Kripke: Identity and necessity - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 41
About This Presentation
Title:

Kripke: Identity and necessity

Description:

He may quit his job tomorrow; in fact, he might have been a car mechanic from ... Another interesting case. It is necessary that Mark Twain is Samuel Clemens. ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:609
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 42
Provided by: jakab1
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: Kripke: Identity and necessity


1
Kripke Identity and necessity
  • Nyelv és elme, 2007 tavasz
  • Jakab Zoltán

2
Are there contingent identity statements?
  • Are there contingent identity statements?
  • Senses of identity
  • 1. Quantitative one and the same (my wedding
    ring)
  • 2. Qualitative exactly similar (two brand-new,
    grey two-stroke Trabant 601s)
  • 3. Personal identity, in the psychological sense
    (largely irrelevant in this context who am I,
    what kind of person, etc.)
  • 4. What needs to be distinguished from 1. role
    filling. (John is a teacher. Contrast Mary
    Katharine Horony is Big Nose Kate) These cases
    are treated differently.

Big Nose Kate (1850-1940)
Tombstone, Arizona
3
An argument
  • (1) Substitutivity of identity
  • ?x?y(xy) ? (F(x)? F(y))
  • (2) Necessity of self-identity
  • ?x ? (xx) ? means necessarily
  • (This is not an uncontroversial notion, but we
    accept it now.)
  • Substitute (2) in (1)
  • (3) ?x?y(xy) ? (? (xx) ? ? (xy))
  • that is (just to see the parallel)
  • ?x?y(xy) ? (necessarily_identical_to_x(x) ?
  • necessarily_identical_to_x(y))

4
  • But we can simplify (3), because the antecedent
    of the second conditional ? (xx) is
    satisfied for each and every entity x. So we get
  • (4) ?x?y(xy) ? ? (xy)
  • So, (4) says if two entities x and y are
    quantitatively identical, then they are
    necessarily quantitatively identical. (Worries
    could be raised about this conclusion due to (2),
    but if (2) is accepted, then the conclusion
    follows by logic.)
  • Of course Nothing remotely similar is true of
    qualitative identity (the Trabants) nor of role
    filling (If John is a teacher, it does not follow
    that he is a teacher necessarily. He may quit his
    job tomorrow in fact, he might have been a car
    mechanic from the start.)

5
The truth of ?x ? (xx)
  • A worry can be raised about non-existent objects
    are they necessarily self-identical?
  • Set this aside, says Kripke, and restrict the
    application of necessarily to cases where the
    objects mentioned exist.
  • There are other worries that well address later.
  • Next issue de re de dicto modality. ? This
    needs a digression

6
De re and de dicto modality
  • Remember de re means concerning the thing.
  • De re modality modal terms apply to the
    possession of an attribute by an object
  • De dicto modality modal terms apply to a
    statement or proposition. (concerning the
    proposition)
  • Two examples follow.

7
  • The number of gospels necessarily exceeds three.
  • De dicto reading
  • The statement that the number of the gospels
    exceeds three is necessary
  • necessarilythe x x numbers the gospels(xgt3)
  • FALSE there are in fact four gospels, but that
    is not necessarily so.
  • De re reading the number of the gospels (i.e.,
    the number four, the thing itself) necessarily
    exceeds three.
  • the x x numbers the gospels necessarily(xgt3)
  • TRUE (4gt3 is necessary)

8
  • If I am sitting, then I am necessarily not
    standing.
  • De dicto reading the statement that if someone
    is sitting then she is not standing is a
    necessary one, so on de dicto reading, the above
    sentence is TRUE.
  • This is because sitting and standing are
    disjunctively related sitting applies to a
    state of the body to which standing does not
    apply. That is, if thats how we use our words,
    then the above statement cannot be but true. (De
    dicto) necessity depends on how we describe the
    world.
  • De re reading if I am sitting, then it is
    necessary that I am not standing. This is FALSE.
    It is a property of me that I am sitting at a
    given time, but not a necessary property. I could
    have been standing at that time.

9
De re modality is the more controversial idea.
  • Can a things possession of its properties be
    regarded necessary? This issue divides
    philosophers.
  • E.g., Quine rejected de re modality, and accepted
    only the de dicto reading. On the de dicto
    interpretation only statements or propositions
    are said to be necessary.
  • Kripke, on the other hand, accepted de re
    modality. This leads to essentialism (the theory
    of natural kinds).

10
Natural kinds
  • Natural kinds (water, gold, electron,
    electromagnetic field, etc.) have essential and
    contingent attributes.
  • For instance, water is essentially H2O. If that
    stuff (e.g., the one which comes from faucets)
    did not have the chemical structure H2O, then it
    would not/could not be what it is.
  • On the contrary, temperature is a contingent
    property of water.
  • Underlying this notion is the idea of
    metaphysical realism the world is the way it is
    (nature has its joints) independently of how we
    conceive of it.

