WORLD HUNGER - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 60
About This Presentation
Title:

WORLD HUNGER

Description:

We saw earlier with Thomas Nagel that it is hard for a person to care about ... to all of their earnings if no malady existed which could be removed by giving ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:491
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 61
Provided by: JeffSt6
Category:
Tags: hunger | world | malady

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: WORLD HUNGER


1
WORLD HUNGER
2
Famine, Affluence, and Morality
Peter Singer (1946-)
3
IMPARTIALITY AND STARVATION
  • We saw earlier with Thomas Nagel that it is hard
    for a person to care about others as much as she
    cares about herself, her family, and friends, but
    that a question for ethics is how impartial we
    ought to be towards others, and how much we owe
    to other people, even ones we dont know.
  • Singers paper is concerned with what each of us
    owes morally to other people, and with what our
    moral obligation is to prevent world hunger.

4
PRACTICAL AND MORAL ISSUES CONCERNING STARVATION
  • Singer says that mass starvation is preventable.
  • But Singer says that neither individuals nor
    governments have responded in any significant way
    to the problem of world hunger.
  • For Singer, the behavior of affluent individuals
    and wealthy countries regarding this issue cannot
    be ethically justified, and those who are capable
    of helping starving people should help.

5
CHANGING OUR MORALITY AND OUR LIFESTYLE
  • Singer says that the whole way in which we look
    at moral issues - our moral conceptual scheme -
    needs to be altered, and with it, the way of life
    that has come to be taken for granted in our
    society.
  • Thus, according to Singer, our morality is not
    the correct one, and our lifestyle must change in
    order to reflect a correct morality.
  • That our morality needs to change, and that we
    can no longer take for granted what we take for
    granted in our lifestyle, are things which Singer
    hopes to prove in this paper.

6
PRELIMINARY POINTS
  • The first point Singer makes in defense of his
    position that we need to do everything possible
    to eliminate world hunger is that suffering and
    death from lack of food, shelter, and medical
    care are bad.
  • He thinks that most people will agree with this,
    and he will take it that this point is accepted.
  • Point number two is that we ought to prevent
    something bad from happening which it is in our
    power to prevent if we do not have to sacrifice
    something of comparable moral importance in order
    to prevent it from happening.
  • Thus if I can help prevent someones starving
    without making it the case that my own family
    starves then I ought to do it.
  • The health and welfare of others then is of
    comparable moral importance to my own familys
    health and welfare.

7
THE MORALITY OF PREVENTION
  • This second point Singer thinks is almost as
    uncontroversial as the first one, since the
    principle just asks us to prevent what is bad
    from happening to other people if we can prevent
    it without causing something else bad to happen
    which is of similar moral importance
  • But the principle is really stronger than that,
    since it goes beyond asking us to prevent what we
    can and says that we ought to prevent what it is
    in our power to prevent if we can do so without
    sacrificing something of equal or like moral
    importance.
  • Thus, to use Singers own example, I ought to
    save a drowning child if I have the power to do
    so. This might make me wet, muddy, and
    uncomfortable, but that is a small price to pay
    for the life of a child.

8
THE PRINCIPLE OF PREVENTION I
  • This moral principle we ought to prevent
    something bad from happening which we can prevent
    if we can prevent it without sacrificing anything
    morally significant, Singer calls the principle
    of preventing bad occurrences, and I will call
    the principle of prevention for short.
  • And Singer says that, if this principle were
    acted upon by everyone, our lives, our society,
    and the world would change radically.
  • This is because the principle of prevention, the
    principle that we ought to prevent something bad
    from happening which we can prevent if we can
    prevent the bad thing without sacrificing
    anything morally significant, does a couple of
    important things.

9
THE PRINCIPLE OF PREVENTION II
  • 1. The principle takes no account of proximity or
    distance. Thus it does not matter if the thing
    which I can help prevent is near or far.
  • 2. It does not matter if I am the only person
    who can help, or if I am one of millions who can
    help. For instance, I might be the only one to
    happen by when a child is drowning, but I may be
    one of millions who could afford to send a little
    money to prevent starvation.

