Title: Announcements
1Announcements
- For Thursday we are going to complete Searles
Minds, brains and programs the Chinese room
and get to Heidegger On Dasein and Anxiety - Tutorial Questions will be posted tomorrow night
2Nagel Continued The Nature of the Problem
- The First Person Standpoint vs. the Third Person
Standpoint - The Subjective vs. the Objective
- Being-for-us vs. Being-in-itself
- Phenomenological vs. the Representational
- The problem with reductionism the idea that
the mind smoothly reduces to the brain is going
to be to negotiate all these vs.
3Three Arguments
- (2) The Appearance/Reality Distinction
- Third Person Objective Representational point of
view the distinction makes sense - First Person Phenomenological Point of View the
distinction makes nonsense. Appearance is the
reality of conscious mental life - It is difficult to understand what could be
meant by the objective character of an
experience, apart from the particular point of
view from which its subject apprehends it. After
all, what would be
4Three Arguments
- (2) continued
- ..left of what it was like to be a bat if one
removed the viewpoint of the bat?(364) - We apply a reality/appearance distinction in
physical reductions. When we define heat as mean
molecular kinetic energy or colour as light
reflectances of a certain frequency we have in a
sense redefined heat and colour in such a manner
that no reference to subjective experience is
necessary.
5Three Arguments
- (2) continued
- The subjective experience is left unreduced. The
subjective experiences are carved off, so to
speak, from such a definition. Such experiences
are simply the appearances of heat or colour for
us while the underlying physical processes are
said to be its reality. Such moves are
inappropriate when we wish to understand
ourselves
- the subjective experience is left
6Three Arguments
- (2) continued
- The idea of moving from appearance to reality
seems to make no sense here (365) - By way of elucidating Nagels argument, consider
the following quote from Colin McGinn ( from The
Mysterious Flame, p.20-1) it is basically the
same argument. - The trouble with this reply think of Argument
B above is that there is no way to distinguish
mental and physical concepts without appealing
7Three Arguments
- to a distinction at the level of facts. What
makes the concept pain different from the concept
C-fiber firing is precisely that the two concepts
express distinct properties, so we cannot say
that these properties are identical. The
materialist is forced to introduce the idea of
two different appearances of the same fact, but
this notion of appearance itself depends upon
there being facts of appearance that cannot be
identified with brain facts. The appearance of
pain cannot be reduced..
8Three Arguments
- to C-fiber firing, just as the appearance of
water cannot be reduced to H2O. But appearances
are what the mind consists of. So the mind
cannot be reduced to the brain. - How something appears to us is what it means to
be conscious of it appearance with respect to
consciousness is the reality. Thus, to state
that a conscious state may appear to us in a
certain manner i.e., qualitative feels, belief
states while its reality is an underlying
physical process..
9Three Arguments
- not only misunderstands what is involved in
physical reductions a methodological mistake
but mistakes what consciousness itself is. - Lets relate this argument to last term with
respect to Descartes distinction between primary
and secondary properties. The mind-brain
identity theorist wishes to state that the
primary property of the mind is just the brain.
It just appears that we have a mental thought
that is distinct from this primary property.
10Three Arguments
- In having a thought we are utterly unaware of
what brain processes are going on so it appears
to us that the thought is different. However,
such a mental thought is just a different
description of this primary property. This
appearance is, in effect, its secondary property. - But now, where do we locate such secondary
properties? In our observation of the external
world this is unproblematic the secondary
properties are subjective, in our heads.
11Three Arguments
- However, we have now internalized the distinction
itself so we can no longer state that it is
subjective. So where are these secondary
properties or as Nagel and McGinn would say,
these facts of appearance?
12Three Arguments
- (3) Failures of Analogies to Other Fields of
reduction - Key quote here The idea of how a mental and
physical term might refer to the same thing is
lacking and the usual analogies with theoretical
identification in other fields fail to supply it.
They fail because if we construe the reference
of mental terms to physical events on the usual
model, we either get a reappearance of separate
subjective events as the effects through which
mental .