11
Natural kinds continued
  • Realist intuition It is a mind-independent fact,
    for instance, that two elephants are more similar
    to one another than an elephant to a butterfly.
  • Two intuitively plausible ideas (1) categories
    in the world are independent of our conceptions
    of them, (2) some properties play more important
    role than others in distinguishing objective
    categories from each other. Categories or types
    have essential properties (and contingent ones).
    Being essential, of course, is category-relative.

12
  • For example, take two samples of liquid, if both
    have the chemical composition H2O, then they are
    of the same (chemical) kind, regardless of the
    fact that one has the temperature 2 ?C, and the
    other 90 ?C. So, chemical composition is an
    essential property it outlines categories, or
    natural kinds, in nature. However, temperature is
    also a natural kind (MKE of molecules), or so it
    is assumed by Kripke. So a bottle of water and a
    bottle of alcohol can have the same temperature
    at a time, and be in the same objective category
    in that respect. Finally, there are properties
    that are not really essential for any category
    i.e., ones that do not outline natural kinds. An
    example is, being alive from t1 to t2. Another
    example of such properties is mind-dependent
    attributes, like being red. All and only red
    objects do not have anything in common
    mind-independently all they have in common is
    that they look red to us.
  • Some think very few properties are essential in
    the sense of corresponding to natural kinds,
    namely only fundamental physical properties.
    Others are inclined to say, being a natural kind
    is a matter of degree.

13
De re and de dicto identity statements.
  • Next example
  • The first person in space might have been Alan
    Shepard.
  • De dicto reading
  • Possiblythe x 1st_person_in_space(x)(xAlan
    Shepard)
  • It says that there is some counterfactual state
    of affairs in which A.S. was the first person
    into space. TRUE
  • De re
  • the x 1st_person_in_space(x)possibly(xAlan
    Shepard)
  • This says that the person who happened to be the
    first into space (i.e., Gagarin) is such that
    there is some conterfactual state of affairs in
    which he is (identical with) A.S. FALSE.

14
Another interesting case
  • It is necessary that Mark Twain is Samuel
    Clemens.
  • First, note that since there is no description in
    this sentence, just names, scope ambiguity of the
    sort shown above is missing too.
  • In de re reading, this is true. The person
    referred to by Mark Twain is such that he is
    necessarily identical with the person referred to
    by Samuel Clemens.
  • In de dicto reading, however, it is also true.
    Given how we use these proper names (considering
    also that, for Kripke, names are rigid
    designators), the statement Mark Twain is Samuel
    Clemens cannot be false.
  • This however, raises an interesting problem

15
There is a counterfactual possible world
  • in which, hm, a numerically distinct person has
    the name Mark Twain, whereas Samuel Clemens
    referred to the very same person as it does in
    the actual world. That is

Actual world
Counterfactual world (W2)
- Arrows indicate reference - Transparency
assumed (Kripke)
Samuel Clemens
Samuel Clemens
Mark Twain
Mark Twain
Problem If Necessarily, Mark Twain is Samuel
Clemens is true both de re and de dicto, then
what reading expresses the above possibility,
namely that in W2, Mark Twain is Samuel Clemens
is apparently false, so this sentence cannot be
necessary after all.
16
Solution
  • One of the names should be swapped for a
    description, say
  • The person called Mark Twain in W2
  • Now of course, the sentence
  • The person called Mark Twain in W2 Samuel
    Clemens
  • is false, and this will be our way to interpret
    the utterances in W2 of the sentence Mark Twain
    is Samuel Clemens which denizens of W2 take to
    be false.
  • Another way to put the point Mark Twain in our
    world and in W2 is not the same name (they need
    to be indexed apart, e.g., Mark TwainA, Mark
    TwainW2), because their reference differs. Now
    Mark TwainA is Samuel Clemens remains true (and
    necessary) whereas Mark TwainW2 is Samuel
    Clemens will be necessarily false.

17
If there are two descriptions in a sentence, then
there are three readings of the modal form
  • Kripkes example Necessarily, the inventor of
    the bifocals is Americas first Postmaster
    General.
  • 1. De dicto reading it says that the proposition
    The inventor of the bifocals is the first
    Postmaster General of the US is necessary.
    (I.e., whoever filled one role filled the other
    by necessity.) FALSE
  • 2. Intermediate reading the guy who is the
    inventor of the bifocals is such that he
    necessarily filled the role of Americas First
    PG. FALSE.
  • 3. De re The guy who happened to invent the
    bifocals, and the guy who happened to be the
    first postmaster, are one and the same, therefore
    necessarily so. TRUE.