10
PREVENTION AND IMPARTIALITY
  • It may be a fact of human psychology that we tend
    to help those who are closer to us, but,
    according to Singer, that does not show that we
    ought to help someone closer to us rather than
    someone who is farther away.
  • The principle of prevention, the principle which
    says prevent something bad from happening which
    you can if you dont have to sacrifice anything
    morally significant, is a principle of
    impartiality.
  • It means that we ought to treat everyone equally,
    that we cannot discriminate against a person
    simply because she is far away.

11
PROXIMITY, DISTANCE, AND MORAL JUDGEMENT I
  • Singer admits that, if we are in a better
    position to judge what those people who are close
    to us need, then this would be a good reason to
    help those who are closest to us first.
  • But he also notes that mass communication has
    changed the relation of modern man to the rest of
    the world. Now it is easy to get the sounds and
    pictures of mass starvation in foreign countries
    from newspapers, television, and the Internet.
  • Kinds of mass communication have made the world
    into Marshall McLuhans global village, and so
    have changed our moral relation to the rest of
    the world.

12
PROXIMITY, DISTANCE, AND MORAL JUDGEMENT II
  • Famine relief agencies can get help to the people
    abroad who need it almost as easily as we could
    get help to someone on our own block. And, for
    Singer, that means that we have no excuse not to
    help those far removed from us.
  • Accordingly, he says that There would seem,
    therefore, to be no possible justification for
    discriminating on geographical grounds.

13
NUMBERS, PSYCHOLOGICAL DIFFERENCES, AND MORAL
OBLIGATION
  • Singer says that, although there is a
    psychological difference between being the only
    person who can prevent something bad from
    happening, and being one of a million who can
    prevent something bad from happening, there is no
    moral difference between these cases.
  • Should I feel less obligated to help the drowning
    child if other people are as close to her as I
    am?
  • Singer says of course not, and this he thinks
    shows the absurdity of the view that numbers
    lessen moral obligation.
  • Singer says that most of the major evils in the
    world - poverty, overpopulation, and pollution -
    are problems in which everyone is almost equally
    involved.

14
DUTY AND CHARITY I
  • The outcome of the principle of prevention, the
    principle that we ought to prevent something bad
    from happening which we can prevent if we can
    prevent the bad thing without sacrificing
    anything morally significant, is that we lose the
    traditional distinction between duty and charity.
  • Thus, traditionally we think of giving as
    charitable, and, as charitable, we do not think
    that there is anything wrong with not giving.

15
DUTY AND CHARITY II
  • But on Singers principle of prevention there is
    something wrong with not giving, and giving is
    now a duty and not an instance of charity.
  • A persons spending money on things which she
    does not need rather than giving it to help
    prevent something bad from happening cannot be
    justified, and is immoral on Singers principle.
  • We have a duty to give money away for a good
    cause when we do not need it for ourselves or our
    family.

16
CHALLENGES TO SINGER
  • Some people might object to Singers point of
    view by saying that it is too radical, that we do
    not think about morality the way he maintains
    that we should. For instance, we do not condemn
    those people who do not give money to help
    prevent something bad.
  • But Singer says that whether we do or do not
    judge people in this way has nothing to do with
    the legitimacy of his moral principle that we
    ought to prevent something bad from happening
    which we can prevent without sacrificing
    something of comparable moral importance, and so
    is not really an objection to it.
  • Someone else might object that, since we are all
    self-interested to some degree, very few people
    will be doing all that they ought to do to
    prevent bad things from happening to others.
  • But Singer says, even if this is true, that this
    is not an argument against his principle.

17
APPLICATION OF THE PRINCIPLE OF PREVENTION I
  • Just how much money should we all be giving away
    to prevent bad things from happening?
  • For Singer, we ought to give away as much as we
    can before we would begin to suffer ourselves, or
    before we cause the bad condition for ourselves
    through our giving that our giving is designed to
    eliminate for others.
  • Thus we do not want to cause in ourselves and our
    dependents the suffering which we are trying to
    help others avoid.