13Three Arguments
- .reference to physical events is secured, or
else we get a false account of how mental terms
refer(366) - We do not have a clue when it comes to ourselves
how we would perform a reduction how we bridge
the interlacing of the subjective and the
objective. From other fields of scientific
reduction this is unproblematic the
species-specific viewpoint is omitted from what
is to be reduced.
14Three Arguments
- However, will this approach be appropriate when
we wish species specific understanding? Nagel
No. In two respects. First, as mentioned, when
what we precisely wish to understand is
ourselves, thinking subjects, adopting a method
of subtracting the subjective omitting the
species-specific viewpoint to get to pure
objectivity is counter-productive, not to mention
silly. Second, understanding what a term means
in order to reduce it to a physical event
presupposes an
15Three Arguments
- ..understanding not explainable in physical
terms, in physicalist theory. Therefore, the new
theory does not encompass or replaces the old but
rather depends on it.
16D. Conclusions
- Physicalism where do we go from here?
- Has Nagel refuted physicalism?
- Nagels response No.
- It would be truer to say that physicalism is a
position we cannot understand because we do not
at present have any conception of how it might be
true. (365) and - But nothing of which we can now form a
conception corresponds to it nor have we any
idea what a theory would be like that enabled us
to
17D. Conclusions
- to conceive of it.We cannot genuinely
understand the hypothesis that their nature is
capture in a physical description unless we
understand the more fundamental idea that they
have an objective nature (or that objective
processes can have a subjective nature) (366) - If we are to understand what physicalism is
saying, how it could be true, we need greater
conceptual shifts and conceptual resources than
we presently have according to Nagel.
18D. Conclusions
- We have to derive a way theoretically of bringing
together the first person introspective account
of knowing conscious experience with the third
person perceptual account of brain science in
such a way that we can conceive how neural tissue
is connected to and generates consciousness.
Some philosophers are not as optimistic on this
score as Nagel. For example, McGinn quoted
earlier, who is a materialist believing there
must be some physical property that explains
consciousness,..
19D. Conclusions
- .believes the very dichotomies that Nagel
mentions points to consciousness forever being an
intractable natural mystery. - What we need (1) a developed phenomenology
- (2) a re-conceptualization of the subject/object
distinction
20D. Conclusions
- Problem given (1) and (2) above, it will no
doubt result in quite a conceptual revolution in
the understanding of our terms, it it can be
pulled off. Why assume that physicalism will
not be altered in such a revolution? What we
mean by the physical and by object will no
doubt change. We know perfectly and exhaustively
what physicalisms claims are presently, what it
is saying and what its concepts are.
21D. Conclusions
- Therefore, if we cannot incorporate, as Nagel
states, this what it is like phenomenon, as
Nagel concedes, then should not one conclude that
in the very least that physicalism as presently
understood is simply false and who knows what it
will look like, if anything at all, consequent to
theoretical revolutions?
22Dennett, The Intentional Stance
23An intentional system
- I wish to examine the concept of a system whose
behavior can be at least, sometimes explained
and predicted by relying on ascriptions to the
system of beliefs and desires.I will call such
systems intentional systems, and such
explanations, and predictions intentional
explanations and predictions in virtue of the
intentionality of the idioms of belief and
desire..(375)
24An intentional system
- A system any entity whose activity we ate
attempting to predict. It could be as simple as
a stick or as complex as a person - Intentional system its defining
characteristic is that in its interpretation
essential and ineliminable reference to
rationality, to beliefs, desires, norm-governed
behaviour must be made in order to make sense of
the agent and its behaviour.
25An intentional system
- What do we mean by the intentional here?
- For me, as for many recent authors,
intentionality is primarily a feature of
linguistic entities idioms, contexts and for
my purposes here we can be satisfied that an
idiom is intentional if substitution of
codesignative terms do not preserve truth or if
the objects of the idiom are not capturable in
the usual way by quantifiers (376)
26An intentional system
- What does Dennett mean here?
- Usually referred to as intensionality and
semantic opacity - Whats that?
- Note this move is not universally accepted.
