Title: The Nature of Systematicity in Natural Language
1The Nature of Systematicity in Natural Language
2Systematicity
- Introduced in Fodor Pylyshyn (1988)
- A feature of cognition, inferential coherence
- The ability to produce/understand some
sentences is intrinsically connected to the
ability to produce/understand certain others.
(p. 37) - Fodor Pylyshyn give no clear definition (see
van Gelder) and only two examples
3The operationalization of systematicity
- When an agent understands the sentence Peter
likes Maria, she understands the sentence Maria
likes Peter as well. - When an agent understands the expressions brown
triangle and black square, she understands the
expressions brown square and black triangle as
well.
4Outline
- What is systematicity?
- and to what degree is our understanding
systematic - Does compositionality entail systematicity?
- No, because
- context-dependence of meaning
- intrusion of encyclopedic knowledge on language
understanding - What are appropriate models of natural language
understanding if systematicity is taken into
account ?
5Is our understanding systematic ?
- Do all who understand good writer and bad teacher
also understand bad writer and good teacher? - Do all who understand within an hour and without
a watch also understand within a watch and
without an hour? (Szabó 2004). - Does a child who understands Mom drives me to
kindergarten also understand I drive mom to
kindergarten ?
6Understanding not Systematic
- Language understanding is not completely
systematic. - This is because the world is not entirely
systematic - A. Clark (1996) Instead of treating
systematicity as a property to be directly
induced by a canny choice of basic architecture,
it may be fruitful to try to treat it as
intrinsic to the knowledge we want a system to
acquire. - A good model of language
- explains the systematic patterns of our language
understanding - gives an account of when and why we find patterns
that are not really predictable.
7Does compositionality entail systematicity?
- Compositionality The meaning of a compound
expression is determined by the meanings of its
constituents and the syntactic way these
constituents are combined. - Systematicity there are predictable patterns
among the sentences we understand.
8The present position
- Compositionality does not entail systematicity
- Systematicity is possible without compositionality
9How to derive systematicity?
- Fodor Pylyshyn
- in the presented case the systematicity of
linguistic competence derives from the fact that
the syntactic operation of modification relates
to the semantic operation of conjunction (or
intersection)
10Understanding NL Expressions
- According to the classical view, the phrase
'understanding natural language expressions'
means more than just fixing a denotation. - We 'understand' a phrase as brown triangle if
- (i) we are able to grasp the corresponding
conceptual representation (brown?triangle) - (ii) the corresponding conceptual components
have an known truth functional content - (iii) With the help of the involved logical
operators it is possible to determine the truth
conditions of the whole phrase under discussion
11Sytematicity Clauses A sample derivation
- understanding the expressions brown triangle and
black square - deriving brown?triangle and black?square
- extracting the lexicon entries brown ? brown,
black ? black, triangle ? triangle, square ?
square. - calculating the corresponding conceptual
representations for brown square and black
triangle brown?square and black?triangle - can get the truth-conditional impact of these
forms - we understand the expressions brown square and
black triangle
12But does this actually work?
- This proposal doesnt work for even the simplest
of adjective-noun combinations - Intersection doesnt give you the systematic
inferences that you would expect or would desire
13Why compositionality fails to explain
systematicity
14Context dependence
- In his Grundlagen der Mathematik Frege (1884)
noticed the context-dependence of words (and took
this as a argument against compositionality in
NL) - One should ask for the meaning of a word only
in the context of a sentence, and not in
isolation - There are compositional models of semantics that
take context dependence into account - We can use the phenomenon of context-dependence
for construing an argument against deriving
systematicity from compositionality.
15What is a white triangle?
The white triangle
A
The black triangle
From P. Bosch (2002) Explaining semantic
productivity. Paper presented at the Symposium on
Logic and Creativity Integrating Categorial
Rules and Experience, Osnabrück.
16Context Dependence?
- Does the proposition expressed by black
triangle depend on the contrast set? - Answer 1 No.
