Chapter 6: Treating or Terminating: The Dilemma of Impaired Infants - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 28
About This Presentation
Title:

Chapter 6: Treating or Terminating: The Dilemma of Impaired Infants

Description:

Every year, more than 400,000 babies are born at least six weeks prematurely and about 62,000 of them weigh less than 1600 grams (about 3.5 pounds). – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:33
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 29
Provided by: cengageCo4
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: Chapter 6: Treating or Terminating: The Dilemma of Impaired Infants


1
Chapter 6 Treating or Terminating The Dilemma
of Impaired Infants
2
Ethical issues
  • The treatment of impaired infants raises ethical
    questions common to other bioethical issues such
    as abortion and euthanasia but also specific to
    the conditions of such infants themselves.
  • The severe under-development of low-birth-weight
    babies puts them at high risk for developing
    serious physical and mental problems later in
    life. Some facts about such infants are
    summarized below.
  • The basic moral question about extremely
    low-birth-weight infants is whether they ought to
    be treated at all or, if they are already being
    treated, whether that treatment should continue.

3
Ethical issues
  • On the one hand, are those who regard the
    treatment of all infants as a moral obligation
    because they have a right to life in the same way
    as an adult human being. The fact that these
    infants might develop severe problems later, for
    themselves or others, is simply irrelevant.
  • All means necessary should be used to keep such
    infants alive. Those who take this perspective
    will typically be opposed to abortion and
    euthanasia on similar grounds.

4
Ethical issues
  • On the other hand, others believe that the great
    likelihood of serious later physical and mental
    problems provide compelling reasons to withhold
    or minimize extraordinary efforts to keep such
    children alive.
  • On this view, the potential quality of life of
    the child is a crucial factor in deciding whether
    such effort should be made.
  • Additionally, resources devoted to such children
    are resources that cannot be used to help others.
    How should the choice be made?

5
Ethical issues
  • One of the factors that make impaired infants an
    ethically unique situation is the fact that the
    children themselves cannot be asked what they
    would want. Indeed, depending on the impairment,
    they may never reach a level of competence which
    would allow them to make such a decision.
  • In the case of adults, whether a patient should
    be treated or not, is today recognized as a
    question which the patient, himself, should
    answer if he is competent.

6
Ethical issues
  • But, since the impaired infant cannot make this
    decision, someone else, physicians, parents, or
    the state must do so.
  • Further, what criteria should be used in making
    the decision whoever is determined to be the
    appropriate authority?

7
Ethical issues
  • The two issues intertwine. In the case of
    euthanasia of adults in severe pain or at the end
    of life, they have lived long enough to develop
    preferences, which others might know about. Such
    preference could be part of a decision by the
    patient or others to end life.
  • But, in the case of an impaired infant, such
    preferences do not exist because there was no
    time for them to develop. In such cases,
    assumptions must be made by others. Indeed,
    some raise the question whether we can say the
    infant is even a person.
  • One approach, appealing to the best interests of
    the child tries to assess what will best benefit
    the child given the state of its development. But
    what constitutes best interests and is there a
    disinterested way of answering this question?

8
Facts about impaired infants
  • Every year, more than 400,000 babies are born at
    least six weeks prematurely and about 62,000 of
    them weigh less than 1600 grams (about 3.5
    pounds).
  • In the United States, more than a thousand
    preterm babies are born each day, and from 1990
    to 2006 (the latest figures, published in 2010),
    the preterm birthrate increased by 20 percent.
  • About 13 percent of all births in the U.S. are
    preterm.

9
Facts about impaired infants
  • Thanks to the development of new procedures and
    the use of new drugs, almost 85 of premature
    infants live long enough to leave the hospital
    (though many must return), but only about 20
    have no lasting major physical or mental
    impairment.
  • The more premature an infant and the lower the
    birth weight, the more likely it is that the
    infant will die soon after birth or be severely
    physically and mentally impaired.

10
Facts about impaired infants
  • About half of premature infants in the 500- to
    750-gram (1- to 1.5-pound) range fail to survive.
    From 25 to 33 percent of babies under 750 grams
    have irreversible neurological damage.
  • The figure rises to between 40 and 50 percent for
    those with a birth weight between 500 and 600
    grams. About 5 to 10 percent of these very
    low-birth-weight babies will have cerebral palsy,
    and a similar percentage will have IQs below 70,
    where 100 is average.

11
Facts about impaired infants
  • Survival rate is closely connected with gestation
    time. The technological limit for preserving the
    lives of premature infants is about twenty-three
    to twenty-four weeks.
  • Estimates of an infants developmental stage may
    be off by a week or so because its impossible to
    be certain when conception took place.

