Functions and infinite sets - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 71
About This Presentation
Title:

Functions and infinite sets

Description:

Title: Slides for Rosen, 5th edition Subject: Discrete Mathematics Author: Michael P. Frank Description: Slides developed at the University of Florida for course ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:211
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 72
Provided by: Micha1272
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: Functions and infinite sets


1
Functions and infinite sets
  • (Approx 2-3 lectures. Initial sections adapted
    from slides for a course by Michael P. Frank)

2
Reading relevant chapters of any book on
Discrete Maths. For example, Rosen 5th ed., 1.8
3
Functions
  • From calculus, you know the concept of a
    real-valued function f, which assigns to each
    number x?R one particular value yf(x), where
    y?R.
  • Example f defined by the rule f(x)x2
  • Roughly, functions say the so-and-so of
  • Functions are also called operations, mappings,
    etc.

4
Functions
  • To understand functions more precisely, one needs
    the mathematical notion of a set
  • We assume you are familiar with naïve set
    theory (as opposed to axiomatic set theory).
  • In a nutshell

5
Reminder of main set concepts
  • ?, ?, ?, ?, ?,
  • , ?, ?, ?, ?, ?, etc.
  • a,b,... (def. of a set by enumeration)x
    P(x) (def. by set builder notation)
  • x?S, S?T, ST, S?T.
  • P(S) (power set of S),
  • A?B (Cartesian product of A and B)

6
Reminder of main set concepts
  • Important sets of numbers N, Z, Q, R
  • A relation on A is a subset of AxA. E.g.,
  • on, N, the relation lt is (0,1),(0,2), (1,2),
  • Set equality proof techniques
  • E.g., to prove AB, prove each of
  • A?B
  • B?A

7
Function Formal Definition
  • A function f from (or mapping) A to B (fA?B)
    is an assignment of exactly one element f(x)?B to
    each element x?A.
  • Generalisations
  • Functions of n arguments f (A1 x A2... x An) ?
    B.
  • A partial (non-total) function f assigns zero or
    one elements of B to each element x?A.

8
Functions precisely
  • We can represent a function fA?B as a set of
    ordered pairs f (a,f(a)) a?A.
  • This makes f a relation between A and Bf is a
    subset of A x B. But functions are special
  • for every a?A, there is at least one pair (a,b).
    Formally ?a?A?b?B((a,b)?f)
  • for every a?A, there is at most one pair (a,b).
    Formally ??a,b,c((a,b)?f ? (a,c)?f ? b?c)
  • A relation over numbers can be represent as a set
    of points on a plane. (A point is a pair (x,y).)
  • A function is then a curve (set of points), with
    only one y for each x.

9
Useful diagrams
  • Functions can be represented graphically in
    several ways

A
B
f


f




y

a
b




x
A
Bipartite Graph
B
Plot
Like Venn diagrams
10
Functions that youve seen before
  • A set S over universe U can be viewed as a
    function from the elements of U to

11
Still More Functions
  • A set S over universe U can be viewed as a
    function from the elements of U to
  • T, F, saying for each element of U
    whether it is in S. (This is called the
    characteristic function of S)
  • Suppose U0,1,2,3,4. Then
  • S1,3? S(0)S(2)S(4)F, S(1)S(3)T.

12
Still More Functions
  • A set operator, such as ? or ?, can be viewed as
    a function from to

13
Still More Functions
  • A set operator such as ? or ? can be viewed as a
    function from (ordered) pairs of sets, to
    sets.
  • Example ?((1,3,3,4)) 3

14
A new notation
  • YX is the set F of all possible functions f X?Y.
  • Thus, f ? YX is another way of saying f X?Y.
  • (This notation is especially appropriate, because
    for finite X, Y, we have F YX. )

15
Some Function Terminology
  • If fA?B, and f(a)b (where a?A b?B), then we
    say
  • A is the domain of f.
  • B is the codomain of f.
  • b is the image of a under f.
  • a is a pre-image of b under f.
  • In general, b may have more than 1 pre-image.
  • The range R?B of f is Rb ?a f(a)b .

We also saythe signatureof f is A?B.
16
Range versus Codomain
  • The range of a function may not be its whole
    codomain.
  • The codomain is the set that the function is
    declared to map all domain values into.
  • The range is the particular set of values in the
    codomain that the function actually maps elements
    of the domain to.

