Singer
- argues that since animals can feel pleasure and
pain just like humans, their interests must be
taken into account when calculating the overall
good an action produces. - So it is morally wrong to eat animals, to
experiment on them, or to imprison them in zoos. - Can you think of Mills reply to Singers
argument? - What about future generations?
- Should we consider the interests of future
persons? - Should we consider the environment?
15Quantifying happiness?
- To determine how much pleasure vs. pain an act
produces - one must consider whether an act will lead to
greater pleasure than pain - one must also consider the intensity of that
pleasure (and the intensity of that pain). - Is an action Morally right if it
- Brings a good number of people a small amount of
pain - But also brings a small number of people a great
amount of pleasure. - But it is extremely difficult to calculate the
intensity of pleasure and pain. - Could you assign numeric values to your pleasures
and pains? - And how do we assign numeric values to your
pleasures and pains in comparison to my pleasures
and pains or between higher and lower pleasures? - Mills reply
- Estimation is sufficient
16Calculation is based onmere prediction
- Isnt it just impossible to weigh out the
pleasure and pain that result from an action. - Consider
- How can we even predict all of the consequences
of our actions? - And how do we predict the pleasure and pain that
will result from the consequences of our actions? - A plausible response
- We are only trying to maximize probable utility.
17Demanding-ness
- Utilitarianism really asks us to leave our lives
to go cure world hunger - If everyones happiness is of equal value to our
own, then it will be hard to justify doing
anything other than working to alleviate world
hunger. - Justifying School or a steak dinner?
- The response
- We know what will produce our own happiness
better than what will produce happiness in other
people. - Counter-response
- Basic necessities
18Utilitarianism ignoresthe distinctness of
persons
- Utilitarianism could justify inflicting pain in
some if others are afforded pleasure - Slavery example
- a utilitarian would have to weigh the suffering
of those who would be slaves against the benefits
accruing to those who would be slave owners. - Making the trade off
- It may be possible for a single individual to
make this trade-off - One could weigh the pain of having a tooth pulled
against the benefit of getting rid of the
toothache, -
- But is it really possible to make this trade-off
between people? - Can you really justify inflicting pain on one
person by pointing to the increased pleasure this
will bring to others?
19What about promises?
- Utilitarianism does not give sufficient weight to
past acts - Utilitarianism is forward looking
- it gives no weight to past acts.
- Past events have relevance only to the extent
that they affect future consequences. - For the Utilitarian, the fact that I have
promised to do something is not in itself a
reason for doing it. - As a Utilitarian, I will keep my promise only if
keeping it will have the best consequences
20Promises once again
- The Utilitarian will often talk of justifying
keeping a promise because of the negative
consequences brought if it is broken - I make it less likely that people will rely on my
promises in the future - Undermining the institution of promise keeping
- But dont we keep our promises for reasons other
than that doing so produces pleasure? - Dont we have a hard time breaking promises just
because of what a promise is? - Isnt there something valuable about keeping a
promise in and of itself?
21What about Rights?
- For a Utilitarian there arent any absolute
prohibitions - For anything can be justified if it produces the
best consequences. - Thus, there are no absolute rights either.
- But arent there absolute rights?
- These are rights that cannot be violated under
any circumstances. - Consider the rights not to be tortured or
murdered or - The reply
- while murder or torture, etc. might maximize
happiness in extreme circumstances, - such circumstances are very unlikely
- it would almost always maximize happiness to
respect rights against such conduct. - The counter
- But this still allows for individual violations
of such rights
22The fatal flaw of Utilitarianism
- The problem with Utilitarianism
- a Utilitarian would tell you to kill an innocent
if it meant the production of more pleasure than
pain. - The real problem the Utilitarian puts the good
before the right - Utilitarians first decide what is good and then
decide what is right by looking at what will
produce the greatest amount of good. - As long as you do this, critics argue, no act is
always morally wrong - Put the right before the good
- Some critics argue this is the only way to solve
this problem
23Williams
- Bernard Williams (1929-2003) was a British
philosopher. - Taught at Cal Berkeley
- Was a great admirer of Mill, but not himself a
Utilitarian. - Like Mill he wanted to apply his philosophical
views to form public policy.