12
Facts about impaired infants
  • Premature girls have about a one-week
    developmental advantage over boys, and black
    infants have the same advantage over white
    infants. Thus, a white boy may be about two weeks
    behind in development compared with a black girl.
  • Premature babies have not spent enough time in
    the uterus, and as a result, they are
    physiologically underdeveloped. The more
    premature the infant, the more underdeveloped it
    is. Birth weight, generally, is an index of
    developmental prematurity.

13
Facts about impaired infants
  • Extremely premature neonates are fetal infants
    that have spent hardly more than half of the
    forty-week gestation period in their mothers
    uterus.
  • Extremely premature infants are liable to
    life-threatening disorders. Many have problems
    eating, digesting food, and absorbing nutrients.

14
Facts about impaired infants
  • Their lungs are small and brittle and fill up
    with secretions, making it impossible for them to
    breathe normally. They must be put on a
    mechanical ventilator, and they tend to suffer
    from respiratory infections.
  • Poor prenatal development also makes smaller
    infants prone to cerebral hemorrhages, or brain
    bleeds, that can result in a variety of
    devastating consequences. Infants that have had
    brain bleeds are prone to seizure disorders,
    blindness, low vision, deafness, mental
    retardation, and various more subtle mental
    difficulties that may show up only years later.

15
Section 1 The Groningen Protocol
  • The focus of the protocol is on proposed
    guidelines for determining when active infant
    euthanasia is justified.
  • But, just as important, is the context which gave
    rise to its formulation. Active infant euthanasia
    is illegal in most, if not all, countries of the
    world. This means that doctors who practice it
    are subject to criminal prosecution.

16
Section 1 The Groningen Protocol
  • Should this be?
  • Is it reasonable to put the euthanizing of an
    infant, like Bente Hindriks (discussed on page
    506) who was in intractable pain and bound to
    die, in the same moral category as someone who
    has deliberately committed homicide?
  • Answering the question of how impaired infants
    ought to be treated is relevant to answering this
    question as well. The fortunes of well-meaning
    physicians are on the line as well as impaired
    infants.

17
Reading The Groningen Protocol The Why and the
WhatJames Lemuel Smith
  •  
  • The author describes the problem faced by Dutch
    pediatrician Eduard Verhagen of dealing with
    infants who have a hopeless prognosis and
    intractable pain.
  • Smith then presents the scheme for classifying
    infants with serious medical problems into three
    categories and the five conditions for
    legitimizing active infant euthanasia that make
    up the Groningen Protocol as developed by
    Verhagen and his collaborator Pieter Sauer.

18
Section 2 The Ashley Treatment 
  • The Case of Ashley explores a set of ethical
    issues parallel to those raised by premature
    infants. Though born normally, Ashley began to
    develop in many of the abnormal ways that
    commonly result from premature birth.
  • The Ashley case raises the question of what
    criteria should be used to make decisions about
    problems that arise as impaired children grow.
  • For example, as Ashley matured, she would begin
    to menstruate. Should this be allowed to occur
    normally or, given her impaired condition, was it
    reasonable, as her parents believed, to intervene
    and prevent the menstrual cycle from occurring to
    spare her the discomforts, which can accompany
    it?
  • This first article describes the parents view of
    physical treatments of Ashley which they thought
    justified. The second offers a detailed analysis
    of ethical issues raised by the Ashley treatment,
    casting doubt on some of the parents decisions.

19
Reading The Ashley TreatmentAshleys Mom and
Dad
  • The young girl known only as Ashley had an
    apparently normal birth, but she appears to have
    suffered damage to her brain from an unknown
    cause.
  • Her mental and motor faculties have failed to
    develop, and as a result, she is completely
    dependent on others for her care.
  • Although the growth of her body was proceeding
    along a normal developmental path, her mental and
    motor functions would never improve.
  • Her parents, who identify themselves only as
    Ashleys Mom and Dad, argue on their blog about
    their daughter that the medical procedures they
    requested on the behalf of Ashley when she was
    nine (the Ashley treatment) were all intended
    to improve the quality of her life, not that of
    their own as caretakers.

20
Reading The Ashley TreatmentAshleys Mom and
Dad
  • With or without the treatment, the parents claim,
    their intention has always been to keep Ashley at
    home. The growth attenuation by hormone
    injections will keep her small enough to ensure
    that she is frequently moved to be with the other
    family members and the surgery to remove her
    uterus and breast buds will prevent menstrual
    cramps and the breast discomfort caused by lying
    down most of the time.
  • The surgeries, including a preventive
    appendectomy, will also spare Ashley the dangers
    of breast and uterine cancer and unrecognized
    appendicitis. The Ashley treatment, her parents
    argue, is in her best interest and will improve
    the quality of her life.

