Title: CAUSALITY
1CAUSALITY
- A causal claim df. A claim which says or implies
that one thing causes another. - A causal hypothesis df. A causal claim offered
to explain the cause or effect of something, when
the cause or effect hasnt yet been conclusively
established. - A causal argument df. An attempt to support a
causal claim or hypothesis. - (See examples of causal claims on page 420.
Notice how one claim is put in negative form thus
denying that one thing has a causal relation to
another.)
2ONLY-RELEVANT-DIFFERENCE I
- Only-relevant-difference reasoning makes the
following points as it concerns reaching a
conclusion that one specific event or occurrence
caused some other specific event or occurrence - 1. One item has a feature that other similar
items or things of the same kind lack. This is
called the feature in question. - 2. There is only one other relevant difference
between the thing that has the feature in
question and the other items that dont have the
feature in question. - 3. Therefore, that relevant difference is the
cause of the feature in question.
3EXAMPLE I
Similar things, or things of the same kind.
One thing.
Another thing of the same kind. (Side-by-side
comparison.)
One cut rose lasted longer than another cut rose.
The longer-lasting rose was treated with
aspirin. Therefore, the aspirin caused the first
rose to last longer.
The feature in question.
The cause.
The only relevant difference. (The two roses were
cut from the same bush, put in the same kind of
container, given water from the same source, put
in the same location so as to get the same light,
etc.)
4EXAMPLE II
Similar things, or things of the same kind.
One thing.
The same thing at a later time after a change, or
similar things which are different stages of the
same thing. (Before-after comparison.)
Janes computer used to take a couple of minutes
to save large files, particularly those with
graphics. Then she doubled the size of the
computers RAM, and the same files now take about
one-fourth the time to save. Therefore the
cause of the faster time of saving files was due
to increasing the computers RAM.
Only relevant difference.
The cause.
The feature in question faster saving time.
5ONLY-RELEVANT-DIFFERENCE II
- Only-relevant-difference reasoning requires at
least two things to compare. - The things compared must be the same except for
- 1. The feature in question that we want to know
the cause of (e.g. the longer life of the rose,
the faster saving time of the computer) and - 2. The difference that produced the feature (e.g.
the aspirin, the increased RAM).
6ONLY-RELEVANT-DIFFERENCE III
- Note the term only in only-relevant-difference.
For this kind of reasoning to work, it must be
the case that what is identified as the cause of
the feature in question is the only relevant
difference, and not just a relevant difference
amongst others that may contribute to the
feature. - MP Critical thinking requires consideration of
important alternative differences that may have
been overlooked. - For instance, The rose with aspirin might have
come from a hardier bush, or it might have been
fresher to begin with.
7ONLY-RELEVANT-DIFFERENCE IV
- MP Only-relevant-difference reasoning can be
conclusive at least in experimental conditions
(where things are very carefully controlled).
(See the example on page 422.) - MP Even apart from carefully controlled
experimental conditions, this pattern of
reasoning can yield conclusions that are certain
by everyday standards. (See the example on page
423.) - However, Often we cannot be certain that the
difference in question is the only relevant
difference between the cases we are comparing.
8RELEVANCE I
- A difference is relevant when it is not
unreasonable to suppose that the difference might
have caused the feature in question. - Thus it is not unreasonable to suppose that the
aspirin might have caused the rose to last
longer, and it is certainly not unreasonable to
suppose that the memory boost caused the computer
to save files faster. - MP The more you know about a subject, the
better you are to whether a given difference is
relevant to a feature in question.
9RELEVANCE II
- If you know nothing about anything then you are
not in a position to determine if a difference is
relevant to causing the feature in question. - Say, for instance, that when Janes computer
received additional memory that the technician
cleaned the casing of the computer. If you know
nothing about anything then you could not
conclude that cleaning the casing was not a
relevant difference which might be the cause of
the faster saving time of the computer. - MP However, it is not the mark of a critical
thinker to pretend to know nothing about
anything.