18
APPLICATION OF THE PRINCIPLE OF PREVENTION II
  • Singer says that each person should give until
    she reaches the point of marginal utility. This
    is the point at which giving away more money
    would result in the same kind of suffering for
    you and your dependents that the giving is
    designed to prevent in others.
  • Singers principle of prevention - the principle
    which says that we ought to prevent from
    happening something bad which we can prevent
    unless we would sacrifice something of a
    comparable moral significance - seems to require
    our giving to help others until we reach the
    level of marginal utility.

19
QUESTIONS FOR SINGER
  • If we balk at this, what might be the reasons?
    Egoism? Partiality for some people over others?
  • If we feel no duty to hold to Singers principle
    why might that be? Could we feel that, by
    investing money in ourselves and our dependents,
    we might be better improving the world than by
    giving our money away?
  • Should we give until we reach the level of
    marginal utility if our musically gifted daughter
    wants a new piano? If our athletic son wants to
    go to summer basketball camp? If my wife is
    dying of cancer and wants to take a last trip to
    Europe?

20
A MORE MODERATE VERSION OF THE PRINCIPLE OF
PREVENTION
  • Singer also has a more moderate version of his
    principle, and that is that we give away money to
    help others, but only if in doing so we sacrifice
    nothing of moral significance, and so need not
    give until we reach the level of marginal
    utility.
  • Some people might think that the more moderate
    version is preferable, since they might think
    that it is bad for a person to reduce himself and
    his family to the level of marginal utility.
  • Singer prefers the strong version, but he says
    that even the moderate version would radically
    change things, and might cause a consumer society
    like ours to be radically affected, and perhaps
    even to disappear.

21
CONSUMER SOCIETIES
  • The effect of even the moderate version of the
    principle of prevention would have a great impact
    on consumer societies such as ours. This effect
    would cause the consumer society to slow down
    and perhaps disappear entirely.
  • The disappearance of a consumer society, which
    includes spending money on trivia rather than
    giving to famine relief would be a good thing,
    according to Singer.
  • It would be good because the values of a consumer
    society - buy yourself a life - have had a
    distorting effect on the goals and purposes of
    its members.

22
PRUDENCE IN GIVING
  • Having said what he says about consumer
    societies, Singer nevertheless recognizes that we
    would have to consider carefully how much it
    would be intelligent to give away as a percentage
    of our Gross National Product (the total output
    of a nations goods and services for a period of
    time, usually a year).
  • This is because, if we gave away too great a
    percentage of the GNP, then it might slow down
    the economy so much that we end up giving away
    less than we would have if we had given a smaller
    percentage.

23
THE IMPACT OF PHILOSOPHERS ON LIFE
  • Ending starvation is something important which
    Singer thinks philosophers can help to do.
  • And their assistance can come in the form of
    showing, as Singer himself attempts to show in
    this article, that we have an obligation to
    prevent misery and to help others when it is
    within our power to do so.
  • Accordingly Singer says that people ought to give
    money to help others that they themselves do not
    need in order to live decent lives.

24
World Hunger and Moral Obligation the Case
Against Singer
John Arthur
25
NORMAL ASSUMPTIONS ABOUT OUR MORAL OBLIGATIONS
  • Arthur writes from the perspective of those of us
    who live in wealthy industrial nations and have
    more than many others in other parts of the
    world.
  • And he says that such people normally think that
    our money is ours to do with what we please.
    This is because we earned it, and so feel that we
    are under no obligation to give whatever we do
    not need to someone else, especially to someone
    we have never met in some other part of the
    world.

26
SINGERS DISAGREEMENT WITH THIS
  • This is what Singer thinks is wrong.
  • Singer thinks that we are being immoral if we do
    not help those who could benefit from our help by
    simply doing without things which we and our
    family do not need.
  • For Singer, it is morally wrong for us not to
    prevent an evil like starvation if we have the
    means to do it.