21
Reading The Ashley Treatment Best Interests,
Convenience, and Parental Decision-MakingS.
Matthew Liao, Julian Savulescu, and Mark Sheehan
  •  The authors argue that although growth
    attenuation in a severely disabled child like
    Ashley may be justifiable, hysterectomy and the
    surgical removal of breast buds are not.
  •  
  • Small size could be in Ashleys best interest,
    permitting her family to care for her at home. If
    the attenuation also promotes the interest of her
    parents, that should not count against it.
  • Moral obligations do not typically require large
    sacrifices of health and all others interests and
    duties. The benefit to Ashley of the removal of
    her uterus and breast buds, by contrast, is not
    as clear, and harms are more likely.

22
Reading The Ashley Treatment Best Interests,
Convenience, and Parental Decision-MakingS.
Matthew Liao, Julian Savulescu, and Mark Sheeh
  • Less invasive ways of protecting against cramps
    and the discomforts of having breasts might be
    found, and the risks of cancer and sexual abuse
    seem too unlikely to justify surgery.
  • The authors also reject the argument that an
    immature body is more in keeping with Ashleys
    mental age and will give her greater dignity.
  • Finally, the authors encourage us to see that the
    right to be loved and cared for that Ashley
    shares with other children, disabled people, and
    the elderly should be recognized by society and
    supported by every able person by paying taxes
    and voting for policies that help parents and
    other caregivers.

23
Section 3 The Status of Impaired Infants 
  • The papers in this section raise an issue that is
    common to several other bioethical concerns
    whether impaired infants are persons, that is,
    entities which deserve the same rights as adult
    humans, in particular, the right to life.
  • The right to life debate is systematically
    explored in the readings in the chapter on
    Abortion (chapter 5).

24
Reading Examination of Arguments in Favor of
Withholding Ordinary Medical Care from Defective
InfantsJohn A. Robertson
  •  John Robertson defends a conservative natural
    law position in criticizing two arguments in
    favor of withholding necessary but ordinary
    medical care from impaired infants.
  • He rejects the claim made by Michael Tooley that
    infants are not persons and argues that, on the
    contrary, there is no non-arbitrary consideration
    that requires us to protect the past realization
    of conceptual capability but not its potential
    realization.

25
Reading Examination of Arguments in Favor of
Withholding Ordinary Medical Care from Defective
InfantsJohn A. Robertson
  • The second argument that Robertson considers is
    one to the effect that we have no obligation to
    treat defective newborns when the cost of doing
    so greatly outweighs the benefits (a utilitarian
    argument).
  • In criticism, Robertson claims that we have no
    way of judging this. Life itself may be of
    sufficient worth to an impaired person to offset
    his or her suffering, and the suffering and cost
    to society are not sufficient to justify
    withholding care.

26
Reading Ethical Issues in Aiding the Death of
Young ChildrenH. Tristram Engelhardt, Jr.
  • The author contends that children are not persons
    in the full sense.
  • They must exist in and through their families.
    Thus, parents, in conference with a physician who
    provides information, are the appropriate ones to
    decide whether to treat an impaired newborn when
  • there is not only little likelihood of a full
    human life but also the likelihood of suffering
    if the life is prolonged or
  • (2) the cost of prolonging the life is very
    great.

27
Reading Ethical Issues in Aiding the Death of
Young ChildrenH. Tristram Engelhardt, Jr.
  • Engelhardt further argues that it is reasonable
    to speak of a duty not to treat an impaired
    infant when this will only prolong a painful life
    or would only lead to a painful death.
  • He bases his claim on the legal notion of a
    wrongful life. This notion suggests that there
    are cases in which nonexistence would be better
    than existence under the conditions in which a
    person must live.
  • Life can thus be seen as an injury, rather than
    as a gift.

28
Right to Life of the HandicappedAlison Davis
  • Davis argues, from her experience as a
    handicapped person, against allowing doctors,
    within the first 28 days of the life of a
    severely disabled infant, to predict the infants
    quality of life and decide the course of
    treatment on the basis.
  • Davis points out that the prediction for her
    would have been a life without worthwhile
    quality, a prediction wholly at odds with her own
    experience of life.
  •  She rejects the notion of non-personhood during
    the first four weeks of life and expresses the
    fear that following predictions made during that
    period to justify non-treatment would lead to the
    decriminalization of killing handicapped people
    at later ages.
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com