10RELEVANCE III
- MP To say that a factor is relevant is only to
say that it is not unreasonable to suppose that
it caused some feature. - It is not unreasonable to suppose that increasing
the RAM of a computer increases the speed with
which it saves files. It is unreasonable to
suppose that cleaning the computers container
increased that speed. - MP If you learn that, in fact, it did not
cause the feature, that doesnt necessarily mean
you were mistaken to think it relevant. Even
though it did not cause the feature, it might not
have been unreasonable to suppose that it did. - Maybe the aspirin did not cause one rose to last
longer than the other, maybe it had been
fertilized before being cut and the other had
not. Even so, it was not unreasonable to suppose
that the aspirin was the cause of the feature in
question.
11ONLY-RELEVANT-COMMON-THREAD I
- Only-relevant-common-thread reasoning
(common-thread reasoning) concerns multiple
occurrences of something. - For instance, a number of trees in a forest die
at the same time. When we try to determine what
caused the trees to die we look for the common
thread which caused the feature in question (the
trees dying). - The pattern of only-relevant-common-thread
reasoning is - 1. Multiple occurrences of a feature (the feature
in question) are united by a single relevant
common thread (the common thread in question). - 2. Therefore, the common thread in question is
the cause of the feature in question.
12ONLY-RELEVANT-COMMON-THREAD II
- It is possible that more than one common thread
exists. In that case there is more than one
possible cause. - For instance, one common thread could be drought,
another could be damaging winds, a third could be
disease. - MP Common-thread reasoning is best for forming
hypotheses which are to be tested in some other
way, usually through experimentation involving
relevant-difference reasoning. - This is because multiple occurrences of a
feature in question could always have resulted
from different causes. - Different instances of the multiple occurrences
of tree death could have had different causes
one tree dies from drought, another from wind,
and a third from disease.
13ONLY-RELEVANT-COMMON-THREAD III
- Common-thread reasoning is also best suited for
forming hypotheses because even if we are
dealing with multiple occurrences of an effect
somehow known to have been caused by one and the
same thing, these multiple occurrences are likely
to have many other things in common besides
whatever it was that caused them. - And common-thread reasoning cannot by itself
tell us which of these common things was the
actual cause of the multiple occurrences of the
effect. - Thus the trees in the forest which died (the
multiple occurrences) likely had many things in
common. Because of this common-thread is better
for forming a hypotheses about the cause of death
which might be identified by only-relevant-differe
nce reasoning.
14MISTAKES IN RELEVANT- DIFFERENCE REASONING I
- 1. The difference taken to be the cause of the
feature in question might not be a relevant
difference. - (Recall that a difference is relevant when it is
not unreasonable to think that it played a role
in causing the feature in question. One is not
thereby committed to saying that it definitely
did play a role in causing the feature in
question.) - For instance, thinking that what caused the
deaths of the trees was the noise from a new
construction site nearby.
15MISTAKES IN RELEVANT- DIFFERENCE REASONING II
- 2. The difference thought to have caused the
feature in question might be a relevant
difference, but might not be the only relevant
difference. - (Again a difference is relevant when it is not
unreasonable to think that it played a role in
causing the feature in question. However, that
does not necessarily mean that it did play a
role.) - MP If the major difference is not the only
relevant difference, then it may not be the cause
of the feature in question. - Perhaps a farmers crop production is much better
this year than last year. And perhaps the major
difference between this year and last year is
more rain. But more rain may not be the only
relevant difference perhaps there was more sun
too, and the farmer used a new brand of
fertilizer. Then more rain might not be the cause
of the better crops.
