PSEUDOREASONING I - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 35
About This Presentation
Title:

PSEUDOREASONING I

Description:

This is because invisible rhinos conflict with our background information ... that there are no invisible rhinos, therefore it is perfectly acceptable to ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:66
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 36
Provided by: JeffSt6
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: PSEUDOREASONING I


1
PSEUDOREASONING I
  • Recall that pseudoreasoning is false reasoning,
    and includes using emotional appeals, factual
    irrelevancies, and persuasive devices to persuade
    people to accept or reject claims when there are
    no rational grounds for doing so.
  • Pseudoreasoning exploits the rhetorical content
    of words and phrases, where rhetoric here once
    again means the use of language to persuade or
    influence beliefs or attitudes rather than to
    prove them logically.

2
PSEUDOREASONING II
  • MP Sometimes pseudoreasoning and other
    rhetorical arguments are used in place of
    argument, and other times they are used in
    addition to argument.
  • MP Still other times they are used as if they
    were legitimate argument.
  • The key thing to keep in mind is that
    pseudoreasoning and rhetorical techniques can
    tempt us to accept a claim or modify our
    position on an issue without our having a good
    reason for doing so.

3
AD HOMINEM I
  • Ad hominem df. Attacking a person rather than
    his or her argument, view, or position on an
    issue.
  • Ad hominem is Latin for to the man, and the
    idea in this kind of fallacy is that criticisms
    are directed towards the person rather than to
    the persons thoughts about or arguments for a
    particular view.
  • MP However, ad hominem reasoning is
    fallacious since logically, the faults of the
    person are one thing, and the defects in what he
    or she says are quite another and the faults of
    the individual dont automatically attach
    themselves to what he or she says.

4
AD HOMINEM II
  • Joe may be a right wing radical who is
    anti-government and against gun control, and I
    might disagree with such attitudes, but that in
    itself will not prove that his reasoning on a
    particular political issue is automatically
    wrong. And Jane may be a liberal feminist who is
    pro-choice in abortion, and I might think that
    such views are wrong, but that alone will not
    show that whatever she says about social issues
    are either right or wrong simply in virtue of her
    holding these opinions. Rather, her argument for
    or against a certain social issue must be
    assessed on its own merits, and so independently
    of her personal beliefs.
  • Thus arguments have to be assessed on their own
    as arguments, and so independently of our
    attitudes towards the person by whom the argument
    is given.

5
AD HOMINEM III
  • Disliking either a person or something negative
    about him, and finding critically acceptable
    reasons to reject a claim that he makes are two
    different things.
  • We commit the error or fallacy of reasoning
    called ad hominem when we reject a persons
    claim merely because we dislike the person or
    something about the person. This version of ad
    hominem is called personal attack.
  • Because we simply reject a claim made by a person
    or group because we dislike the person or group,
    personal attack ad hominem pseudoreasoning is
    much more emotional or psychological than it is
    rational or logical.

6
AD HOMINEM IV
  • If we think that a persons negative
    characteristics are relevant to rejecting a claim
    she makes, then it may be plausible to reject the
    claim. However, we must be able to explain the
    relation of those characteristics to the claim
    being made so that rejecting the claim for this
    reason can be made plausible.
  • For instance, if we know that a person x is a
    hater of another class of people y, then any
    negative claim about y made by x may be
    reasonably regarded as being suspicious and
    likely to be false, at the same time that further
    information may be needed to assess the claim
    accurately.

7
AD HOMINEM V
  • Circumstantial ad hominem df. A fallacy in which
    a persons claim is rejected based upon the
    circumstances of the person making the claim.
  • In circumstantial ad hominem the attack is not on
    the person, but her circumstances, and it is
    inferred that a claim made by the person is false
    because someone in her position or circumstances
    would make such a claim.
  • For instance, thinking that a tax cut proposed by
    a wealthy congressman cannot be good for the
    average person because of his position of wealth
    is a circumstantial ad hominem. Rejecting Bills
    arguments against the death penalty because he is
    sitting on death row is also circumstantial ad
    hominem.

