Introduction to Ethics Lecture 11 Utilitarianism - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 24
About This Presentation
Title:

Introduction to Ethics Lecture 11 Utilitarianism

Description:

Introduction to Ethics Lecture 11 Utilitarianism By David Kelsey – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:180
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 25
Provided by: DavidK279
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: Introduction to Ethics Lecture 11 Utilitarianism


1
Introduction to EthicsLecture 11Utilitarianism
  • By David Kelsey

2
Mill
  • John Stuart Mill (1806-1873)
  • He was the greatest 19th century defender of
    Utilitarianism.
  • He was a child prodigy.
  • Defended womens suffrage.
  • His text Utilitarianism was published in 1861.

3
Utilitarianism
  • The greatest happiness principle
  • Actions are right in proportion as they tend to
    promote happiness,
  • wrong as they tend to produce the reverse of
    happiness.
  • Or
  • Always do whatever will produce the greatest
    happiness for the greatest number.

4
Utilitarianismits two parts
  • Any version of Utilitarianism (including Mills
    version) is composed of two other views
  • Consequentialism
  • We determine whether an act is right or wrong by
    looking at its consequences.
  • Hedonism
  • This tells us what makes for a better or worse
    consequence.
  • Good what promotes pleasure
  • Bad what promotes pain.

5
Consequentialism
  • Consequentialism To determine whether or not an
    action is right
  • weigh the good consequences of doing the action
    against the bad consequences of doing it.
  • And weigh the good consequences of not doing the
    action against the bad consequences of not doing
    it.
  • Do whatever will have the best overall
    consequences.
  • Sorting good from bad Thus, to determine whether
    or not an action is right
  • One must be able to sort the good consequences
    from the bad consequences.
  • Defining the good then the Right Thus,
    Consequentialist moral theories, like
    Utilitarianism,
  • Define the good, I.e. what they want to promote,
    then define what is right by simply calculating
    what will best promote that good.

6
Consequentialism
  • Other ways to define Consequentialism
  • Between two actions, perform the one that has
    better consequences.
  • One determines whether an act is right or wrong
    by looking solely at its consequences.
  • The end justifies the means.
  • The consequences of an action can justify the
    action itself.
  • Thus, harming someone could be justified

7
Hedonism
  • Hedonism says that a good thing is one that adds
    to the sum total of human happiness.
  • Happiness pleasure and the absence of pain.
  • Unhappiness pain and the absence of pleasure.
  • Hedonism Happiness
  • What makes something, anything and not just life,
    good is the amount of happiness it produces.
  • Happiness is the only non-derivative good
  • It is the only thing that is good as an end in
    itself.
  • Derivative goods money, knowledge, fulfilling
    personal relationships, etc.

8
Calculating Pleasures
  • Jeremy Bentham, who with Mill created the
    Utilitarian theory, took it upon himself to
    provide a way to calculate pleasures and pains
  • A calculus of pleasures and pains
  • He first lists the various pleasures and pains
  • Those of sense, of wealth, of skill, of a good
    name, of piety, power, happy memories, etc.
  • He then highlights the ways in which pleasures
    and pains can differ
  • Intensity
  • Duration
  • Certainty or uncertainty
  • Purity
  • Extent
  • So Pleasures and Pains can be quantified.
  • We have a mathematical formula, a science, of
    pleasures and pains.

9
A Side noteThe two forms ofUtilitarianism
  • Utilitarianism comes in two forms
  • The first is called Act Utilitarianism
  • The view that you should determine whether any
    act is morally right by looking at the
    consequences of that act itself.
  • The second is called Rule Utilitarianism.
  • The view that you should determine whether any
    act is morally right by looking at the
    consequences of a rule which says that everyone
    should perform that act in like circumstances.
  • You want a rule that would overall best serve to
    maximize happiness.

10
Objections toRule Utilitarianism
  • Objection to Rule Utilitarianism it collapses
    into act utilitarianism.
  • This is because no matter what the rule, there
    will be some circumstances in which it is
    beneficial to break the rule, which means the
    rule would have to be modified to make an
    exception for those circumstances.
  • But deciding whether a rule should be modified is
    tantamount to just being an act utilitarian

11
Mills argument for Hedonism
  • The non-derivative good is what people want
    non-derivatively
  • Mill thinks that a non-derivatively good thing
    must be what all people want for itself, as an
    end, not as a means to something else.
  • But, Mill says, the production of pleasure and
    the absence of pain is what everyone wants for
    itself.
  • His evidence for this look around!!!
  • What people do desire is just the production of
    pleasure and the absence of pain.

12
The form of Mills argument
  • The form of Mills argument
  • 1. A non-derivatively good thing is one that
    people want for itself.
  • 2. Happiness is the only thing that people want
    for itself.
  • 3. Thus, happiness is the only non-derivative
    good.
  • Is this argument sound?
  • Premise 1
  • Premise 2?
  • What about the move to the conclusion?

13
Objection to Hedonismthe life of the beasts
  • Some people object that hedonism is degrading.
  • It makes the best life the life of the beasts.
  • If a pig can live a life completely satisfied,
    while a morally concerned and thoughtful man like
    Socrates cannot ever be so satisfied, isnt the
    life of the pig preferable?
  • Mills reply
  • Human beings have faculties more elevated than
    the animal appetites, and when once made
    conscious of them, do not regard anything as
    happiness which does not include their
    gratification.