17
Choosing the right (co)domain
  • Consider the function f such that f (x) 100/x
  • Is f a (total) function from Int to R?
  • f is a partial function from Int to R
  • f is a (total) function from Int-0 to R
  • Consider the function g such that g(x) vx
  • Is g a (total) function from R to R?
  • g is a total function from R to RxR
  • e.g. g(4) (2,-2)

18
Images of Sets under Functions
  • Given fA?B, and S?A,
  • The image of S under f is the set of all images
    (under f) of the elements of S. f(S) ? f(s)
    s?S ? b ?s?S f(s)b.
  • The range of f equalsthe image (under f) of ...

19
Images of Sets under Functions
  • Given fA?B, and S?A,
  • The image of S under f is the set of all images
    (under f) of the elements of S. f(S) ? f(s)
    s?S ? b ?s?S f(s)b.
  • The range of f equalsthe image (under f) of fs
    domain.

20
One-to-One Functions
  • A function is one-to-one (1-1), or injective, or
    an injection, iff every element of its range has
    only 1 pre-image.
  • Formally given fA?B,f is injective ?
    (??x,y x?y ? f(x)?f(y)).
  • In other words only one element of the domain is
    mapped to any given one element of the range.
  • In this case, domain range have same
    cardinality. What about codomain?

21
  • Codomain may be larger.

22
One-to-One Illustration
  • Are these relations one-to-one functions?




























23
One-to-One Illustration
  • Are these relations one-to-one functions?




























One-to-one
24
One-to-One Illustration
  • Are these relations one-to-one functions?




























Not one-to-one
One-to-one
25
One-to-One Illustration
  • Are these relations one-to-one functions?




























Not even a function!
Not one-to-one
One-to-one
26
Sufficient Conditions for 1-1ness
  • For functions f over numbers, we say
  • f is strictly increasing iff xgty ? f(x)gtf(y) for
    all x,y in domain
  • f is strictly decreasing iff xgty ? f(x)ltf(y) for
    all x,y in domain
  • If f is either strictly increasing or strictly
    decreasing, then f must be one-to-one.
  • Does the converse hold?

27
Onto (Surjective) Functions
  • A function fA?B is onto or surjective or a
    surjection iff its range is equal to its codomain
    (?b?B, ?a?A f(a)b).
  • Consider country of birth of A?B,where
    Apeople, Bcountries. Is this a function? Is
    it an injection? Is it a surjection?

28
Onto (Surjective) Functions
  • A function fA?B is onto or surjective or a
    surjection iff its range is equal to its codomain
  • Consider country of birth of A?B,where
    Apeople, Bcountries. Is this a function? Yes
    (always 1 c.o.b.) Is it an injection? No (many
    have same c.o.b.) Is it a surjection? Probably
    yes ..

29
Onto (Surjective) Functions
  • A function fA?B is onto or surjective or a
    surjection iff its range is equal to its codomain
  • In predicate logic

30
Onto (Surjective) Functions
  • A function fA?B is onto or surjective or a
    surjection iff its range is equal to its
    codomain.
  • In predicate logic
  • ?b?B?a?A f(a)b

31
Onto (Surjective) Functions
  • A function fA?B is onto or surjective or a
    surjection iff its range is equal to its codomain
    (?b?B?a?A f(a)b).
  • E.g., for domain codomain Z, the function
    ?x.x1 is injective and surjective.

32
  • Claim if fZ?Z and f(x) x1 then
  • f is 1-to-1 and also onto.
  • (Z is the set
    of all integers)
  • Proof that f is onto Consider any arbitrary
    element a of Z. We have f(a-1)a, where a ? Z.
  • Proof that f is 1-to-1 Suppose f(u)f(w)a. In
    other words, u1a and w1a. It follows that uw.

33
Onto/surjective functions
  • Are these functions onto their depicted
    co-domains?




































34
Onto/surjective functions
  • Are these functions onto?






































35
Onto/surjective functions
  • Are these functions onto?




































onto
not onto
onto
not onto
36
1-1/injective functions
  • Are these functions 1-1?




































onto
not onto
onto
not onto
37
1-1/injective functions
  • Are these functions 1-1?




































not 1-1onto
not 1-1not onto
1-1onto
1-1not onto
38
Bijections
  • A function is said to be a one-to-one
    correspondence, or a bijection iff it is both
    one-to-one and onto.