8
AD HOMINEM VI
  • Personal attack and circumstantial ad hominems
    overlap, and trying to distinguish between them
    in particular instances can be pointless. The
    main thing to recognize is that, if it is an ad
    hominem, then it is fallacious.
  • Pseudorefutation df. A type of ad hominem based
    on charges of inconsistency where no relevant
    inconsistency exists.
  • Relevant inconsistencies concern inconsistencies
    between claims. Thus if Jane says that it is both
    snowing and not snowing at the same time in the
    same place, then we can reject her claim as
    logically inconsistent.

9
AD HOMINEM VII
  • However, if there are no inconsistencies between
    claims, then the fact that a person may not act
    (or may not always have acted) as if the claim
    before us is true does not allow us to infer that
    the claim is false or even that the person
    thinks the claim is false.
  • For instance, Jane may claim to love Jim, but we
    cannot reject her claim simply by noting that she
    has never acted as if she loved Jim. And we cant
    then infer that she herself believes her claim
    about her love for Jim to be false. Either would
    be pseudorefutation.
  • We must also recognize that a person can change
    his mind and either accept something which he
    earlier rejected, or reject something which he
    earlier accepted. A person does not contradict
    herself by now agreeing with the morality of
    euthanasia when she earlier rejected it. To say
    that this is contradictory is pseudorefutation.

10
AD HOMINEM VIII
  • A child might be punished by her parents for
    cheating on a test because she is told by them
    that cheating is morally reprehensible. For the
    child later to reject the claim that cheating is
    immoral because she finds out that her parents
    cheat on their taxes would be an example of
    pseudorefutation. She has not used reasoning to
    reject the view, but has thought that if its
    okay for you its okay for me. She could rightly
    accuse her parents of being hypocritical, but
    their behavior is not itself a reason for finding
    cheating acceptable.
  • The child might cheat again and then, after being
    caught, attempt to justify her actions by saying
    you do it too! This brand of pseudorefutation
    is called tu quoque or you too pseudoreasoning.

11
AD HOMINEM IX
  • To this point we have looked at ad hominem
    arguments in relations to something negative
    about a person, and have seen that, in abusive or
    personal attack ad hominem, a persons claim is
    rejected merely because we dislike the person or
    something about the person.
  • However, it is also fallacious to accept an
    argument merely we like the person or something
    about the person. This form of pseudoreasoning
    does not have a name in the literature, but it is
    an ad hominem because a persons claim is
    accepted, not on the basis of critically
    acceptable arguments, but because of an agreeable
    characteristic(s) which the person has.
  • Accordingly, it is once again emotional or
    psychological rather than rational or logical.

12
AD HOMINEM X
  • However, as before with negative characteristics,
    if we think that a positive characteristic(s) of
    a person is relevant to accepting a claim she
    makes, then it may be plausible to accept the
    claim. However, we must be able to explain the
    relation of those characteristics to the claim
    being made so that accepting the claim for this
    reason can be made plausible.
  • For instance, if we know that Jane is a lover of
    classical music, and her love has made her listen
    carefully and extensively to such music, then a
    claim which she makes about the worth of a
    particular classical composition might be
    accepted hypothetically as likely to be true, at
    the same time that further information may be
    needed to assess the claim accurately.

13
POISONING THE WELL I
  • Poisoning the well df. Attempting to discredit
    in advance what a person might claim by relating
    unfavorable information about the person.
  • This is a kind of pseudoreasoning which can be
    thought of as an ad hominem in advance.
  • For instance, if A says Bs loyalty is to her
    political party. Therefore, anything she says
    about a particular issue will simply reflect the
    party line. The idea is that Bs thinking about
    an issue then need not be considered on its own,
    and so A has poisoned the well of discourse.

14
POISONING THE WELL II
  • MP When A poisons your mind about B by
    relating unfavorable information about B, you may
    be inclined to reject what B says to you.
  • Psychological studies show that even a statement
    such as It is not true that Professor x grades
    unfairly may bias our thinking about someone in
    advance.
  • However, a critical thinker must be extra
    careful not to reject what a person says just
    because we have an unfavorable impression of the
    individual.