Many philosophers would regard intentionality
to be the directedness of conscious mental
states and not necessarily a characteristic of
linguistic idioms.
27Section One Three Stances
- The key point to remember with respect to all
these stances is that they are only in relation
to the strategies of someone who is trying to
explain and predict its behaviour (376). - The Design Stance
- Whats that?
28The Design Stance
- Different varieties of design-stance predictions
can be discerned, but all of them are alike in
relying on the notion of function, which is
purpose-relative or teleological. (376). - When we approach a system from the design stance
we do not care what it is made of its physical
composition but rather what its function is.
Understanding how a system was designed and
designed for is a great aid.
29The Design Stance
- For example, knowing what a spark plug was
designed for to create a spark will aid us in
repairs and observing whether it performs as
designed. In fact, the only way to ascertain
whether a sparkplug was malfunctioning would be
to adopt the design stance purely physically it
is behaving just as it should. Though the only
way we could tell whether a system was
malfunctioning is from the design stance, the
only way to predict such malfunctioning is
30The Physical Stance
- from physical knowledge the physical stance.
- From this stance our predictions are based on
the actual physical state of the particular
object and are worked out by applying whatever
knowledge we have of the laws of nature. (376)
31The Intentional Stance
- The intentional stance as in interpreting an
intentional system, the defining characteristic
of this stance is an essential and ineliminable
reference to rationality, to beliefs, desires,
norm-governed behaviour in order to make sense of
and predict the behaviour of the system. - Now that we are familiar with such stances lets
apply them to playing a chess computer.
32Playing the Chess Computer
- Scenario we are playing a chess computer and we
want to win. What stances, strategy for
predicting its behaviour, do we adopt? - The Design Stance?
- That is, one can predict its designed response
to any move one makes by following the
computation instructions of the program. (376) - No. We will lose every time. For each move the
computer executes thousands and thousands of
program instructions.
33Playing the Chess Computer
- Each move would take hours, days, weeks to grasp
from the design stance (algorithmic) a game
would take a lifetime. - From the physical stance?
- No. We will lose every time.
- Attempting to give a physical account or
prediction of the chess-playing computer would be
a pointless and herculean labor, but it would
work in principle (376) yeah, for a god
34Playing the Chess Computer
- To trace all the atoms, electrons and physical
movements involved in each move would be quite
the task. - Thus, a mans best hope of defeating such a
machine in a chess match is to predict its
responses by figuring out as best he can what the
best or most rational move would be, given the
rules and goals of chess.(377)
35Playing the Chess Computer
- It is only when we adopt the intentional stance
towards the chess computer that we have a chance
of predicting its behaviour and winning. It is
only when we ascribe rationality and beliefs to
the computer plus the desire to win that we can
effectively predict its behaviour what moves it
will make next that is, only when we interpret
the computer in such a fashion. - So what? Big deal? What does that tell us?
36Playing the Chess Computer
- Here Dennett is agnostic This celebration of
our chess-playing computer is not intended to
imply that it is a completely adequate model of
simulation of Mind, or intelligent human or
animal activity nor Am I saying that the
attitude we adopt toward this computer is
precisely the same that we adopt toward a
creature we deem to be conscious and
rational.(377) -
37Playing the Chess Computer
- Given this, one wonders what to make of Pojmans
intro. to this article that implies that Dennett
believes that computers and machines think. - Pojman is correct however, it is a latter more
radical development of Dennetts building upon
what is said here. - What are these radical moves?
38Playing the Chess Computer
- Dennett will adopt a qualified instrumentalism
with respect to intentional states beliefs,
desires, thoughts, rationality etc. - He construes their reality as abstracta as
opposed to illata. - The abstracts/illata distinction
- Illata atoms, electrons, planets
- Abstracta centers of gravity, the equator,
magnetism, a haircut
39Abstracta/Illata
- Abstracta are not concrete we will not bump
into them. They are not particulars that figures
in causal laws nor are they objects, like
Descartes believed thoughts were before the mind.
