Title: Lecture 6 Genetic discrimination
1Lecture 6Genetic discrimination
2Is everybody against genetic discrimination?
- The media often discuss genetic discrimination
(GD), typically with a critical attitude GD is
regularly condemned as being unfair, immoral - Did you ever hear anyone defending genetic
discrimination? - Do you remember ever reading the opinion that
genetic discrimination is a good thing and that
we should protect the right of genetic
discrimination? - Probably not. But why is there so much discussion
about an issue on which everyone agrees?
3The word discrimination
- In fact, some people do advocate genetic
discrimination, but not under that name. - The word discrimination has in itself a
distinctly negative overtone, especially when a
criterion of discrimination is explicitly
mentioned. - It is rare that the word has a positive meaning
e.g., a discriminating mind. - But when the word discrimination is linked with
a criterion of discrimination, the negative
message is directly implied.
4The word discrimination (cont.)
- To most people it would sound almost
self-contradictory to say They are
discriminating on the basis of Xbut this is
completely OK. - Why? It seems that discriminating on whatever
basis (height, age, race, genetic
characteristics) is automatically regarded as
wrong simply because the term discrimination on
the basis of X is only used to refer to the
practices regarded as improper. - If one did not object to X as a criterion of
selection, normally one would not describe the
practice as discrimination-on-the-basis-of-X
but rather as, say, selection-on-the-basis-of-X)
.
5A condemnatory definition of GD
- We define genetic discrimination as drawing a
distinction among individuals or groups plus an
element of either irrationality or social
unacceptability or both. (M. A. Rothstein M.
R. Anderlik, in Genetics in Medicine 2001, p.354) - When discrimination is defined in this way, the
term clearly has a negative connotation
genetic discrimination is a bad thing. (ibid.) - After a few pages
- There are good ethical reasons for preventing
genetic discrimination. (p.357)
6Bewitched by language?
- Imagine that someone presented the abortion
debate as being about whether murdering babies
should be allowed. - Would the pro-choice side be happy with this?
- General advice to avoid begging the question,
show that a practice deserves to be condemned
before you describe it in condemning terms. - With genetic discrimination, it is too late to
change the terminology. But we should be aware of
the bias built into the phrase. - Most importantly, we should resist the temptation
to regard GD as morally wrong before a convincing
argument is produced for condemnation.
7What (if anything) is wrong with GD?
- No one should be denied health insurance because
of predispositions found in their DNA. (F. C.
Collins J. D. Watson, in Science, 31/10/2003) - Any form of discrimination against a person on
grounds of his or her genetic heritage is
prohibited. (The Council of Europes Convention
on Human Rights and Biomedicine, 1997) - Any discrimination based on any ground such as
genetic features shall be prohibited. (The EUs
Charter of Fundamental Rights, 2000) - For a long time people were denied insurance on a
mere suspicion about what might be found in their
DNA, and no one was particularly bothered about
that!
8Family history vs. genetic tests
- Two sources of genetic information, two very
different reactions. Why? - Knowledge about genetic predispositions that
comes from family history is typically indirect,
probabilistic and quite limited. - Knowledge obtained through genetic tests is
direct, certain and potentially comprehensive. - It is unclear how these differences could be
relevant for morally opposite reactions to these
two cases. - Kitcher (1996) suggests that using the family
history information is also ethically problematic
but that it was tolerated just because of its
narrow scope.
9Genetic tests a bigger threat?
- There is a lot of public nervousness and sense of
urgency in dealing with genetic discrimination. - Many countries and most U.S. states have laws
against genetic discrimination. - There is a push for federal legislation as well.
- The House of Representatives needs to approve
the Genetic Nondiscrimination Act of 2003 as soon
as possible. (Collins Watson, Science 2003) - Genetic discrimination and health insurance an
urgent need for reform, Science 1995. - Before it's too late - addressing fear of
genetic information, Science 2002.
10How bad is the situation already?
- Once all of this starts to really get going, and
insurance companies begin demanding information
on you from this and that sort of genetic test,
some people are going to find that they can't get
the insurance they need. Whenever I give talks on
this I make this point, and invariably one or two
people come up to me afterward and say, "I know
somebody who..." and tells me a sad story about
the system, about something like this that is
happening already. People are finding that
because of the genetic tests that they have been
asked to take or that they actually have taken,
their insurance is now over or changes
drastically. (Kitcher 2001)
11I know somebody who
- There are almost no well-documented cases of
health insurers asking for, or using, genetic
test results in their underwriting decisions.
(Hall Rich, AJHG, 2000) - What emerges from those conversations is that
the journalists are desperate to find, but have
great difficulty in finding, citizens who will
claim that they were victims of genetic
discrimination. (Reilly 1999) - I investigated whether any consumers had sued
insurers alleging discriminatory practices in
underwriting on the basis of genetic information.
I found not a single case. (ibid.)
12The matter of definition?
- The inability to document GD is sometimes
attributed to a too narrow definition of GD. - It is objected that Hall Rich take into account
only cases in which illness was in no manner
manifested yet (Lemke 2005). - Two alternative definitions (a) includes cases
where the persons in question have already fallen
ill, and (b) where the symptoms of the illness
are very mild or do not constitute disability. - The first (too narrow) definition is obviously
preferable here. After all, health insurance is
insurance against future illness!
