Title: Phenomenalism
1Phenomenalism
2The general idea
- Classical Idealism (Berkeley) Physical objects
are actually (structured) collections of ideas. - More recent (and more modest) efforts Carnap,
Die Logische Aufbau der Welt. Carnap tries to
come up with an analysis of talk about the world
in terms of a. Logical structure b. Space and
time c. Sensible properties. (Red at place p
and time t as a protocol sentence.) - Others Attempts to analyze ordinary object talk
as some kind of theory grounded in immediately
observable features of our sensory experiences
(some think there really is a parallel here with
scientific theories).
3Direct (Naïve) Realism
- while the verb to see has many usesits
primary use is one in which a person is said to
see a physical object and to see that it is of a
certain colour - Sellars winds up defending some such view (but
thats later). - A more naïve realism holds that things seen
(whatever they may be) always are as they appear
to be this Sellars does not hold, so he adopts
direct realism to distinguish the view he will
defend from this more naïve realism.
4The phenomenalistic theme
- Objects really do have the sorts of properties
they look to have. - Direct realism holds that the standard use of
colour predicates is in contexts like O is red
at place P. - Looks-talk must then be explained in terms of
this basic sort of claim. - Classical phenomenalism has a different starting
point A collection of more basic objects
which have these properties in a more basic
way. Ayer calls these objects sense contents. - The idea is that a physical object is redp, i.e.
red in the physical sense, if and only if there
are reds sense contents that are parts of it
under normal viewing conditions. - The object merely looks red when there are reds
sense contents that are parts of the object, but
are not produced under normal viewing conditions.
5Saving sensory judgments in cases of illusion
- The main point for the phenomenalist is that when
something merely looks redp, this is because
there really is a reds sense content being
experienced. - Further, all the sense contents produced by the
object, under normal and abnormal viewing
conditions, are parts of the object. - The DR, on the other hand, says that only parts
of physical objects have colours and physical
objects and their parts are publically
observable, i.e. they belong to the
intersubjective world.
6Surfaces and slippery slopes
- It seems right to say that, when we call (say) a
car red, what we mean is that it has a red
surface. - Such a surface is not 2-dimensional its a 3D
physical object, the (thin) layer of paint that
covers the car. - But its tempting to move in a more metaphysical
direction, and say that what really has a colour
is a really 2D surface, and to conclude that what
we really see is such 2D surfaces (the rest of
3D physical objects being inferred from the
surfaces we see). - Even if we make this move, were still operating
in the public world were not yet
phenomenalistseven though we may now describe
physical objects as made up of actual and
potential (exposable) colour surfaces.
7Rejecting surfaces
- There are a few ways to relate this talk of
surfaces back to the colours of 3D objects. - But its not pretty we can make lots of
different exhaustive slicings across an apple,
and to say the apple is made of all of these
seems redundant at best. - It seems we should either say the 3D object comes
first, and its slices are dependent and only
actual when the thing is sliced, or the object is
really a collection (continuum) of colour points,
and both the object and the slices are (3D and
2D) collections of such points. - The last seems dubious the first makes the
slices depend on the 3D object. - The real mistake Sellars is worried about,
though, is the distinction between what is really
seen, viz. the surface and what we then
believe/infer from it (the object). This is an
epistemic step towards phenomenalism, since it
leads to the idea of unattached surfaces that
we can also see, and to an epistemic conservatism
about what we see that makes the phenomenalist
account of illusions tempting.
8Still some distance to go
- Pure seeing is introduced here for the new D.R.
view that says, what we see (really, purely) is
just surfaces, and we then infer the objects that
have them. - But so far, the D.R. says there is no dagger that
Macbeth sees, and this new D.R. agrees. - However, the new D.R. may be tempted to say there
was a dagger-shaped surface there (with no dagger
inside it?). - This step removes the surfaces from the public
world and shifts them to the theatre of the
mind where the classical phenomenalist is at
home
9Resistance
- The new D.R. need not go this way she can keep
her new surfaces firmly linked to the public
world. - On this view, surfaces without cores just dont
exist. And (consequently) neither do surfaces
without backs. - On the other hand, if she begins to say that only
facing surfaces really exist, the new D.R. is on
her way to phenomenalism. - For Sellars this is just a mistake we do not see
surfaces and infer objects we see objects,
though what we see of them is just a facing
surface, we take it that there is an object and
that it has a back (and inner surfaces, if we
should slice it) with some shape and colour too. - Both the objects and the parts of them that we
see can seem to be other than they are Illusion
remains possible concerning them. - But a second train of thought leads to
phenomenalism Here, what is basically seen is a
sense content these are private, and not subject
to illusion they are always as they seem to be
to the subject.