16MISTAKES IN RELEVANT- DIFFERENCE REASONING III
- 3. The difference being considered as the cause
of something may in fact be the effect rather
than the cause. - For instance, George has not slept well the past
couple of nights, and he has also been nervous
the past couple of days. He may think that his
not sleeping well (difference considered as
cause) is the cause of his nervousness (the
feature in question), while the truth is that his
nervousness is the cause of his not sleeping
well. - 4. The difference might not cause the feature in
question. Instead, the difference and the feature
in question are each effects of a third
underlying cause. - It might be that both Georges nervousness and
his insomnia are due to his feelings of guilt
about something.
17MISTAKES IN COMMON-THREAD REASONING I
- 1. Is the thread identified as common relevant to
the feature in question? - Suppose that five friends all get sick after
eating Jeanies pot roast. A thread common to the
group, in addition to eating the pot roast, might
be that each just finished reading the same book.
However, that would not seem to be relevant to
their getting sick (the feature in question). And
so that particular common thread should not be
identified as the cause of the sickness. - Better reasoning would be to suppose that eating
the pot roast was the common thread which caused
the multiple occurrences of illness.
18MISTAKES IN COMMON-THREAD REASONING II
- 2. A difference taken to be the cause of the
feature in question might be a relevant
difference, but is not the only relevant
difference. - For instance, the friends who got sick after
eating Jeanies pot roast might also have in
common consuming a fair amount of red wine. The
consumption of this wine might be relevant to
their sickness, but may not be the only thing of
relevance to their illness, since something about
the pot roast may also be relevant. - If there is more than one common thread, then any
particular common thread focused on as the cause
of the feature in question may only be one cause
of the feature in question, and so may only
partially explain it. (It may also have nothing
to do with it.)
19MISTAKES IN COMMON-THREAD REASONING III
- 3. Cause and effect may have been reversed.
- Perhaps a correlation is noted between education
and values in that societies that spend a lot on
education tend to have better values than those
which do not. It is then hypothesized that
spending more on education promotes better
values. However, the situation may as a matter of
fact be reversed. It may be that societies with
better values spend more on education. - 4. What is taken to be the common thread and the
feature in question may have a common cause. (See
the two examples on page 428.)
20MISTAKES IN COMMON-THREAD REASONING IV
- 5. The feature in question might not require a
common cause. - Maybe the people who got ill after eating
Jeanies pot roast all got ill for different
reasons too much wine in one case, the flu in a
second, an earlier lunch for a third, and so
forth. If the causes of the common feature the
illness were different in each case, then the
common thread of eating Jeanies pot roast was
not the cause of getting ill, but was merely
coincidence. - MP We should not unthinkingly assume that
multiple occurrences of something have a common
cause even if there is a common thread
present. - MP A common thread might induce us to assume
that a single thing caused the feature in
question, and that might be a mistake.
21POST HOC, ERGO PROPTER HOC I
- Post hoc, ergo propter hoc is Latin for after
this, therefore because of this. - The fallacy of post hoc, ergo propter hoc df.
Thinking that x causes y simply because y occurs
after x. - For instance, thinking that day causes night
simply because night follows day, or thinking
that because every time that the Yankees win the
world series we have a cold winter that the cause
of the cold winter is the Yankees winning the
world series.
22POST HOC, ERGO PROPTER HOC II
- MP It is a mistake to think that, just because
y happened around the same time that x happened,
that y happened because x happened, which is why
post hoc, ergo propter hoc is a fallacy. - It is true that effects follow their causes in
time, and so it may be true that x both causes y
and y follows x in time. It is just that, it is
fallacious to assume a causal relation between x
and y based only on the fact that one follows the
other. - You have good reason to suppose that x caused y
if it is the only thing which accounts for y or
if it is the best explanation of y. (See examples
on pages 429-430.)
23CAUSALITY VS. COINCIDENCE I
- The connection between events can be
coincidental, not causal. Three common kinds of
coincidence are - 1. Two things might not be causally related at
all, but are taken to be causally related. - For instance, a man has a heart attack and dies
after running. The running is taken to be the
cause of the heart attack but in fact an autopsy
shows that the running has nothing to do with it.