27
SINGERS BASIC PRINCIPLES
  • Recall that Singer says that we have a moral
    obligation to help others who are suffering due
    to two basic principles
  • 1. Suffering and dying from lack of food,
    shelter and medical care are bad.
  • 2. We should prevent bad things from happening
    to others which it is in our power to prevent
    when doing so will not cause us to sacrifice
    anything of comparable moral significance.
  • This second principle I have called the
    principle of prevention, and Arthur calls the
    greater moral evil rule.

28
APPLICATION OF THE SECOND PRINCIPLE I
  • The second principle applied to world hunger
    means that we ought to give away money until we
    reach the level of marginal utility, or until we
    reach the level at which further giving will, or
    could, cause a comparable evil to happen to us or
    to those who depend on us.
  • To give beyond the point of marginal utility
    would mean that we would sacrifice something of
    comparable moral significance, such as our own
    health, or the health of those, such as our
    children, who depend on us, in order to help the
    people we are trying to help.

29
APPLICATION OF THE SECOND PRINCIPLE II
  • Arthur says that Singers greater moral evil rule
    means that people are entitled to keep their
    surplus earnings if there is no way for them to
    prevent a greater evil by giving them away.
  • Although he does not say so, the world being full
    of problems which money can be used to solve, it
    must be recognized that people would also be
    morally entitled to all of their earnings if no
    malady existed which could be removed by giving
    their surplus earnings to aid in its removal.

30
APPLICATION OF THE SECOND PRINCIPLE III
  • Arthur says that the greater moral evil rule
    would suggest that, if we spend money on
    ourselves for something which we do not need,
    then we are treating our own special interests as
    being more important than a persons life.
  • And most people would think that a persons life
    is more important than a trip to Cancun or a new
    car if the old one still runs.

31
MORAL EQUALITY I
  • Arthur points out that we have a sense of moral
    equality as part of our moral code. Thus if I am
    in pain and you are in pain, our moral equality
    means that my pain is not more important to
    remove than yours. It further indicates that, if
    I am happy and you are happy, then it is not more
    important that my happiness continue than yours.
  • The principle of moral equality means then that
    like amounts of suffering (or happiness) are of
    equal significance, no matter who is experiencing
    them.

32
MORAL EQUALITY II
  • Moral equality is taken by many to be an
    objective principle which is true for all.
    Accordingly, no one has a unique status in this
    regard, and so your pain is just as evil as the
    presidents and your happiness just as important
    as his.
  • Arthur also recognizes that our sense of moral
    equality means that we ought to give equal
    consideration to needs which are equally serious.
    And this means that removing your hunger is as
    important as removing mine.
  • This then seems to lead to Singers greater moral
    evil rule that we ought to help eliminate those
    bad things from happening to people when it would
    not cause us to experience something of similar
    badness.

33
MORAL EQUALITY III
  • Arthur Equality, in the sense of giving equal
    consideration to equally serious needs, is part
    of our moral code.
  • Arthur And so we are led, quite rightly I
    think, to the conclusion that we should prevent
    harm to others if in doing so we do not sacrifice
    anything of comparable moral importance.
  • However, Arthur says there is also another side
    to the coin which is of moral significance, one
    which Singer ignores . . . the notion of
    entitlements.

34
ENTITLEMENTS AND THE GREATER MORAL EVIL RULE I
  • Generally, an entitlement is something to which
    we are entitled, and to say that a person is
    entitled to something means that he or she has a
    right or claim to that thing. For instance, we
    are entitled to our eyes, our ears, our legs, our
    organs, and so forth.
  • Entitlements are divided into rights and desert,
    and where a right may or may not be a natural
    right, and desert is just reward or punishment.
  • For Arthur, a problem with Singers greater moral
    evil - prevent what evil it is in your power to
    prevent without your sacrificing anything of
    comparable moral significance - is that it would
    seem to demand that we do things like give an eye
    or a kidney to a stranger.

35
ENTITLEMENTS AND THE GREATER MORAL EVIL RULE II
  • A person can live with one kidney or one eye, and
    he would only be sacrificing something of
    comparable moral significance - his life - if he
    gave both of his kidneys to someone who has none,
    and he would only be sacrificing something of
    comparable moral significance - his sight - if he
    gave both of his eyes to a blind person.
  • Since we can live with one kidney and see with
    one eye, it looks to Arthur that, according to
    Singers principle of prevention, we are
    obligated to give an eye or a kidney to someone
    who needs them if we will be no worse off than
    when we had two of each.