- The contrast set is relevant only for choosing a
good/appropriate/optimal referring expression - PROBLEM ? Triangle 1 is black and white (in one
and the same respect) - Answer 2 Yes.
- Context-dependency of utterance meaning is
widely accepted and also applies here - (Kaplans characters Haas-Spohns hidden
indexicality e.g. in connection with natural
kind terms like water theories of
underspecification, e.g. Carstons 2002
explicatures in relevance theory) -
17What is a red apple?
- (a) a red apple red peel
- (b) a sweet apple sweet pulp
- (c) a reddish grapefruit reddish pulp
- (d) a white room/ a white house inside/outside
A red apple? No, its a green apple but its red
on the inside
18More examples
- Quine (1960) was the first who noted the contrast
between red apple (red on the outside) and pink
grapefruit (pink on the inside). - In a similar vein, Lahav (1993) argues that an
adjective such as brown doesnt make a simple and
fixed contribution to any composite expression in
which it appears - In order for a cow to be brown most of its
bodys surface should be brown, though not its
udders, eyes, or internal organs. A brown
crystal, on the other hand, needs to be brown
both inside and outside. A brown book is brown if
its cover, but not necessarily its inner pages,
are mostly brown, while a newspaper is brown only
if all its pages are brown. For a potato to be
brown it needs to be brown only outside, ...
(Lahav 1993 76).
19Three consequences
- Intersectivity, A(B) A(?)?B,
doesnt hold for most absolute adjectives and
Fodor Pylyshyn's compositional analysis breaks
down - Systematicity statements cannot be derived from
compositionality if intersectivity fails - Encyclopedic knowledge is required to determine
the truth conditional content of an utterance
(explicature in Relevance Theory) - When an agent understands the expressions red
apple (RED PEEL) and sweet grapefruit (SWEET
PULP), then it's likely that she understands red
grapefruit (RED PULP) and sweet apple (SWEET
PULP) as well.
20The Theoretical Part
21Approach 1 The underspecification view
- Radical underspecification augmented with
contextual enrichment - small ? ?x small(x,N) small terrier ? ?x
small(x,N) terrier(x) - Analogously for red apple with place-holders for
the relevant partsred ? ?x part(Y,x)
red(Y)red apple ??x part(Y,x) red(Y)
apple(x) - How to determine the proper values for N and Y,
respectively? - with small(x,N) ? size(x) lt N
22A mechanism of contextual enrichment
- The variables are specified in a way that
maximizes the relevance of the corresponding
question - Small Terrier Is a (randomly selected) terrier
smaller than N? - Red Apple What color is part Y (of a randomly
selected apple)? - Probabilistic Theory of Relevance, see
- Robert van Rooy (2000) Comparing Questions and
Answers A bit of Logic, a bit of Language, and
some bits of Information
23Entropy of a question
- The semantic value of a question Q is a partition
q1, ..., qn of the domain O. - ? inf(q) -log2 prob(q) information
measure of surprise - ?
Entropy of a question Q - The entropy of a question expresses our
uncertainty about the answer. Good questions have
high entropies
24What is a black triangle?
What color is the inner part? E1 E0
What color is the outer part? E0 E1
25What is a red apple?
A red apple? What color is an apple? Q1 What
color is its peel? Q2 What color is its
pulp? E(Q1) gtgt E(Q2) Color differences between
apples are expected for the peel and not for the
pulp.
Therefore, the presented apple is considered as a
green apple (inside red) and not as a red apple
(outside green).This can change if we update
our probability distribution.
26Problems with the underspecification view
- Requires rather clumsy lexical entries
- How much of the peel of an apple has to be red in
order to call it a red peel? - This theory does not really clarify how the
border line between the underspecified
representation and the contextual enrichment is
ever to be determined
27Approach 2 Adnominal functors
- Take Montague (1970) as its starting-point and
take adjectives as adnominal functors. - red(X) means roughly the property
- (a) of having a red inner volume if X denotes
fruits only the inside of which is edible - (b) of having a red surface if X denotes fruits
with edible outside - (c) of having a functional part that is red if X
denotes tools,
28Montague and systematicity clauses
- We cannot derive the intended systematicity
clauses if we realize compositionality via
adnominal functors! - f(a) p, g(b) q
- f(b) ?, g(a) ?