Think of magnetism when iron atoms are
aligned in the same direction, a block becomes
magnetized. However, there is not a magnetic
object or entity in the block itself it is an
abstract term describing the arrangement of iron
atoms. Or think of a haircut. We do refer to
haircuts and they have .
40Abstracta/Illata
- .that reality however, a haircut is an abstract
term in which nothing exists over and above the
individual haircuts that are cut. - So mental states are abstracta they have that
form of reality. Adopting the intentional stance
in predicting behaviour is practically
indispensable. We cannot do without it however,
the main point of focus for Dennett is that it is
practically indispensable which itself does not
entail any ontological commitments.
41Instrumentalism
- What is this?
- A view from the philosophy of science regarding
the ontological status of hidden entities or
theoretical posits - For example, the electron. We do not directly
observe an electron. Its justification, the
reason we believe it exists, is the success of
the theory positing them in terms of prediction
and explanatory coherence.
42Instrumentalism
- Realists electrons are real just like rocks and
trees. They just cannot be observed directly.
After all, if the theory positing them has such
predictive success, then there must be something
to its posits. - Instrumentalists if the only reason we believe
in such theoretically posited entities such as
electrons is the predictive success of the
theory, then the only rational conclusion to take
is to restrict the reality of the electron to
just that its usefulness...
43Instrumentalism
- for prediction. The electron theory is an
instrument for the prediction of phenomena that
we do observe. And who knows, future scientific
theories may dispense altogether with the notion
of an electron. - Dennett is slippery. In numerous articles
Dennett appears robustly instrumentalistic
concerning the mental. He refers to the myth of
our rational agenthood, belief as virtual
realityThree Kinds of Intentional Psychology
and belief as useful fictions
44Instrumentalism
- So many philosophers have, with good reason,
interpreted Dennett as claiming that beliefs are
only instrumental in adopting the theory of the
intentional stance. Dennnett as claimed that
this interpretation is mistaken, though in his
more finer moments he concedes it is a mistake
that his writings has encouraged they are
abstracta - The story gets more complicated in Dennetts
later works i.e., the paper Real Patterns (1991)
45Real Patterns
- Real Pattern think of economic laws (
generalizations lets be strict with what we
call a law) of exchange. Describing such
exchanges purely physically i.e., the currency
in terms of paper bills, coins, sticks, cows,
etc., - will cause us to miss what all these
exchanges have in common and what is their
point. We need to adopt the intentional stance
in order to see this real pattern of behaviour.
In fact, with such an adoption we couldnt see
all these physical goings on as a
46Real Patterns
- .pattern to begin with, as an exchange. We
behave in certain patterns such behaviour is
out there, quite real and not simply in the
eye of the beholder. If we are to have any
understanding of the regularity of such patterns,
if they are not to appear as mysterious
happenings and even more strongly, if they are to
appear to us at all, we must of necessity adopt
the intentional stance. It is only by
understanding beliefs, desires, and rationality
that such a pattern comes to light think of 3-D
pictures. Do you see it?
47Real Patterns
- But then if this is the case, do not the
beliefs, intentions and desires, rationality
that make up the intentional stance have a
reality akin to electrons on the realist picture?
Are not beliefs then just as real as the
patterns themselves? Dennett, in my opinion, is
unsatisfying here. - Given all this, to return to the chess computer
example, the argument becomes
48Playing the Chess Computer
- (1) If it becomes practically indispensable in
predicting the moves of the chess computer to
adopt the intentional stance, then since what we
mean by beliefs, desires and rationality, our
mentalistic concepts, is just this practical
indispensability, a chess computer has beliefs
it is an intentional system. - (2) It is practically indispensable to employ
the intentional stance with respect to a chess
computer.
49Playing the Chess Computer
- (3) Therefore, the chess computer has
intentional states. - (4) Therefore, the chess computer is a genuine
rational agent. - Obviously, our beliefs and rationality differs
from the chess computers we can reflect upon
our beliefs, discard some, self-consciously
adopt some etc.