24Applying our moral theoriesMoral Dilemmas
- So far we have looked at a few Ethical Theories,
including both Utilitarianism and Deontology. - Ethical theories give general answers to the
question What ought I do? - But sometimes more specific answers are
interesting. - Moral dilemmas
- are specific cases in which it is hard to tell
what one ought to do. - We can use our reactions, our gut feeling or
intuitions, to moral dilemmas to find out which
of our ethical theories we think is the correct
one. - The Williams Dilemma
- Compare the answer of the Utilitarian to that of
the Deontologist
25George the Chemist
- George the Chemist
- George, who has taken his Ph.D in chemistry,
finds it extremely difficult to get a job. He is
not very robust in health, which cuts down the
number of jobs he might be able to do
satisfactorily. His wife has to go out to work
to keep them, which itself causes a great deal of
strain, since they have small children and there
are severe problems about looking after them.
The results of all this, especially on the
children, are damaging. An older chemist, who
knows about this situation, says that he can get
George a decently paid job in a certain
laboratory, which pursues research into chemical
and biological warfare. George says that he
cannot accept this, since he is opposed to
chemical and biological warfare. The older man
replies that he is not too keen on it himself,
come to that, but after all Georges refusal is
not going to make the job or the laboratory go
away what is more, he happens to know that if
George refuses the job, it will certainly go to a
contemporary of Georges who is not inhibited by
any such scruples and is likely if appointed to
push along the research with greater zeal than
George would. Indeed, it is not merely concern
for George and his family, but (to speak frankly
and in confidence) some alarm abut this other
mans excess of zeal, which had le the older man
to offer to use his influence to get George the
jobGeorges wife, to whom he is deeply attached,
has viewsfrom which it follows that at least
there is nothing particularly wrong with research
into CBW. What should he do? (From the first
page of Williams Utilitarianism and Integrity)
26Georges options
- George gets to choose between these actions
- A. working to make chemical weapons.
- B. Being unemployed.
- Their consequences
- A. George makes small amounts of chemical
weapons. - B. Someone else who doesnt see anything wrong
with making chemical weapons makes large amounts. - What should George do? What would you do?
27Some things to notice
- George is in a tough position.
- Thats why it is a moral dilemma.
- Changing the case to make things easier doesnt
help - Thats just changing the topic.
- Changing the case to make things harder is ok.
- because were interested in the hard cases.
- The hard cases are where ethical theories help us
out.
28Jim and Pedro
- Jim and Pedro
- Jim finds himself in the central square of a
small South American town. Tied up against the
wall are a row of twenty Indians, most terrified,
a few defiant, in front of them several armed men
in uniform. A heavy man in a sweat-stained khaki
shirt turns out to be the captain in charge and,
after a good deal of questioning of Jim which
establishes that he got there by accident while
on a botanical expedition, explains that the
Indians are a random group of the inhabitants
who, after recent acts of protest against the
government, are just about to be killed to remind
other possible protestors of the advantages of
not protesting. However, since Jim is an
honoured visitor from another land, the captain
is happy to offer him a guests privilege of
killing one of the Indians himself. If Jim
accepts, then as a special mark of the occasion,
the other Indians will be let off. Of course, if
Jim refuses, then there is no special occasion,
and Pedro here will do what he was about to do
when Jim arrived, and kill them all. Jim, with
some desperate recollection of schoolboy fiction,
wonders whether if he got hold of a gun, he could
hold the captain, Pedro and the rest of the
soldiers to threat, but it is quite clear from
the set-up that nothing of that kind is going to
work any attempt at that sort of thing will mean
that all the Indians will be killed, and himself.
The men against the wall, and the other
villagers, understand the situation, and are
obviously begging him to accept. What should he
do? (From the first page of Williams
Utilitarianism and Integrity)
29Jims options
- Jim gets to choose between these actions
- A. Killing one of the villagers himself.
- B. Not killing anyone.
- Their consequences
- A. One villager gets killed (by Jim) and the rest
of the villagers go free. - B. Twenty villagers get killed (by Pedro).
- What should Jim do? What would you do?