39
Two terminologies for talking about functions
  • injection one-to-one
  • surjection onto
  • bijection one-to-one correspondence
  • 3 12

40
Bijections
  • For bijections fA?B, there exists a function
    that is the inverse of f, written f ?1 B?A
  • Intuitively, this is the function that undoes
    everything that f does
  • Formally, its the unique function such that
  • ...

41
Bijections
  • For bijections fA?B, there exists an inverse of
    f, written f ?1 B?A
  • Intuitively, this is the function that undoes
    everything that f does
  • Formally, its the unique function such that
  • (the identity function on A)

42
Bijections
  • Example 1 Let f Z?Z be defined as f(x) x1.
    What is f?1 ?
  • Example 2 Let g Z?N be defined as g(x) x.
    What is g?1 ?

43
Bijections
  • Example 1 Let f Z?Z be defined as f(x)x1.
    What is f?1 ?
  • f?1 is the function (lets call it h) h Z?Z
    defined as h(x)x-1.
  • Proof

h(f(x)) (x1)-1 x
44
Bijections
  • Example 2 Let g Z?N be defined as g(x)x.
    What is g?1 ?
  • This was a trick question there is no such
    function, since g is not a bijectionThere is no
    function h such that h(x)x and h(x)?x
  • (NB There is a relation h for which this is
    true.)

45
Cardinality (informal)
  • The cardinality of a finite set is its number of
    elements
  • E.g., card(a,b,c) card(e,f,g) 3
  • Note for finite sets X and Y, card(X)card(Y)
    if and only if there exists a bijection between X
    and Y

46
infinity
  • This is straightforward if a set has 0 or 1 or 2
    or n (any natural number) elements
  • But what if the set has more elements than that?
    Some examples
  • The set of all natural numbers itself
  • The set of all even natural numbers
  • L(1) 1, 11,111,1111,11111, etc.
  • L(01) 01,001,011,0001,0011, etc

47
The Diagonalisation Method
  • Georg Cantor (1873) Whats the size of an
    infinite set?
  • E.g., is card(L(1)) card(L(01))?
  • Both are infinite
  • But is one larger than the other?
  • Cantors idea
  • The size (cardinality) of a set should not depend
    on the identity of its elements
  • Two finite sets A and B have the same size if we
    can pair the elements of A with elements of B
  • Formally there exists a bijection between A and B

48
Correspondences (Contd)
  • Example Let
  • N be the set of pos. natural numbers 1, 2, 3,
  • E the set of even pos. natural numbers 2, 4, 6,
  • Using Cantors definition of size, we can show
    that N and E have the same size
  • Bijection (!) f (n) 2n
  • Intuitively, E is smaller than N, but
  • Pairing each element of N with its corresponding
    element in E is possible,
  • So we declare these two set to be the same size
  • This even though E ? N (E is a real subset of
    N )

49
Countable sets
  • A set X is finite if it has n elements, for some
    n in N.
  • A set is countable if either
  • It is finite or
  • It has the same size as N, the natural numbers
  • For example,
  • N is countable, and so are all its subsets
  • E is countable
  • 0,1,2,3 is countable
  • ? is countable
  • How about supersets of N ?

50
An Even Stranger Example
  • Let Q be the set of positive rational numbers
  • Q m/n m,n ? N
  • Just like E, the set Q has the same size as N !
  • We show this giving a bijection from Q to N
  • Q is thus countable
  • One way is to enumerate (i.e., to list) Qs
    elements.
  • Pair the first element of Q with 1 (first elt. of
    N )
  • And so on, making sure every member of Qappears
    only once in the list

51
An Even Stranger Example (Contd)
  • To build a list with the elements of Q
  • make inf. matrix with all positive rational
    numbers
  • i -th row contains all numbers with numerator i
  • j -th column has all numbers with denominator j
  • i /j is in i -th row and j -th column

52
An Even Stranger Example (Contd)
  • Now we turn the previous matrix into a list
  • A bad way begin list with first row
  • Since rows are infinite, we will never get to 2nd
    row!

53
An Even Stranger Example (Contd)
  • Instead, we list the elements along diagonals

We should, however, eliminate repeated elements
54
An Even Stranger Example (Contd)
  • We list elements along diagonals w/o repetitions

?1/1, 2/1, 1/2, 3/1, 1/3, ?
55
Uncountable sets
  • Some sets have no correspondence with N
  • These sets are simply too big!
  • They are not countable we say uncountable
  • Theorem
  • The set of real numbers between 0 and 1(e.g.,
    0.244, 0.3141592323....) is uncountableCall this
    set R0,1
  • (Some sets are even larger. Serious set
    theory is all about theorems that concern
    infinite sets. Most of this is irrelevant for
    this course.)