50Playing the Chess Computer
- None of this the computer does however, the way
in which the chess computers states have
intentionality is exactly the same as the way in
which a persons states have intentionality the
chess computer is directed towards the rook in
the same way we are, qua directedness. - The chess computer is rational rationality does
not require self-consciousness - When a physical system becomes so complex that we
must interpret it as rational it is rational.
51Section Two
- There are two key points here
- (1) the taking out of intentionalist loans.
- (2) the necessity of logical rationality in
interpretation and flexibility - There is also an interesting critique of
behaviourism in this section arguing how
Skinners experimental design illicitly attempts
to covered over the mental and intentional
however, that is not essential for our purposes.
52Intentionalist loans
- Any time a theory builder proposes to call any
event, state, structure, etc., in any system (say
the brain of an organism) a signal or message or
command or otherwise endows it with content, he
takes out a loan of intelligence. He implicitly
posits along with his signals, messages, or
commands, something that can serve as a
signal-reader, message-understander or commander,
else his signals will be for naught, will decay
unreceived, uncomprehended..
53Intentionalist loans
- The loan must be repaid eventually by finding and
analyzing away these readers or comprehenders.
(380) - What does Dennett mean here?
- Simply this. Dennett is not a reductionist. We
cannot reduce mental concepts to physical ones.
There is no way of explaining intentionality in
non-intentional terms. In themselves, understood
purely physically, from the physical stance, a
brain state does not bear information.
54Intentionalist loans
- We have to PRESUPPOSE, based upon mental criteria
and rationality what information is before we
can look at any neural process and say thats
it. This presupposition is taking out a loan.
And this presupposition is only accessed via the
intentional stance. - If the agent level, the intentional stance, were
abandoned, then all of this would become
invisible. The intentional cannot be reduced to
the physical or design stance.
55Intentionalist loans
- Neurons, programs, do not of themselves bear
information. They work to show at best the
underlying mechanism for such information bearing
that way we do not have to appeal to anything
supernatural. However, no amount of analysis or
understanding of neurons or syntax will get us to
the very idea of information.
56Intentionalist loans
- But now, how do we, on Dennetts account, pay
back the loan? By analyzing away these readers
or comprehenders (380) - How so?
- One answer Yes, we have to presuppose
rationality and mental criteria in order to get
our brain science going but such a science will
eventually become so sophisticated and detailed
that we can kick this ladder away and no longer
rely on such presuppositions we will pay back
the loan.
57Intentionalist loans
- Dennett suggests such an approach in part (382)
though for him it is never the case that we can
eliminate such presuppositions that is, capture
the intentional stance in non-intentional terms. - Problem most philosophers and neuroscientists
think this is a pipe dream. - The Lashleyan doctrine of neurological
equipotentiality - Whats that?
58Intentionalist loans
- Multiple realizability any of a wide variety of
psychological functions can be served by any of a
wide variety of brain structures. Therefore,
there are no type-identical physical structures
no neurological evidence of such type identities.
Thus, pointing to a particular brain process
in-itself does not necessarily answer our
question of what amental state it is. - But lets do some science fiction and assume that
this is possible.
59Intentionalist loans
- Can we say that we have paid back the loan?
- Are we entitled to sweep such presuppositions
under the rug and downgrade their importance if
at every stage of testing the evolving theory we
have had to rely upon them? - Or, in other words, is it still the case that
correlation is not reduction?
60(2) Necessity of rationality and flexibility
- The intentional stance is central to all of our
interactions - We apply it even to animal behaviour i.e., a
mouse sees a cat in one mouse hole and cheese at
another. We will predict what the mouse will do
by ascribing beliefs and desires. - But does the animal believe in the truths of
logic? - Is the mouse making rational logical inferences
here?
61Rationality and Flexibility
- The assumption that something is an intentional
system is the assumption that it is rational
that is, one gets nowhere with the assumption
that entity x has beliefs p.q.r unless one also
supposes that x believes what follows from p, q,
r otherwise there is no way of ruling out the
prediction that x will, in the face of its
beliefs p,q,rdo something utterly stupid, and,
if we cannot rule out that prediction, we will
have acquired no predictive..