15
GENETIC FALLACY I
  • Genetic fallacy df. Rejecting a claim, policy,
    or position on an issue simply because of its
    source, associations, or history.
  • For instance, a member of political party x
    commits the genetic fallacy when he rejects an
    idea simply because it came from a member of a
    different party y.
  • Ad hominem pseudoreasoning is a kind of genetic
    fallacy since here we are rejecting a claim or
    something due to a person based on where it comes
    from, namely, that person.
  • For instance, to reject the music of Richard
    Strauss, to say that it cannot be good, simply
    because it is said that Strauss was sympathetic
    to the Nazis is to commit the genetic fallacy.

16
GENETIC FALLACY II
  • MP say that when we reject a claim, policy, or
    position just because of its source,
    associations, or history, we commit the genetic
    fallacy.
  • However, we also commit a genetic fallacy if we
    accept a claim, policy, or position only on the
    basis of its source, associations, or history.

17
BURDEN OF PROOF I
  • (Inappropriate) burden of proof df. The burden
    of proving an issue is placed on the wrong side
    of an issue, or is placed too heavily on one side
    rather than another.
  • When person x makes a claim that a certain thing
    t is true, and another person y disagrees and
    thinks that that thing is false, one side or the
    other has the burden of proof Does x have the
    burden of proving that t is true, or does y have
    the burden of proving that t is false?
  • It depends on the nature of the claim. It is
    legitimate to talk of burden of proof concerning
    claims. Burden of proof names a fallacy or a kind
    of pseudoreasoning only when the burden of proof
    is placed on the wrong or too heavily on one
    side when x should have the burden of proof, but
    the burden of proof is placed on y, or the other
    way around.

18
BURDEN OF PROOF II
  • Initial plausibility. MP The general rule that
    most often governs the placement of burden of
    proof is The less the initial plausibility a
    claim has, the greater the burden of proof we
    place on someone who asserts that claim.
  • For instance, if I assert that there is a
    rhinoceros in the room with us, and there is no
    evidence of that, then I have the burden of
    proving that it is in the room. This is because
    any claim which conflicts with your own direct
    observations is open to serious doubt.
  • Accordingly, the burden of proving that a rhino
    is not in the room would be inappropriately
    placed on you, and to say Prove that it is not
    in the room would be the fallacy of
    (inappropriate) burden of proof.

19
BURDEN OF PROOF III
  • Remember that the more a claim coincides with
    our background information, the greater its
    initial plausibility.
  • If I now assert that the rhinoceros in the room
    is invisible, and that is why you cant see it,
    but yet it exists, then I have the burden of
    proving that it exists, and the burden of proving
    that it does not exist would be inappropriately
    placed on you.
  • This is because invisible rhinos conflict with
    our background information information which
    says that there are no such things as invisible
    rhinos.
  • Once again, my claim lacks initial plausibility,
    and so, once again, I have the burden of proof,
    and to place it on you would be fallacious.

20
BURDEN OF PROOF IV
  • Affirmative/negative. MP Other things being
    equal, the burden of proof falls automatically on
    those supporting the affirmative side of an issue
    rather than on those supporting the negative
    side.
  • This is the idea that reasons should be given why
    something is the case rather than why something
    is not the case.
  • For instance, a person who maintains that global
    warming is due to industrial pollution has the
    burden of proving that that is the cause and not
    something else.
  • The affirmative/negative rule also applies to
    existence versus nonexistence, so that a
    scientist who maintains that life exists
    elsewhere in the universe has the burden of
    proving that it does.

21
BURDEN OF PROOF V
  • MP In general, the affirmative side gets the
    burden of proof because it tends to be much more
    difficult or at least much more inconvenient
    and perhaps impossible in some cases to prove
    the negative side of an issue.
  • I think that it is possible to prove the negative
    claim that there is no perceptible rhino in the
    room, but not that there is no imperceptible
    rhino in the room. Still, there is no reason
    which favors such an assertion, and so it should
    be rejected.
  • Saying No one has proved that there are no
    invisible rhinos, therefore it is perfectly
    acceptable to believe in them is an appeal to
    ignorance.
  • An appeal to ignorance df. Saying that absence
    of evidence against a claim counts as evidence
    for that claim.