Or people theorize that the cause of AIDS (rather
than a cause of the spreading of AIDS) is sex.
Both examples are post hoc reasoning. - MP What underlies many superstitions is
thinking of coincidental events as being causally
related to one another.
24CAUSALITY VS. COINCIDENCE II
- 2. Multiple occurrences of an effect are thought
to be due to a common thread shared by all the
occurrences when the truth is that some other
common thread caused the occurrences. - When this is the case then it is just
coincidence that the first common thread is
present. - For instance, the people who got ill after eating
Jeanies pot roast may have been together a day
or two before at a party at which each was
exposed to a common virus which took a couple of
days to make them sick. Their shared feature of
getting sick also had the common thread of eating
at Jeanies, but that common thread is just
coincidence, and, as such, is causally irrelevant.
25CAUSALITY VS. COINCIDENCE III
- 3. It can be assumed that multiple occurrences of
a particular effect are due to a common thread
shared by all the occurrences when in fact the
occurrences were not caused by a single thing. - In the five people getting ill after eating at
Jeanies, the multiple occurrences are the five
cases of illness and the common thread assumed to
be the cause of the illnesses is eating Jeanies
pot roast. Eating Jeanies pot roast may be the
common thread which is shared by all five
illnesses, and so may be their cause, but it may
also simply be a coincidence. The truth may be
that each illness has a different cause.
26CAUSATION IN POPULATIONS
- Some causal claims apply to populations rather
than to individuals. - For instance, Smoking causes cancer is meant to
link smoking causally to cancer, not in any
particular individual, but to smokers in general.
Saying that smoking causes cancer means that, we
would expect more cases of lung cancer in
populations in which everyone smoked rather than
in populations in which no one smoked. - MP To say that X causes Y in population P is
to say that there would be more cases of Y in
population P if every member of P were exposed to
X than if no member of P were exposed to X.
27KNOWLEDGE OF CAUSES IN POPULATIONS
- How do we know, or what makes us think, that one
thing is a cause of another? Or what is the
evidence for the claim that there would be more
cases of something (Y) in a population in which
every person in the population were exposed to
something (X) than if they were not? - The first thing which argues in favor of one
thing causing another in a population is
controlled cause-to-effect experiments.
28CONTROLLED CAUSE-TO-EFFECT EXPERIMENTS II
- Controlled cause-to-effect experiments involve
randomly dividing a random sample of a target
population into two groups an experimental group
and a control group. - In the experimental group all members of the
group are exposed to something c which is
suspected to cause something else. (For instance,
being exposed to some mold which is thought to
cause a certain allergy.) - The members of the control group are not exposed
to c. However, other than this difference,
members of the control group are treated exactly
the same as members of the experimental group.
(Thus the members of this group are not exposed
to the mold, but otherwise everything else is the
same.)
29CONTROLLED CAUSE-TO-EFFECT EXPERIMENTS III
- The the experimental and control groups are then
compared with respect to frequency of some
effect, e. (Here the occurrence of the allergy
which the mold is thought to cause.) - MP If the difference d, in the frequency of e
in the two groups is sufficiently large, then c
may justifiably be said to cause e in the
population. - Thus if 50 of 100 people in the experimental
group get the allergy when exposed to the mold,
and only 1 out of 100 people in the control group
gets the allergy when not exposed to the mold,
then the difference - 49 - may be said to be
sufficiently large for the mold to cause the
allergy in that group.
30CONTROLLED CAUSE-TO-EFFECT EXPERIMENTS IV
- It is a question how large the difference d must
be between the experimental group and the control
group to say that a certain effect e is due to a
certain cause c. - This is determined in relation to the size of
each group, say 100 people, at some approximate
statistically significant level, say 0.05, which
means that the result could have arisen by
chance in about 5 cases out of 100. - For instance, to think that e is due to c in a
group of 100 people, the difference d between the
number of people in the experimental group with e
and those in the control group with e must exceed
13. (For further see table on page 447, and note
that, as the size of the population goes up, the
figure that d must exceed goes down.)