36
NATURAL RIGHTS I
  • Singer might respond here that each of us has a
    natural right to our organs, and that a second
    organ is not to be viewed as a surplus item to be
    given away like additional money.
  • A natural right is a moral right which is said to
    belong to humans by nature, or to the kind of
    being called human being in virtue of being a
    human being, and so does not rest on custom or
    convention, but on self-evident principles or
    fundamental laws of reason.
  • Thus, for Thomas Hobbes, man has a natural right
    to life for John Locke, life, liberty, and
    property are natural rights and, in the
    Declaration of Independence, Thomas Jefferson
    names life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness
    as natural rights.

37
NATURAL RIGHTS II
  • Jeremy Bentham was opposed to the notion of
    natural rights and called them nonsense on
    stilts. There are no rights as such within
    nature or guaranteed by nature as opposed to
    rights which are created by men in the form of
    laws. Thus there is nothing but custom and
    convention.
  • The notion of self-evidence (mentioned above in
    relation to the notion of natural rights) is
    difficult to evaluate and is subject to change.
    Also, as what is reasonable to one thinker may
    not be reasonable to another, there may be a
    problem in resting a natural right on reason.

38
NATURAL RIGHTS III
  • Still, it may be hard not to think of some rights
    as natural, like the Kantian right to be treated
    as an end in oneself. That is, this would be
    considered to be a natural right since it is
    either self-evident or a fundamental law of
    reason, and that it is not merely arrived at by
    convention.
  • Singer might say that each of us has a natural
    right to our organs, and that a second organ is
    not to be viewed as a surplus item to be given
    away like additional money.
  • In addition, it might be noted that money and
    organs are not quite the same. What if we lose
    the second eye or kidney? We do not have the
    power to make another, but we do have the power
    usually to make more money as we have in the
    past.

39
NATURAL RIGHTS IV
  • Singer might also say that we have an obligation
    in dying to give our undamaged organs to anyone
    who needs them, but not while we are alive.
  • Arthur recognizes that a basic right to our own
    body parts is part of our moral code. Thus it
    is our body rather than someone elses, and we
    are not obligated to give up a second organ while
    living, although we may if we choose.
  • Arthur To sacrifice a kidney for a stranger is
    to do more than is required, its heroic.

40
NEGATIVE RIGHTS
  • Arthur notes that moral rights are normally
    divided into negative rights and positive rights.
  • Negative rights are rights of noninterference.
    We have the right not to be interfered with in
    certain ways, and since we are talking about the
    right not to be interfered with, the right is
    called negative.
  • For instance, we have the negative right not to
    be harmed or killed by another, not to have our
    property taken, not to have our privacy breached,
    etc.

41
POSITIVE RIGHTS
  • Whereas negative rights are rights of
    noninterference, positive rights are rights of
    recipience.
  • For instance, you have a positive right to be
    paid by your employer - to receive money - since
    he has agreed to pay you for work performed. And
    you have a positive right to receive a degree
    from the university for completing you degree
    requirements, since this is what the school
    promises to give you in exchange for money and
    academic work.

42
POSITIVE AND NEGATIVE RIGHTS I
  • Negative rights are natural. What natural rights
    you have depends on what kind of being you are.
    Thus human beings have a natural right to their
    bodies but cows do not, at least in our culture.
  • This is an example of how biology makes a
    difference to morality, which is an important
    issues in such topics in applied ethics as
    abortion and animal rights.
  • Positive rights are not natural. Instead, they
    depend on non-natural things like agreements made
    in good faith between people.

43
POSITIVE AND NEGATIVE RIGHTS II
  • Does a stranger in need typically have either a
    positive (contractual or agreed to by different
    people) or negative right (natural, depending on
    what kind of being you are) to be helped by
    another?
  • Arthur says no. Such a right, if it existed,
    would be positive. However, positive rights
    depend on contracts or promises made between
    people, and no such agreement has been entered
    into between us and a stranger in need.