22
BURDEN OF PROOF VI
  • Special circumstances. MP Sometimes getting at
    the truth is not the only thing we want to
    accomplish, and on such occasions we may
    purposely place the burden of proof on a
    particular side.
  • For instance, in our system of justice a person
    is presumed innocent until proven guilty, and the
    burden of proving that an accused is guilty rests
    with the prosecution.
  • In addition, it is reasonable to place a higher
    burden of proof on someone who advocates a policy
    that could be dangerous or costly if he or she is
    mistaken.
  • For instance, one would place a high burden of
    proof on someone who recommends a risky health
    procedure or substantial financial investment.

23
STRAW MAN
  • Straw man df. Ignoring an opponents actual
    position, and presenting a distorted,
    oversimplified, or misrepresented version of that
    position in place of that position.
  • For instance, saying that Johns view about
    abortion is simply that no one has a right to
    tell a woman what to do with her body is straw
    man rhetoric if Johns position about the
    abortion issue and the rights of the mother
    versus the rights of the child is considerably
    more sophisticated than this.

24
FALSE DILEMMA I
  • False dilemma df. Limiting consideration to only
    two alternatives when in fact there are others
    that deserve consideration.
  • Thus, to think that x or y are the only options,
    when in fact there is at least one other option z
    is to commit the fallacy of false dilemma.
  • For instance, saying that either we replace the
    school cafeteria with fast food franchises or
    students will not each lunch on campus. However,
    another alternative which could be considered
    would be to improve the food at the cafeteria.

25
FALSE DILEMMA II
  • False dilemma also occurs when we think that, of
    two alternatives x and y, one must be true and
    the other false when both x and y could be false.
  • If this is the case, then to say that, because y
    is false, x must be true, is to commit the
    fallacy of false dilemma.
  • For instance, saying that Either party x is
    going to have to get control of Congress in the
    next election or we are going to have war is a
    false dilemma in that it might both be false that
    party x gets control of Congress and false that
    we have war.

26
FALSE DILEMMA III
  • Recall that placing a distorted, oversimplified,
    or misrepresented version of a persons position
    is called straw man because the position of the
    real man is replaced with a position which he or
    she does not hold hence the position is as
    false as a straw man is unreal.
  • False dilemma pseudoreasoning can involve straw
    man pseudoreasoning. Thus, a person who attempts
    to get someone to accept position x may present
    an alternative position y in such a way that y is
    distorted, oversimplified, or misrepresented.
  • For instance, a candidate who is trying to get
    you to vote for her may so misrepresent her
    opponents position in an effort to get you to
    vote for her, that the position described is that
    of a straw man.

27
FALSE DILEMMA IV
  • A false dilemma is opposed to a true dilemma,
    that is, one in which only two alternatives truly
    present themselves, as when a physician tells a
    patient Either you have surgery or you will
    die.
  • MP False dilemma pseudoreasoning only occurs
    when reasonable alternatives are ignored. In such
    cases x and y may be false, and some other
    alternative may be true.
  • MP Before you accept x because some
    alternative y is false, make certain that x and y
    cannot both be false. Look especially for some
    third alternative, some way of rejecting y
    without having to accept x.
  • The either x or y alternative characteristic of
    false dilemma can also be stated as if not x,
    then y.

28
THE PERFECTIONIST FALLACY
  • The perfectionist fallacy says either x is
    perfect or it must be rejected.
  • Saying that no piece of legislation should ever
    be passed which will not deal exactly with every
    problem which it is designed to concern is an
    example of the perfectionist fallacy.
  • The perfectionist fallacy is a version of false
    dilemma.