31CONTROLLED CAUSE-TO-EFFECT EXPERIMENTS V
- The sample of the population from which the
members of both the experimental and control
groups are taken should be representative of the
target population. - Accordingly, the sample used to construct each
group should be taken at random. - In addition, the assignment of a member of the
sample to either the experimental or the control
group should also be done at random.
32SAMPLE SIZE
- One should not automatically assume that a sample
size in controlled experiments is large enough
to guarantee significance. - MP A large sample is no guarantee that the
difference (d) in the frequency of the effect in
the experimental group and in the control group
is statistically significant a particular
experiment may not achieve statistically
significant results even with a large sample
size. - MP However, the larger the sample, the smaller
d expressed as a difference in percentage
points need be to count as significant. (Refer
to table on page 447.)
33FREQUENCY DIFFERENCE
- One must also not automatically assume that the
difference in frequency between experimental
group and control group of an effect being
investigated is great enough to guarantee
significance. - A difference may seem great that is not really
statistically significant. - For instance, If there are 50 rats in an
experimental group and 50 more in a control
group, then even if the frequency of skin cancer
found in the experimental group exceeds the
frequency of skin cancer found in the control
group by as much as 18 percentage points, say 2
rats in the control group and 11 in the
experimental group got cancer this finding would
not be statistically significant (at the 0.05
level). (This is 9 rats in 50, and where we
would expect that 2 rats 0.05 might get cancer
by chance.)
34ANALOGICAL EXTENSION
- MP The results of controlled experiments are
often extended analogically from the target
population (e.g. rats) to another population
(e.g. humans). - We need to be careful here, since we would need
to know how representative the rats used in each
group are of all rats how many features relevant
to the experiments conclusion human beings have
in common with rats so that the conclusion of the
rat study can be reasonably applied to humans
and whether there are important relevant
differences between the target population in the
experiment the rats and the population to which
the results of the experiment are analogically
extended humans.
35REPUTABLE SOURCES
- MP In reputable scientific experiments it is
safe to assume that randomization of the sample
from the target, and the division of members of
the sample into the two groups control and
experimental has been employed, but one must be
suspicious of informal experiments in which no
mention of randomization is made. - MP Any outfit can call itself the Cambridge
Institute for Psychological Studies and publish
its own journal. However, such an outfit
could consist of little more than a couple of
university dropouts with a dubious theory and an
axe to grind.
36NON-EXPERIMENTAL CAUSE-TO-EFFECT STUDIES I
- In a non-experimental cause-to-effect study
members of a target population, such as humans,
who have not yet shown evidence of a suspected
effect e, such as allergic reaction, are divided
into two groups that are alike in all respects
but one. - MP The difference is that members of one
group, the experimental group, have all been
exposed to the suspected cause c (e.g. mold),
whereas the members of the other group, the
control group, have not.
37NON-EXPERIMENTAL CAUSE-TO-EFFECT STUDIES II
- The difference between non-experimental
cause-to-effect studies and controlled
cause-to-effect experiments is that the members
of the experimental group are not exposed to the
suspected causal agent by the investigators. - This is because there are limits to what is
ethically acceptable to expose humans to (and
some other creatures?). We cant purposely
expose human subjects to potentially dangerous
agents. - For instance, if smoking is suspected of causing
cancer, we would not make people smoke to see if
it causes cancer. What we would do is select from
a group of people who voluntarily smoke and
compare them with people who are otherwise like
them who do not smoke.
38NON-EXPERIMENTAL CAUSE-TO-EFFECT STUDIES III
- Just as with controlled experiments, experimental
and control groups in non-experimental studies
are compared to see how often the effect being
looked for appears in each group. - MP If the frequency in the experimental group
exceeds the frequency in the control group by a
statistically significant margin, then we may
conclude that c is the cause of e in the target
population. - For instance, if more people get lung cancer in
the experimental group by a statistically
significant margin than do those in the control
group, then we can conclude that smoking causes
cancer.