10Retaining a key point
- Rejecting phenomenalism does not require that we
reject the existence of phenomenal colour
expanses as elements of visual experience. - Sellars is persuaded that there are such things,
but that we need to locate them very carefully in
our conceptual scheme.
11Phenomenalism The slogan
- Physical objects are patterns of actual and
possible sense contents. - Taxonomy Three traditions on the nature of
sense contents. - The first Grounds its talk of sense contents in
ordinary perceptual talk directly sees and
directly sees that parallel normal use of
sees and sees that. So direct seeing
involves knowing things about what is directly
seen. - For example, the usual inference from S saw an
X to an X exists carries over S directly saw
a red triangular sense content implies there was
such a sense content. - Further, just as objects can exist unsensed, this
model allows (at least in principle) that sense
contents can also exist unsensed, and just as
objects can look other than they are, so can
sense contents (error is not ruled out). (Contra
Berkeley here.) - But of course direct seeings are seeings of sense
contents, not of public objects.
12A second approach to phenomenalism
- Links sense contents to conceptual thinking.
- This is where we get the esse is percipi notion
Just as, for there to be an idea of x, someone
must be thinking of x, for there to be a red
sense content, someone must be having
(perceiving) it. - That some red triangular expanses (the
sense-content ones) must be perceived to exist
does not mean that all are like this we can
still have them out there in the physical world
too. - So its a further step to say (with Berkeley)
that the real red triangular expanses are all
dependent on perception, and that there are no
independent ones at all.
13Tangling the first two
- Someone who starts in the first way might still
move on to claim that for sense contents esse is
percipi. - But the argument she would need to make her case
must either be inductive (i.e. all the red
triangles observed have been perceived, so in
general all existing red triangles must be
perceived?) or synthetic a priori (something
about the idea of a red triangle demands a
subject who perceives it this sounds rather like
Berkeley). - On the second approach, though, X is red
outside of contexts of the form X is a red sense
content is just ill-formed. This emphasizes how
far from our ordinary perceptual talk the second
sort of theory takes us. - Further still X sees that has no parallel on
the second approach there is no X senses that
here, just direct-object sensings of various
kinds of sense contents.
14The third phenomenalism
- Here the beginning point is the link between
sense content talk and appears talk. - So S senses a red triangle doesnt imply that
there is a red triangle (as with approach 2).
(After all, that there appears to be a red
triangle does not imply that there is one!) - We can get a form of the implication back by
force. - According to the third version, though, is that
what we directly know in sense perception is
facts about sense contents, i.e. (on this
account) facts about how things appear to us. - But this makes classical phenomenalism hard to
accept, since it puts appears talk in its
application to the physical world first, and
sense content talk is defined/understood in
terms of a language that apparently presupposes
the categories of public physical objects and
their sensible properties.
15A thesis
- Whenever there appears to S to be a red
triangular physical object somewhere, then it is
also true that S has a sensation of a red
triangle. - 3 gives us this by defining the second in terms
of the first. But a phenomenalist must find a
different route to this claim. - Sellars also endorses the claim, but not in a way
that gives comfort to the phenomenalist. - Sellars will defend a form of the second line on
sense contents.
16A forced choice
- The phenomenalist has to choose between a version
of the second account of sensations (one that
doesnt equate sensations with states produced
ordinarily by talk, which makes them dependent
on ordinary object talk), and the first (in which
sensations are perceived directly, and such
perceivings involve direct knowledge of our
sensations).
17Esse is Percipi
- On the first approach, esse is percipi is not a
natural principle to adopt (since the model is
ordinary perceptual talk, and there what is
perceived can and does exist without being
perceived). - It can be added by force, if a direct object
version of sensing (S senses x) is added, and we
assert that sensations only exist in such
relations to subjects. But we lose a direct link
to the cognitive side here such relations might
exist, in principle, without S knowing anything
about the sensation S is having.
18Towards a refutation
- The challenge to phenomenalism comes here.