56
  • Theorem R0,1 gt N. Proof strategy
  • R0,1 gtN. Suppose R0,1 N and derive a
    contradiction Each member of R0,1 can be written
    as a zero followed by a dot and a countable
    sequence of digits. Suppose there existed a
    complete enumeration of R, (using whatever order)
    lte1,e2,e3,...gt.

57
  • showing how an arbitrary list might start
  • e1. 0.0000000000000000000000....
  • e2. 0.0100000000000000000000....
  • e3. 0.8200000000000000000000....
  • e4. 0.1710000000000000000000....
  • ...

58
Now construct a Real number n thats not in the
enumeration
  • ns first digit (after the dot) e1s first
    digit 1
  • ns second digit e2s second digit 1 ...
  • General ns i-th difit e-is i-th digit 1
  • ?i n differs from e-i in its i-th digit
  • Contradiction lte1,e2,e3,...gt is not a (complete)
    enumeration after all. QED

59
  • This proof of the non-countability of the set of
    Real numbers is known as Cantors diagonalisation
    argument
  • It proved to be the start of a large new area of
    set theory, involving the cardinalities of
    infinite sets

60
The Russell Paradox
  • For example, read Rosen 5th ed., 1.6especially
    ex. 30 on p. 86

61
Basic Set Notations
  • Set enumeration a, b, c
  • and set-builder xP(x).
  • ? relation, and the empty set ?.
  • Set relations , ?, ?, ?, ?, ?, etc.
  • Venn diagrams.
  • Cardinality S and infinite sets N, Z, R.
  • Power sets P(S).

62
Axiomatic set theory
  • Various axioms, e.g., saying that the union of a
    set of sets is a set the intersection of a set
    of sets is a set etc.
  • One key axiom Given a Predicate P, one can
    construct a set. It consists of all those
    elements x such that P(x) is true.
  • But, the resulting theory turns out to be
    logically inconsistent!
  • This means, there exists set theory proposition p
    such that both p and ?p follow logically from
    the axioms of the theory!
  • ? The conjunction of the axioms is a
    contradiction
  • This makes the theory is fundamentally
    uninteresting, because any possible statement in
    it can be (very trivially) proven!

63
Prove
  • Theorem Given a contradiction, any statement can
    be proven

64
Prove
  • Theorem Given a contradiction, any statement can
    be proven
  • Proof Let your contradiction be p ?p
    (the assumption is youve proven it before)
  • Suppose you want to prove q
  • (p ?p) --gt q is a tautology of propositional
    logic(Check truth table of the formula, given p
    ?p is false)
  • Youve proven p ?p
  • q follows with Modus Ponens. Note that q is
    arbitrary!

65
This version of Set Theory is inconsistent
  • Russells paradox
  • Consider the set that corresponds with the
    predicate x ? x
  • S x x?x .
  • Now ask is S?S?

66
Russells paradox
  • Let S x x?x . Is S?S?
  • If S?S, then S is one of those x for which x?x.
    In other words, S?SWith Proof by Contradiction,
    we have S?S
  • If S?S, then S is not one of those x for which
    x?x. In other words, S?SWith Proof by
    Contradiction, we have S?S
  • We conclude that both S?S nor S?S
  • Paradox!

67
  • To avoid inconsistency, set theory had to somehow
    change

Bertrand Russell1872-1970
68
One technique to avoid the problem
  • Given a set S and a predicate P, construct a new
    set, consisting of those elements x of S such
    that P(x) is true.
  • Youll seen this technique in use when we get to
    the programming language Haskell, where we can
    write
  • x x ? 1.. , even x, but not x even x.

69
Another technique to avoid the problem
  • Russells paradox arises from the fact that we
    can write funny things like x?x (or x?x, for
    that matter). One solutionforbid such
    expressions using types.
  • Youll seen this technique in use as well
    Haskells use of typing.

70
Our focus computability
  • We shall not worry about saving set theory from
    paradoxes like Russells
  • Instead, we shall use the Russell paradox in a
    different setting
  • But first we need to talk about Formal Languages,
    Haskell, and Turing Machines

71
(No Transcript)
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com