39NON-EXPERIMENTAL CAUSE-TO-EFFECT STUDIES IV
- MP Non-experimental studies are inherently
weaker than controlled experiments as arguments
for causal claims. - One reason for this is that members of the
experimental group who have already been exposed
to the cause c in question may differ in some
respect r from the control group in addition to
c. And it may be that r is a cause of the effect
being looked for. - For instance, we may think that a fatty diet c
causes colon cancer e. Members of the
experimental group will have a fatty diet and
those of the control group will not. But even if
the experimental group has a statistically
significant higher rate of colon cancer, it may
be due to a different or additional factor, such
as heavy drinking, since many people who eat
fatty foods also consume too much alcohol.
40NON-EXPERIMENTAL CAUSE-TO-EFFECT STUDIES V
- Another problem is incomplete knowledge of the
causal complexity of nature and human reality. - MP Because we do not have complete knowledge
of what factors are causally related to what
other factors, it is impossible to say for
certain that all possibly relevant variables in
such studies have been controlled.
41NON-EXPERIMENTAL EFFECT-TO-CAUSE STUDIES I
- In a non-experimental effect-to-cause study the
experimental group already have the effect e
such as lung cancer being investigated. - The experimental group is then compared with a
control group none of the members of which have
e, and the frequency of the suspected cause c
e.g. smoking cigarettes is measured. - MP If the frequency of c in the experimental
group significantly exceeds its frequency in the
control group, then c may be said to cause e in
the target population.
42NON-EXPERIMENTAL EFFECT-TO-CAUSE STUDIES II
- One cannot simply assume that, because the sample
size seems large enough, or because the
difference in frequency seems significant, the
findings of the study are significant. - One must also be careful about extending the
results of a non-experimental effect-to-cause
study analogically to other populations. - For instance, we must be careful in concluding
from a group study of something that caused a
certain reaction in men that the same thing will
cause the same thing in women since there may be
relevant differences between the sexes which
would interfere with the expected result.
43NON-EXPERIMENTAL EFFECT-TO-CAUSE STUDIES III
- It must also be noted that the subjects in the
experimental group may differ in some important
way (in addition to showing the effect such as
lung cancer) from the rest of the target
population. (See the example on page 450.) - MP Any factor that might bias the experimental
group in such studies should be controlled. If,
in evaluating such a study, you can think of any
factor that has not been controlled, you can
regard the study as having failed to demonstrate
causation.
44NON-EXPERIMENTAL EFFECT-TO-CAUSE STUDIES IV
- MP Effect-to-cause studies show only the
probable frequency of the cause, not the effect,
and thus provide no grounds for estimating the
percentage of the target population that would be
affected if everyone in it were exposed to the
cause.
45APPEAL TO ANECDOTAL EVIDENCE I
- If we try to argue that, because we know of a
case or two in which one thing caused another,
then we are appealing to anecdotal evidence in
accounting for the causal relation. - For instance, we might say that aunt Velma has
begun each day with a shot of whiskey for the
last 60 years, and then conclude that drinking a
shot of whiskey in the morning makes you live
longer. - MP To establish that x is a causal factor for
y we have to show that there would be more cases
of y if everyone did x than if no one did, and
you cant really show this or demonstrate that
x isnt a causal factor for y see next slide
by citing an example or two.
46APPEAL TO ANECDOTAL EVIDENCE II
- If, on the other hand, we try to argue that,
because we know of a case or two in which one
thing failed to cause another, then we are
appealing to anecdotal evidence in accounting for
the lack of causal relation. - For instance, a person might maintain that heavy
drinking of alcohol does not cause liver damage
since his uncle drank 10 beers a day for 60 years
and died from getting hit by a kid on a
skateboard. And his autopsy showed that his liver
was normal for a man his age.