30Utilitarianismand the dilemmas
- In both of our dilemmas
- Option (a) (making weapons/killing the villager)
- leads to the best consequences available, but
involves doing something morally repugnant. - Option (b)
- leads to less good consequences, but you get to
have a clean conscience. - Utilitarians seem to have to choose (a).
- Deontologists would choose (b).
31Utilitarianism andNegative Responsibility
- Utilitarianism and Negative responsibility
- According to Williams, Utilitarianism entails the
notion of negative responsibility - If I am ever responsible for anything, then I
must be just as much responsible for things that
I allow or fail to prevent, as I am for things
that I myselfbring about. (492, I.e. the 6th
page of the article) - Thus, for a Utilitarian, should Jim refrain from
killing the 1 Indian, he is morally responsible
and so blameworthy for the deaths of the Indians
Pedro kills. - And should George not take the job, he is
responsible for the increased weapons production
of the new hire.
32Williams on Moral Responsibility
- Williams on Moral Responsibility
- For Williams, Jim is only morally responsible for
his own actions, not for Pedros. So Jim cant
be blamed for what Pedro does. - And George is only morally responsible for his
actions, not for those of whoever will take the
chemical weapons job if he doesnt take it. - Williams supports for this view (492, 6th page of
the article) - While the deaths, and the killing, may be the
outcome of Jims refusal, it is misleading to
think, in such a case, of Jim having an effect on
the world through the medium (as it happens) of
Pedros acts for this is to leave Pedro out of
the picture in his essential role of one who has
intentions and projects, projects for realizing
which Jims refusal would leave an opportunity.
Instead of thinking in terms of supposed effects
of Jims projects on Pedro, it is more revealing
to think of the effects of Pedros projects on
Jims decision
33The dilemmas are Counterexamples to
Utilitarianism
- So Williams thinks the dilemmas are
counterexamples to Utilitarianism - The dilemmas show that sometimes the right thing
to do isnt to bring about the best consequences. - Sometimes it is more important to stick by what
we believe. -
- The Utilitarian reply Its selfish!
- Isnt it really just selfish to try to keep your
own conscience clean by allowing someone else to
do something wrong? - What would the villagers ask of Jim?
34Williams reply a loss of personal integrity
- Williams response A loss of personal Integrity!
- Utilitarianism entails that the projects and
commitments with which a person is most deeply
identified, those which make up who a person is,
can be swept aside for the sake of the greater
good. - The decision so determined is, for
utilitarianism, the right decision. But what if
it conflicts with some project of mine? This,
the utilitarian will say, has already been dealt
with the satisfaction to you of fulfilling your
project, and any satisfaction to others of your
so doing, have already been through the
calculating device and have been found
inadequate. Now in the case of many sorts of
projects, that is a perfectly reasonable sort of
answer. But in the case of projects of the sort
I have called commitments, those with which one
is more deeply and extensively involved and
identified, this cannot just by itself be an
adequate answer, and there may be no adequate
answer at all. For, to take the extreme sort of
case, how can a man, as a utilitarian agent, come
to regard as one satisfaction among others, and a
dispensable one, a project or attitude round
which he has built his life, just because someone
elses projects have so structured the causal
scene that that is how the utilitarian sum comes
out? (494, I.e. the final page of the Williams
article) - Note that Williams is most worried about
Utilitarianisms attack on what he calls
commitments - Examples of commitments
35Personal Integrity
- A loss of personal integrity again
- It is the Utilitarians commitment to the
sacrifice of ones own projects, commitments,
goals and principles for the sake of the greater
good, which lies at the heart of its attack on
ones own personal integrity - It is absurd to demand of such a manthat he
should just step aside from his own project and
decision and acknowledge the decision which the
utilitarian calculation requires. It is to
alienate him in a real sense from his actions and
the source of his action in his own convictions.
It is to make him into a channel between the
input of everyones projects, including his own,
and an output of optimific decision but this is
to neglect the extent to which his actions and
his decisions have to be seen as the actions and
decisions which flow from the projects and
attitudes with which he is most closely
identified. It is thus, in the most literal
sense, an attack on his integrity. (Williams, pg
494, I.e. the final page of the article) - The Utilitarian response
- why cant your integrity be built upon the
Utilitarian principle?