14
Mills reply
  • The form of Mills reply
  • 1-There are higher and lower pleasures.
  • 2-Any amount of higher pleasure is preferable to
    any amount of lower pleasure.
  • His evidence anyone who has experienced higher
    pleasures would prefer them, on reflection, to
    lower pleasures.
  • Higher pleasures
  • any use of the mind including reflection or
    thought,
  • Lower pleasures
  • All pleasures not as a result of using the mind.
  • 3-Since the life of the beast produces only lower
    pleasures, the life of the beast isnt the best
    life at all.
  • Questions

15
The life of virtue
  • Objection wouldnt you rather be virtuous than
    happy.
  • Selling out
  • Often we have the opportunity to sell out, to
    get something that will make us happy at the cost
    of doing bad.
  • Many people would rather not do that.
  • Mills reply
  • The life of virtue is an important part of being
    happy.
  • You wouldnt really be happy if you sold out.

16
Who counts?
  • Objection it is difficult to determine just who
    we include in our calculation of utility?
  • Do we include all persons whose interest may be
    affected?
  • Only those in our own state? Our own community?
    Our own family?
  • What about non-human sentient beings? Should
    their pleasure or pain count?
  • Singer
  • argues that since animals can feel pleasure and
    pain just like humans, their interests must be
    taken into account when calculating the overall
    good an action produces.
  • So it is morally wrong to eat animals, to
    experiment on them, or to imprison them in zoos.
  • What about future generations?
  • Should we consider the interests of future
    persons?
  • Should we consider the environment?

17
Quantifying happiness?
  • To determine how much pleasure vs. pain an act
    produces
  • one must consider whether an act will lead to
    greater pleasure than pain
  • one must also consider the intensity of that
    pleasure (and the intensity of that pain).
  • But it is extremely difficult to calculate the
    intensity of pleasure and pain.
  • Could you assign numeric values to your pleasures
    and pains?
  • Could you assign numeric values to your pleasures
    and pains vs. mine, or higher vs. lower pleasure
    and pains.
  • Mills reply
  • Estimation is sufficient

18
Calculation is based onmere prediction
  • Isnt it just impossible to weigh out the
    pleasure and pain that result from an action.
  • Consider
  • How can we even predict all of the consequences
    of our actions?
  • And how do we predict the pleasure and pain that
    will result from the consequences of our actions?
  • A plausible response
  • We are only trying to maximize probable utility.

19
Demanding-ness
  • Utilitarianism really asks us to leave our lives
    to go cure world hunger
  • If everyones happiness is of equal value to our
    own, then it will be hard to justify doing
    anything other than working to alleviate world
    hunger.
  • Justifying a steak dinner?
  • The response
  • We know what will produce our own happiness
    better than what will produce happiness in other
    people.
  • Counter-response
  • Basic necessities

20
Utilitarianism ignoresthe distinctness of
persons
  • Utilitarianism could justify inflicting pain in
    some if others are afforded pleasure
  • Slavery example
  • a utilitarian would have to weigh the suffering
    of those who would be slaves against the benefits
    accruing to those who would be slave owners.
  • Making the trade off
  • It may be possible for a single individual to
    make this trade-off
  • One could weigh the pain of having a tooth pulled
    against the benefit of getting rid of the
    toothache,
  • But can you really justify inflicting pain on one
    person by pointing to the increased pleasure this
    will bring to others?

21
What about promises?
  • Utilitarianism does not give sufficient weight to
    past acts
  • Utilitarianism is forward looking
  • Past events have relevance only to the extent
    that they affect future consequences.
  • For the Utilitarian, the fact that I have
    promised to do something is not in itself a
    reason for doing it.
  • As a Utilitarian, I will keep my promise only if
    keeping it will have the best consequences

22
Promises once again
  • The Utilitarian will often talk of justifying
    keeping a promise because of the negative
    consequences brought if it is broken
  • I make it less likely that people will rely on my
    promises in the future
  • Undermining the institution of promise keeping
  • But dont we keep our promises for reasons other
    than that doing so produces pleasure?
  • Isnt there something valuable about keeping a
    promise in and of itself?

23
What about Rights?
  • For a Utilitarian there arent any absolute
    prohibitions
  • For anything can be justified if it produces the
    best consequences.
  • Thus, there are no absolute rights either.
  • But arent there absolute rights?
  • These are rights that cannot be violated under
    any circumstances.
  • The reply
  • It would almost always maximize happiness to
    respect rights against such conduct.
  • The counter
  • But this still allows for individual violations
    of such rights

24
The fatal flaw of Utilitarianism
  • The problem with Utilitarianism
  • a Utilitarian would tell you to kill an innocent
    if it meant the production of more pleasure than
    pain.
  • The real problem the Utilitarian puts the good
    before the right
  • Utilitarians first decide what is good and then
    decide what is right by looking at what will
    produce the greatest amount of good.
  • As long as you do this, critics argue, no act is
    always morally wrong
  • Put the right before the good
  • Some critics argue this is the only way to solve
    this problem
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com