62Rationality and Flexibility
- power at all. So whether or not the animal is
said to believe the truths of logic, it must be
supposed to follow the rules of logic. Surely,
our mouse follows or believes in modus ponens,
for we ascribed to it the beliefs (a) there is a
cat to the left and (b) if there is a cat to the
left, I had better not go left, and our
prediction relied on the mouses ability to get
to the conclusion (379-80)
63Rationality and Flexibility
- We have flexibility here. It doesnt matter how
we answer the question in terms of predicting its
behaviour. Whether the mouse thinks logically
grasping theorems such as If A then B, A,
therefore B and guides its action in such a
fashion or whether after seeing a cat it simply
follows a rule telling it not to make its
acquaintance without any such deduction, is
simply our choice nothing hinges on it. Or so
it is claimed.
64Section Three
- Two Main Points
- (1) How are we to understand the normative
character of belief? - (2) Problems in interpretation when such norms
conflict.
65The normative character of belief
- How ought we to believe?
- We should believe the truth?
- This seems problematic what else are we going
to do? Can we believe what we know to be false? - Could one abandon ones sloppy habit of
believing falsehoods? If the advice is taken to
mean believe only what you have convincing
evidence for, it is vacuous advice believe only
what you believe to be true. If alternatively it
is taken to mean believe only what is in fact
66Normative character of belief
- the truth, it is an injunction we are powerless
to obey.(383) - So how do we think of the normative character of
belief? - Answer look at the preconditions for what is
involved in assigning beliefs. - We can note two
67Normative character of belief
- (1) in general, normally, more often than not,
if x believes p, p is true. (2) in general,
normally, more often than not, if x avows that p,
he believes p(384) - One way of elucidating the necessity of such
norms in understanding the nature of belief
Donald Davidsons project of radical
interpretation. - Such norms leads to what Dennett calls pragmatic
implications of our utterances
68Normative Character of belief
- However, they appear to be more than just
pragmatic implications they appear to be
normative requirements themselves. - I assert that p
- What is my responsibility here? What burden do I
or rather ought I to assume? - (1) Evidence for the truth of p should be
presented why I believe it, upon what basis. - (2) Evidence that I do believe it behavioural
evidence (384)
69Conflicts in Interpretation
- Truth and rationality of belief vs. accuracy of
avowal in our interpretive practice. - Conflict arises, however, whenever a person
falls short of perfect rationality, and avows
beliefs that either are strongly disconfirmed by
the available empirical evidence or are
self-contradictory or contradict other avowals he
has made. (384) - Is she lying or is she irrational?
- How do we tell?
70Conflicts
- One Answer Introspection the person herself
knows - (1) Wont help us we still are relying on
verbal reports thus, do we opt for sincerity of
avowal or a rationality judgment. - (2) An even deeper more interesting problem
- If we try to fix minimum standardsof
rationality at something less than perfection,
what will guide our choice? Not phenomenological
data, for the choice we make will determine what
is to count..
71Conflicts
- As Phenomenological data.(385)
- Perfect rationality is beyond us so what should
be our standards of rationality? This question
needs to be answered in order to assess whether
the person is rational. - However, two, maybe implicit, consequences
follows. - (1) given that standards of rationality is what
constitutes beliefs being able to determine such
standards will constitute the introspective data
itself.
72Conflicts
- (2) The same conflict between rationality vs.
sincere avowal can be internalized. If you are
introspecting your false, seemingly irrational
belief p, is it the case that (1) you really do
believe p but are disobeying standards of
rationality or (2) you are lying to yourself.
What is the authentic phenomenological data here?
Without assessing what are standards of
rationality can we even tell?
73Conflicts
- Neurophysiological data can it help? A
non-starter. We must have already fixed our
standards of rationality, of what identifies a
belief, in order to point to some neural
process going on and say thats it. - The problem mutates
- Not just rationality vs. sincere avowal but also
how we are to understand the constitutive
character of rationality as normative for belief
74Conflicts
- The problem none of us are perfectly logically
consistent not even the greatest philosophers - We need to accommodate for this
- One obvious reason already alluded to for the
need to so accommodate if rationality is
constitutive of the very concept of belief and if
rationality can only be ideal rationality, then
none of us have beliefs - But how do we accommodate?