- Compositionality is often very simple to realize
if (higher order) functions are introduced - In many cases, this idea realizes generalizations
to the worst case - Unfortunately, we cannot derive interesting
systematicity clauses from this style of
compositionality!
29Constraining the models
- Additional constraints are required that restrict
the set of possible models - I will assume that these constraints can be
extracted from a Bayesian picture of the mental
encyclopedia - This is not so different from assuming a system
of violable constraints (ranked defaults instead
of inviolable meaning postulates) - Systematicity mainly results from these
additional constraints!
30Approach 3 Connectionst model of adjectival
modification
- Overcoming the gap between compositionality and
systematicity - Modeling both the truth-functional aspects of
adjectival modification and the typicality
effects (Kamp Partee 1995) - Connectionist variant of the selective
modification model of Smith et al. (1988) - It shares with this model the (localist)
attribute-value representation for the prototypes
(apple, grapefruit, ) and for the relevant
instances. - From Blutner, Hendriks, de Hoop, Schwartz (to
appear) When compositionality fails to predict
systematicity
31The simplified model
32Conclusions
- Systematicity of natural language understanding
is intimately related to knowledge about the
world - Systematicity clauses have to reflect this
reality - A compositional representational system doesnt
give you systematicity of understanding because
context-dependency of lexical meaning and
world-knowledge both affect understanding
33Conclusions cont.
- (4) If lexical principles like intersectivity
fail (because of context dependency)
systematicity clauses can no longer be derived
from compositionality - (5) A Bayesian and/or connectionist picture of
the mental encyclopedia is the key for deriving
systematicity clauses! - (6) The principle of compositionality of meaning
may be interesting ? not as part of cognitive
architecture, but as a consequence of
evolutionary learning (e.g. Kirby).
34Thank you for your attention
35... other problems with adjectival modification
- Typicality effects
- The problems of typicality don't relate to the
truth-conditional impact of adjectival
modification. However, a good model should
account for both effects the truth-conditional
peculiarities of adjectival modification and the
typicality effects.
36The red hair problem
- Quine (1960) the different colors typically
denoted (strong preference) by red in red apple
and red hair - In Japanese, aka-zatoo 'brown sugar' (lit. 'red
sugar') comes in the same range of colors as
shira-miso, lit. 'white bean paste - the actual color value deviates in a systematic
way from the prototypical color value that can be
assigned to the color adjective in isolation in
dependency on the conceptual properties of the
modified noun
37The pet fish problem
- Goldfish is a poorish example of a fish, and a
poorish example of a pet, but it's quite a good
example of a pet fish (the conjunction effect of
typicality cx(AB) gt cx(B)) - In case of "incompatible conjunctions" such as
pet fish, striped apple or brown apple the
conjunction effect is greater than in "compatible
conjunctions (red apple).
38Prototype effects
- Using Tversky's (1977) contrast rule (formulated
for activation vectors) - sim(s,t) ??i min(si,ti) ? ??i si ?ti
- sim(sred apple, t1) gt sim(sapple, t1)
- sim(sbrown apple,t2)?sim(sapple,t2) gt sim(sred
apple,t1)?sim(sapple,t1)
39Next steps
- Extend the model by distinguish different parts
of the fruits (inside and outside) - Since without further learning the model starts
with a uniform weight matrix, we expect that the
'neutral' force of modification affects all parts
uniformly - After learning, that the color of the outside of
fruits is more discriminating than the color of
its inside, we expect that the learning mechanism
correctly reproduces the expected sort of
modification - Similarities to Zwarts' (2003) "strongest
meaning" model which starts with an initial
default hypothesis which is subsequentially
modified if more encyclopedic knowledge comes in.