18
Quiz
  • Given the Russellian formalism of a sentence
    containing two definite descriptions, insert the
    necessary operator in three different places
    corresponding to the three readings on the
    previous slide.

19
Kripke on tagging (97-8)
  • Names simply refer, they do not describe their
    objects in any way (p97).
  • Here is Kripkes view on assigning names to
    objects
  • (i) Tagging can be made in all kinds of different
    ways.
  • (ii) It is a contingent fact that we tag heavenly
    bodies and other objects in this, rather than
    that, way.
  • (iii) However, once we in fact perform a given
    tagging (say, in the actual world) then the tags
    assigned will be description-independent rigid
    designators.
  • (iv) Plus, remember, numerical identity is
    necessary.
  • (v) What follows Identity statements using any
    pair of names that we please are necessary, if
    true.

20
Rigid designators
  • They presuppose transworld indentity, which is a
    problem notion (102-3).
  • Kripkes reply transparency (104). Venus in one
    and the same object in every possible world where
    it exists.
  • Transworld identity of properties is accepted as
    well this is even more crucial in comparing
    worlds.

21
Modes of truth
  • A priori (knowable without further experience,
    via reasoning1) vs. a posieriori (need further
    experience to decide2)
  • and
  • necessary vs. contingent
  • come apart.
  • NOTE a priori and a postariori are epistemic
    notions they have to do with our knowledge
  • Necessary vs. contingent are metaphysical notions
    they concern how the world is (independently of
    our knowledge) or how it might have been
    independently of thought
  • Recall modal facts!

22
Contingent a priori
  • The standard meter rod in Paris is one meter
    long.
  • We know a priori that whatever the length of the
    bar that is regarded as the meter standard, that
    length will be called one meter since the bar
    is used to set the standard. All this comes from
    convention.
  • BUT that length can vary in different worlds. It
    is not necessary that the bar used as the meter
    standard is of the same length in every possible
    world.

23
Quiz
  • Take this statement
  • Necessarily, the standard meter rod in Paris is
    one meter long.
  • What is its de re and de dicto reading? Which is
    true, and which is false?

24
A posteriori necessity
  • Knowledge of the essential properties of natural
    kinds belongs here. Pure reflection without
    empirical science would have never taught us that
    water is H2O.
  • Kripkes example the lectern (formal argument,
    p108) the self-identity of particulars is
    necessary

25
The wooden lectern
  • Morals drawn
  • (1) in order for something to be the very object
    it is, it has to be made of the same lump of
    material. (This wooden lectern could not have
    been made of ice) So quantitative identity of
    the material constituting a particular object is
    essential for the quantitative identity of the
    object itself.
  • (2) The necessity in question is a posteriori.

26
The self-identity of particulars
  • The Necessary identity of an object with itself
    is not an uncontroversial notion.
  • Part of this idea is, despite changes in its
    properties, the object remains the same. Mars was
    the same object millions of years ago, when it
    had lots of liquid water on its surface, for
    instance.
  • However

27
  • Theseuss ship type of objections does my bike
    become a different object gradually as its parts
    get replaced over the years?
  • If I have a hammer out of which I create a
    screwdriver i.e., out of the same chunk of
    material do I suddenly have a different object,
    or do I have the same object with slightly
    different properties?
  • The self-identity of human beings a human being
    at the age of 2, and at the age of 30, say, is
    constituted by a completely different chunk of
    matter, yet we want to say that she is one and
    the same person...
  • Kripkes theory requires a more complete account
    of indentity.

28
Back to Kripke
  • Claim Contingent identity statements involving
    names arise from misdescribing situations in
    various ways. Take
  • (5) Hesperus might not have been Phosphorus.
  • We might take this to involve descriptions, not
    proper names
  • (6) The heavenly body seen in the evening sky
    might not have been the heavenly body seen in the
    morning sky.
  • (6) is true, but it is misdescribes what was
    said in (5). (5) is a statement of identity
    between objects.

29
Rigidifying descriptions
  • The definite description the author of Hamlet
    picks out different people in different possible
    worlds.
  • But, the definite description the actual author
    of Hamlet picks out, in all worlds, the person
    who is the author of Hamlet in our world W.
    Shakespeare.
  • This is a rigidified description, which has its
    reference fixed it picks out the same person in
    every world, even in worlds where W.S. failed to
    author Hamlet.

30
Names and descriptions (111-2)
  • Even if we suppose that the reference of a name
    is fixed by a description, the name will not be
    synonymous with the description.
  • Instead, the name will refer rigidly to its
    object, even in worlds where the object does not
    satisfy the description by which it is picked out
    in the actual world.
  • Example water is the waterish stuff in this
    world not so in many other worlds. However, the
    word water refers to the kind of stuff which is
    our waterish stuff (namely H2O) in every possible
    world, even though we fixed its reference here by
    means of a contingent attribute.