44
POSITIVE AND NEGATIVE RIGHTS III
  • But while Arthur says that moral rights are
    factors to be considered in what we owe or do not
    owe to others, he also says that it is not the
    only thing which needs to be considered, and he
    recognizes that our moral code expects us to help
    someone in need in addition to respecting
    positive and negative rights.
  • What Arthur wants to emphasize, against Singer,
    is that we are entitled to invoke our own rights
    as justification for not giving to distant
    strangers or when the cost to us is substantial,
    as when we give up an eye or kidney.

45
POSITIVE AND NEGATIVE DESERT
  • In addition to being entitled to positive and
    negative rights, humans are entitled to desert -
    just reward, which is positive, or just
    punishment, which is negative.
  • An example of a positive desert - something which
    I deserve - is the money which I earn from
    working, some of which may be more than I need.
  • I am entitled to the reward of my hard work, but
    are you? If I earn more than you do because I
    work hard and you do nothing, am I obligated to
    give some of my extra money to you when you have
    done nothing to earn it?
  • Deserved punishment for a crime is an example of
    a negative desert.

46
THE GREATER MORAL EVIL PRINCIPLE AND ENTITLEMENTS
I
  • Arthur says that our moral code considers both
    Singers greater moral evil principle and
    entitlements.
  • The greater moral evil principle emphasizes human
    equality. This means that everyones suffering
    is equally bad, and everyones happiness is
    equally good.
  • The importance of entitlements means that we are
    not just our brothers keeper - where this
    extends perhaps to all humanity - but we are
    entitled to consider our own interests in certain
    respects.

47
THE GREATER MORAL EVIL PRINCIPLE AND ENTITLEMENTS
II
  • The greater moral evil principle also emphasizes
    impartiality.
  • It says to look objectively at the consequences
    of our actions, and in looking at the
    consequences of our actions looks to the future.
  • When we look at our entitlements our attention
    is directed to the past, since whether we have a
    right to something depends on how we came to
    possess them.
  • For instance, we came to the right to our eyes in
    the past since our negative natural right to them
    came with our birth, which occurred in the past,
    and our non-natural positive right to receive a
    degree is backward looking since we did the
    course work to earn it in the past.

48
DESERT AND THE PAST
  • Arthur points out that desert, like rights, is
    also backward-looking.
  • A positive desert - like being given an Olympic
    medal - looks to the past for what we did to earn
    the medal - beating everyone in the 100 meter
    dash.
  • A negative desert - like being sentenced to 10
    years in jail - looks to the past for what we did
    to deserve this punishment - like robbing a bank

49
PRINCIPLES OF COMMON MORALITY
  • Arthur Our commonly shared morality requires
    that we ignore neither consequences nor
    entitlements, neither the future results of our
    actions nor relevant events in the past.
  • Arthur also says that our common moral code
    encourages people to help others in need,
    especially when its a friend or someone we are
    close to geographically, and when the cost is not
    significant.
  • But Arthur also notes that our moral code gives
    weight to rights and desert, so that we are not
    usually obligated to give to strangers.

50
PROXIMITY AND MORALITY
  • Arthur says that charity is encouraged by our
    common morality, especially helping our local
    needy before those in a distant country.
  • Why do we tend to want to help those who are
    closest to us? Is it because, in the case of
    friendship, we act out of feelings which we do
    not have for strangers? And is it because, in
    the case of those nearest to us, that we can see
    the results of our help, and think that they
    would be more able to return the favor to us than
    a distant person?

51
REFORMING COMMON MORALITY I
  • Since this is how our moral code works, Singer
    can be seen to defend the idea of reforming our
    moral code, and making it so that we should feel
    obligated to help those in need, including
    strangers, and to give up the idea that we are
    entitled to money which we dont need.
  • Arthur recognizes that moral rules change, and
    that we have to allow for the possibility of
    moral change, especially replacing inferior
    moral laws with better ones.
  • Should we then see that our notion of
    entitlements is an inferior part of our current
    moral code?