29
THE LINE-DRAWING FALLACY
  • The line-drawing fallacy df. Insisting that a
    line must be drawn at some precise point when in
    fact it is not necessary that such a line be
    drawn.
  • For instance, if we cannot tell exactly how many
    grains of sand it takes to have a heap, then we
    can never say that a number of such grains is or
    is not a heap. But clearly some things are heaps
    and some are not, and this is true even if we
    cant specify exactly where to draw the line
    between a heap and a number of grains which are
    not a heap.
  • MP treat the line-drawing fallacy as a version
    of false dilemma, since the claim is either
    there is a precise place where we draw the line,
    or else there is no line to be drawn. But there
    can be a third alternative, namely, that while
    the line cant be drawn in a precise place, still
    it can be drawn.

30
SLIPPERY SLOPE I
  • Slippery slope df. Thinking that some thing x
    must lead to some other thing y, but there is no
    logical necessity in ys following from x, nor is
    any argument given for the necessity.
  • Saying that euthanasia should not be legalized
    since, if it were, it would inevitably lead to
    abuses, and people would be euthanized who did
    not really want it, is an example of slippery
    slope pseudoreasoning.
  • The fallacy of slippery slope occurs when there
    is no reason to think that x will lead to y and
    yet it is maintained that x will lead to y.

31
SLIPPERY SLOPE II
  • A second version of slippery slope occurs when
    someone claims we must continue a certain course
    of action because we have already begun that
    course.
  • For instance, maintaining that we must continue
    the program of military build-up because it has
    already begun, and so certain industries are
    counting on it financially, is slippery slope
    pseudoreasoning if it cant be shown that there
    are other more substantial reasons for continuing
    the build-up other than those which are simply
    related to the fact that it has already begun.
  • Any force that slippery slope pseudoreasoning has
    is psychological rather than logical. A thought
    of y may follow from a thought of x even though y
    does not have to follow x in fact.

32
BEGGING THE QUESTION I
  • Begging the question df. Assuming to be true
    what you are trying to prove. Since you have
    merely assumed it, you have not proved it.
  • Realism is the view that objects in the external
    world, such as tables, exist apart from
    perception. If you were to attempt to argue for
    realism by saying that you would not see your
    table when you enter your kitchen if the table
    did not exist apart from perception, you would be
    guilty of begging the question. Here the issue is
    whether or not objects exist unperceived, but
    that they do is assumed in the premise that,
    apart from realism, you would not perceive your
    table on entering your kitchen. Therefore the
    conclusion that realism is true repeats the truth
    of realism assumed in the premise.

33
BEGGING THE QUESTION II
  • Begging the question is also known as reasoning
    in a circle because one returns to a premise in
    the reasoning in which the thing to be proved is
    assumed.
  • In the preceding example, the thing to be proved
    is that objects exist unperceived, but that they
    do so exist is itself returned to (or assumed) in
    the premise that you would not perceive what you
    do perceive unless objects like tables exist
    unperceived.
  • But if it is legitimate to question the
    conclusion, as it is here, then it is legitimate
    too to question the premise which the conclusion
    repeats. This is why a question begging argument
    is not proof, but is a form of pseudoreasoning.

34
BEGGING THE QUESTION III
  • MP Persuasive definitions can beg questions.
    Defining capital punishment as state-sanctioned
    murder assumes the immorality of the death
    penalty in that definition. However, the
    definition, and its implicit view that capital
    punishment is immoral, need not be accepted.
  • MP point out that the real problem in cases of
    question begging is a misunderstanding of what
    premises (and definitions) it is reasonable for
    ones audience to accept.
  • MP We are guilty of begging the question when
    we ask our audience to accept premises that are
    as controversial as the conclusion were arguing
    for and are controversial on the same grounds.

35
COMMON GROUND
  • MP If you ever to hope for any measure of
    success in trying to convince someone of a claim,
    you should always try to argue for it based on
    whatever common ground you can find between the
    two of you.
  • MP Indeed, the attempt to find common ground
    from which to start is what underlies the entire
    enterprise of rational debate.
  • For instance, two thinkers cannot debate the
    existence of God if no definition of God can be
    agreed upon by them. Even though the theist and
    the atheist would support different positions on
    the question of theism, their common ground would
    be agreeing on what the term God means. If no
    agreement could be found here, then the rational
    debate could not take place.
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com