75Conflicts
- If we make exceptions to the rule, have we make
it the new rule and therefore losing its status
as exceptions? - But any attempt to legitimize human fallibility
in a theory of belief by fixing a permissible
level of error would be like adding one more rule
to chess an Official Tolerance Rule would we
claim that these people actually play a different
game from ours, a game with an Official Tolerance
Rule with k fixed at 3? This would be to confuse
76Conflicts
- the norm they follow with what gets by in their
world.(385) - With such confusion, this is not the right
approach. - But then, why do we not simply do an empirical
study of what people do in fact believe?
77Conflicts
- If one wants to get away from norms and predict
and explain the actual empirical behavior or
the poor chess-players, one stops talking about
of their chess moves and starts talking of their
proclivities to move pieces of wood or ivory
about on checkered boards..(385) - The problem rationality is still constitutive
of what we mean by belief thus any attempt to
analyze it from some other perspective to help us
in our dilemma just changes the subject.
78Conflicts
- It is no longer belief that is being talked
about. - The solution?
- More philosophical work
79Searle, Minds, Brains and Programs The Chinese
Room
80Some Background
- (1) Machine Functionalism
- (2) Turing Test for Intelligence
81Machine Functionalism
- Predicated upon a functionalist theory of mind
- Whats that? Based upon the idea of functional
explanations. - What is a functional explanation?
- A functional explanation relies on the breaking
down of a system into its various component parts
and then seeks to explain the workings of the
system in terms of the capacities of the parts
and the way the parts are integrated with one
another.
82Functionalism
- A functional explanation is very similar, if not
identical, to what is called an operational
definitional in that instead of seeking the
essence of something, a what it is, we define
that something in terms of what it does,
operationally, the roles and purposes it
fulfills. That is what it primarily IS in a
functional explanation i.e., a VP in a
corporation it can be you, me, or anybody with
the requisite training thus, what makes a VP in
a corporation is not the .
83Functionalism
- particular physical instantiation, in this case
what particular person it happens to be, but
rather the tasks, purposes and experience in the
business setting. A VP is defined by his or her
role in the company not body size, ethnicity,
hair colour, etc. - Functionalism in the philosophy of mind
- The defining feature of a mental state is the
causal role it plays with respect to (1) inputs
(i.e., environmental effects on the body
84Functionalism in the philosophy of mind
- (2) other mental states and (3) outputs (i.e.,
behaviour) - Mental state defined by causal relations or as
is the case in machine functionalism a
programmable set of instructions, to sensory
stimulations (inputs), behavioural outputs and
other mental states.
85Functionalism in the philosophy of mind
- A Metaphysical thesis metaphysical
functionalism as a theory of mind. The
complexities of the functional analysis of how
mental states causally interact with each other
given inputs leading to behavioural outputs is
just WHAT MENTAL STATES ARE. In itself,
functionalism doesnt care what physical
realizations brains, silicon chips or whether
there are any such instantiations disembodied
spirits underlying such an analysis.
86Functionalism in the philosophy of mind
- Mental terms are characterized by their
functional role not physical composition think
of the VP example. - Machine Functionalism The Turing Machine
Example of functionalism - Turing machine specified by two functions
- (I) from inputs and states to outputs
- (II) from inputs and states to outputs
87Turing Machine Outline
- Turing machine finite number of states, inputs
and outputs and the two functions mentioned above
specify a set of conditionals, one conditional
for each combination of state and input. - Conditionals if the machine is in state S1 and
receives input I, it will then emit output O and
go into the next state S2. These conditionals
are often expressed in a machine table.
88Turing Machine Outline
- Simple version each system that has mental
states is described by a least one Turing machine
table of a certain sort. Also, each type of
mental state of a system is identical to one of
the machine table states specified in the machine
table - An illustration sufficient for our purposes on
board