13How to deal with the unjustified fear?
- If there is so much public alarm in connection
with a practice that seems to be infrequent or
even largely non-existent, what is the most
reasonable response? - Are unfounded public fears best treated by
passing stricter laws against these mostly
fanciful threats? - Perhaps not.
- Consider an analogous situation would those
living in terror of alien abductions be really
reassured if a new federal law were introduced
with harsh penalties for keeping people inside
flying saucers against their will? - Or would this just increase their paranoia?
14Genetic injustice?
- It seems to me obvious enough that the potential
misuse of genetic information by insurers is
troublesome first and foremost because it is
unfair that some people are worse off than others
due to bad genetic luck. Justine Burley - Whereas individuals can exercise choices about
whether to smoke, how much exercise they get, and
how much fat is in their diets, they cannot
change the contents of their genes. To make
employment or insurance decisions on the basis of
genetic characteristics determined at the moment
of conception is to discard cherished beliefs in
justice and equality. The Council of Responsible
Genetics
15Genetic advantage
- In many cases we tolerate differential rewards
that depend on genetic (undeserved!)
characteristics (intelligence, musical or
athletic ability, etc.). - Introducing social compensation for those unlucky
in the genetic lottery is a very radical
political idea. - Even if it is defensible, the argument would
transcend the discussion of genetic
discrimination.
G
(T)
A Genetic discrimination direct
(G)
T
A Genetic discrimination indirect
16Adverse selection
- Genetic privacy ? an epistemic asymmetry (between
insurers and their customers). - Under the regime of genetic privacy, people who
learn that they are at increased risk of illness
could hide this information from insurers, and
buy extensive health or life insurance for a low
price. - As a result, insurance companies would face
increased costs, and to stay in business, they
would have to respond by raising the standard
premium. - This would in turn make many healthy people leave
the insurance market, which would push the
premiums even higher, which would
17Trade-off
- Adverse selection is not a serious threat yet.
- But neither is the invasion of genetic privacy.
- The two are connected if the epistemic asymmetry
puts a subject at a significant advantage
vis-Ã -vis the insurer, then (and only then) there
will be two simultaneous effects - (a) a danger of adverse selection, and, because
of that, - (b) the insurers attempt to get genetic
information. - So, the protection of genetic privacy is either
unnecessary or has both effects (positive and
negative). - Will protecting privacy do more good or bad?
18The dilemma of genetic tests
- Take a person who is at increased risk for a
certain disease because of a family history of
that disease. - The dilemma if a genetic test is conducted,
should the information about the result be
private? - Yes, because its personal.
- No, because the result affects the insurance
company as well. - The Nuffield Council on Bioethics proposes a
compromise The information should be shared with
the insurance company, but the insurance premium
should not be raised if the test is positive.
19A hypothetical example
- A disease that costs an insurance company 50,000
- 200 people with family history and risk level of
0.05 - Not tested (20) pay additional 2,600
- Test positive (4) pay additional 50,000
- Test negative (76) pay the regular premium
20The same example the Nuffield scenario
- A disease that costs an insurance company 50,000
- 200 people with family history and risk level of
0.05 - Not tested (20) pay additional 2,600
- Test positive (4) pay additional 2,600
- Test negative (76) pay the regular premium
21Everyone will be uninsurable!
- Because of the work currently being done on the
human genome project, it is likely in the next
years that every one of us will have a
preexisting condition and be uninsurable.
(Hillary Clinton) - Insurance companies function by pooling the risk
for different groups, so when you start having
individuals who are getting tested for genetic
mutations, you cant really give insurance to
anyone because everyone will have some level of
risk. (Sujatha Byravan, President of the Council
for Responsible Genetics)
22Can genetic discrimination lead to racism?
- Since certain genes (including those for cystic
fibrosis, sickle cell anemia, thalassemia) are
more frequent in certain racial and ethnic
groups, or among people of certain provenance,
actuarial fairness can easily lead to thinly
disguised racial or ethnic discrimination. Onora
ONeill - A policy cannot be condemned as being racially
discriminatory just because it has different
impact on different racial groups. - The necessary component of condemnation must be
that there is an intention to harm these groups. - Actuarial fairness lacks this component.
23Genetic discrimination racist motivation?
- In the 1970s the Air Force Academy stopped
admitting people with the sickle-cell trait. - The sickle-cell trait is much more frequent among
blacks (around 8) than among whites. - The high incidence of sickle-cell trait in the
National Football League and the formation of an
exclusionary policy on the basis of flimsy
evidence very likely have a common explanation
In the United States the sickling allele, and
thus both sickle-cell trait and sickle-cell
anemia, is most prevalent among Americans of
African descent. Kitcher 1996
24Are genetic and racial discrimination similar?
- Just as we have addressed discrimination based
on race, gender, and age, we must now prevent
discrimination based on genetic information. (G.
W. Bush) - The problem with Bushs analogy is that we
condemn discrimination when it is based on an
irrelevant characteristic. - Rejecting a student because of race or gender is
unfair because gender and race are in themselves
irrelevant for academic ability. - But genetic characteristics may often be relevant
for insurance and employment purposes.