52
REFORMING COMMON MORALITY II
  • That is what Singer would say.
  • But Arthur notes that the notion of entitlements
    is an important part of our moral code, and that
    entitlements have to do with fairness, justice,
    and respect.
  • Thus we are entitled to a good grade if we earn
    it, and if we earn it but are not given it, then
    that is unfair.

53
REFORMING COMMON MORALITY III
  • We are entitled to punish a criminal for what he
    did - a negative desert - and not to punish
    someone for a wrongdoing would not be just.
  • And we are entitled to the natural negative right
    of our bodies, and our privacy, and not to
    recognize these is not to respect persons.
  • Arthur thinks these things should be recognized
    by morality as important as the equality of
    persons.

54
REFORMING COMMON MORALITY IV
  • Arthur says that he may not be able to convince
    someone who does not think this way, someone who
    wonders why justice, fairness, and respect for
    persons, as they concern entitlements, are more
    important than equality and the obligation to
    help strangers.
  • So he and Singer may have reached a point where
    they simply disagree with one another.

55
MORALITY AND PRACTICALITY I
  • Arthur says that it is extremely important for
    ethicists to recognize that the moral code it is
    rational for us to support must be practical it
    must actually work.
  • Accordingly, all the ethical theory in the world
    is not worth a hill of beans unless it
    facilitates human interaction and helps to
    produce results which people want.
  • Further, for a moral code to be practical most
    people must support it.

56
MORALITY AND PRACTICALITY II
  • It is also important for moral theory to
    recognize the nature and limitations of human
    beings.
  • Ethics should not assume, for instance, that
    people are less selfish than they are. It should
    instead be realistic about the degree of our
    self-interest.
  • Arthur Rules that would work only for angels
    are not the ones it is rational to support for
    humans.

57
MORALITY, RATIONALITY, AND KNOWLEDGE
  • A moral code should also not assume too much
    about our rationality - that we are more
    objective than in fact we are.
  • We tend to lose the objectivity which we expect
    of others when we consider our own case and our
    own interests. Countries do this too, a nations
    diplomacy is often guided by what it is in the
    interests of that nation to pursue.
  • And we have to recognize that we do not have all
    the facts about what would make for a better
    moral situation. We are not in the position of
    an ideal observer with ideal knowledge, but we
    often must work with only our limited knowledge
    from our limited perspective, and we make
    mistakes.

58
ARTHURS CONCLUSIONS I
  • For Arthur as opposed to Singer, it is reasonable
    to expect a person to help others only when
    there is no substantial cost to themselves, that
    is, when what they are sacrificing would not mean
    significant reduction in their own or their
    familys level of happiness. (His italics.)
  • But someone such as Singer might maintain that we
    need some additional considerations here. For
    instance, what if losing a billion dollars would
    significantly reduce the happiness of Bill Gates
    at the same time that it could prevent the
    starvation of thousands? He still has 39 billion
    left.

59
ARTHURS CONCLUSIONS II
  • For Arthur, a persons entitlements can outweigh
    another persons need. And this would be the
    case when sacrificing the entitlement, like
    earned money, for the welfare of another led to
    the persons unhappiness.
  • But Arthur also says that, if what is at stake
    is trivial, . . . then an ideal moral code would
    not allow rights to override the greater evil
    which can be prevented.
  • Is Gates giving up a billion dollars trivial
    since he is still left with the majority of his
    net worth?

60
ARTHURS CONCLUSIONS III
  • Arthur thinks that our current moral code
    reflects the thinking that it is reasonable to
    expect one person to help another only when there
    is no substantial cost to the person who is
    helping the other.
  • In our common morality we tend to blame people
    who are selfish and do not help others when doing
    so would be a small inconvenience to them, at the
    same time that we do not expect people to make
    large sacrifices to help distant strangers.
  • Accordingly, Arthur suggests that an ideal moral
    code may not be that much different from our own
    an ideal code which recognized human nature and
    human intelligence.
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com