31
On the identity of kinds.
  • Kripke Terms that refer to essential properties
    are rigid designators they designate the same
    property in every possible world.
  • Intuition behind
  • Water is H2O that kind of liquid in the glass
    is the very one to which the scientific
    characterization H2O applies. One and the same
    kind is designated by two different terms.
  • Temperature is MKE of molecules If you have
    molecular oscillation, thereby you have
    temperature and vice versa.

32
  • When we imagine that in another world W2 water is
    not H2O, what we imagine is that waterish stuff
    is not H2O. (Therefore the word water in that
    world is different in meaning from our word
    water there are two different words here,
    which need to be distinguished, say, by indexing
    (waterA, waterW2). This we can imagine
    (remember the Mark Twain case).
  • But, on pain of contradiction, we cannot imagine
    that H2O is not H2O, that some stuff has a
    particular essence and does not have it.

33
  • A number of philosophers have noted later that
    there is another thing what we can imagine
  • Suppose some scientists discover that chemical
    theory (or thermodynamics) has gone totally wrong
    because some chemists/physicists made a few
    severe errors in their exmeriments and
    theorizing. Thus, it turns out that, say, the
    periodic system of elements needs to be redrawn.
    As a consequence if this, we have no longer any
    reason to hold that water is H2O. Most plausibly,
    it turns out, water is some other kind, in the
    actual world, and in all other possible worlds as
    well.
  • Thus we can coherently imagine that Water is
    H2O is necessarily false, but not that it is
    contingently false.

34
Heat is not the mean kinetic energy of molecules
  • Another example of misdescription heat is
    identified by one of its contingent attributes,
    namely how it feels to us.
  • True, the same feeling might have been evoked by
    some other physical cause. Under this
    (mis)description, Heat might not have been MKE
    comes out true.
  • p114 the motion of molecules is rigid, says
    Kripke. At least this description picks out an
    attribute motion, or kinetic energy, of some
    particulars (of some molecules). Its like the
    deed of Shakespeare which made him famous.
  • the author of Hamlet picks out a particular
    that has some attribute (a contingent one). So
    there is a subtle disanalogy between these two
    uses of definite descriptions.

35
On the mind-body problem
  • The basic disanalogy
  • (i) heat might not have been MKE
  • (ii) Pain might not have been C-fiber firing
    (i.e., it might not have been identical with its
    actual neural correlate).
  • (i) is understood thus The kind of sensation we
    have on contacting warm/hot things might not have
    been caused by MKE, but rather, but something
    else.
  • (ii) cannot be understood this way

36
  • for (1) the way we feel it is essential for
    being in pain is cannot be pain if it does not
    hurt, nor can it hurt without it being pain,
    moreover (2) the corresponding brain state type
    is also picked out by an essential
    (physiological, biochemical) attribute.
  • Thus we have two rigid designators, and if they
    pick out the same thing in the actual world, then
    they do so in every possible world.

37
The whole argument, reconstructed
  • (1) There are two rigid designators two ways of
    picking out something by an essential property.
  • (2) We also have an identity statement between
    the two things picked out this is the
    materialist thesis. Pain is a brain state of some
    sort.
  • (3) Therefore (given the heat-MKE disanalogy) we
    should not be able to imagine that pain
    sensations could have existed without the
    corresponding brain state.
  • (4) But we can imagine that pain sensations could
    have existed without the corresponding brain
    state.
  • (5) Materialism at least the identity thesis
    is false.

38
Does this argument generalize to functionalism?
(notes on endnote 17)
  • We also seem to be able to imagine that someone
    is in a brain state that does occupy the
    appropriate causal role vis á vis stimuli and
    behavior (causes yelling, avoidance, etc.) yet it
    does not feel like pain. The same is suggested by
    the absent qualia (and the zombie) argument.
  • The conclusion of these arguments is the same as
    what is suggested by Kripke, namely that pain is
    not identical with either a physiological or a
    functional state.

39
How can we reply to this argument?
  • For instance, we can say the following.
  • What we can and do imagine, in Kripkean terms, is
    not that pain might not have been the
    brain/functional state it in fact is (i.e., that
    the identity is true in the actual world but
    false in some counterfactual possible worlds).
  • What we really imagine (and what we can
    coherently imagine according to Kripkes account)
    is that this theory of pain is actually false
    that the two rigid designators do not pick out
    the same thing in the actual world (and hence not
    in any possible world either).
  • That is, Kripkes theory is compatible with
    physicalism. (It had better be although D.
    Chalmers picks up the same line arguing that from
    epistemic premises we can reach dualist
    ontological conclusions.)

40
(No Transcript)
41
(No Transcript)
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com