- Recall that phenomenalism holds that ordinary
objects are (in fact) collections of actual and
possible sense contents. - So we need to understand what possible sense
contents are. - The suggestion Sellars makes is that they are
possibilities that subjects are in a position to
bring about analogous to skids that a driver is
in a position to bring about. - So, for instance, when I have my eyes closed and
Im standing in front of a white wall and its
normally lit and I can open my eyes, then theres
a possible white sensation that I would have if I
opened my eyes.
19Justifying such claims
- To justify that sort of claim about what
sensations I would have if I were to do
something, I need induction. - This requires that I notice a regular pattern in
my sensations, of the form Whenever
circumstances are C and I do A, E results. - We can think of many instances of such
generalizations where E describes sensations that
I will have. - But the standard cases are cases where C and A
are specified, not in terms of the sensations
that I have or had, but in terms of ordinary
objects and actions/movements that I make in
public space (for example, the fireplace on p. 79
or the white wall above).
20A there pure phenomenal generalizations?
- The circumstances and the action must be
described in phenomenal terms, not just the
resulting sensations. - But will the circumstances and the action be
described using actual sensations, or actual and
possible (i.e. conditional) sensations? - On one hand, the phenomenalist has only claimed
to reduce objects goings-on in the physical
world to a combination of actual and possible
sensations. - But on the other hand, if all the generalizations
here invoke both actual and possible sensations,
how could we ever have learned them? That is,
what we learn about the world depends on actual
experience possible experience (whether
phenomenal or not) makes no impression on us and
teaches us nothing.
21Getting down to actual sensations
- So the challenge to the phenomenalist is to frame
generalizations that are pure, in the sense that
they are stated solely in terms of actual
sensations only then could we have inductive
evidence of what sensations are possible in a
given (purely phenomenally described)
circumstance.
22E and A generalizations
- Sellars allows that there really are some purely
phenomenal generalizations. - But he distinguished between two kinds of such
generalizations essentially autobiographical
and accidentally autobiographical. - The first are generalizations that we would
normally explain as due to the fact that, as
individuals, we live among particular objects and
are subject to other particular ordinary object
perceptual facts about ourselves. They cannot be
separated from our autobiographies. - The second, however, though they are learned in
the course of our experience as individuals, hold
independently of the particular circumstances of
individuals only these could provide a general
account of possible/conditional sensations in
pure terms that would support a phenomenalistic
reduction of ordinary objects to actual and
possible sensations.
23Details on what generalizations are needed
- what the phenomenalist wants are
generalizationswhich are accidentally
autobiographical, generalizations in which the
antecedent (circumstances C/ available/possible
action A) serves to guarantee not that I am in
the presence of this individual thingbut rather
that my circumstances of perception are of a
certain (general/sensation-only dependent) kind.
(83)
24Theres more
- A lot has been granted that could be disputed
here the idea of persons is also part of the
ordinary object framework, and it too needs to be
reconstructed (ditto for their actions the focus
here has been on the circumstances C). - E generalizations come with dirty hands (84),
i.e. they hold only for people in circumstances
that are fixed in terms of the types of objects
present (including their sensible properties and
spatial/temporal arrangements). - So they are not credible as unrestricted
inductive generalizations which are what the
phenomenalist really needs. - There are real generalizations here- but they
make the possible sensations available to a
subject dependent on the physical circumstances
of the subject. That is, they depend on the
framework of ordinary objects and our beliefs
about how these objects and the subjects
relations to them determine what sensations the
subject will have.
25A hypothetico-deductive turn
- What is the hypothetico-deductive (HD) method?
- Theories are not arrived at by direct induction
from our observations they are hypotheses which
can subsequently be tested by what they imply
about our observations. - So the idea is that we form hypotheses and deduce
consequences for observations (Then we observe to
see if those consequences actually hold). - Sellars argument to here has assumed a kind of
inductive basis for the bootstrap attempt to get
ordinary object concepts out of sensations. - Maybe an HD approach can save phenomenalism!?!
26Whats involved
- Neo-Lockean Physical objects are part of a
theory that explains observed facts about our
sensations. - No more translation of physical object talk
into phenomenal talk. - Nevertheless, theoretical entities (such as
ordinary objects) are still just that purely
conceptual posits, intended to do the job of
organizing our observations. There is no need to
regard ordinary objects as anything more than a
convenient hypothesis.
27Sellars response
- For Sellars, we should take theoretical entities
seriously, not dismiss them as mere conceptual
tools. - But this is not his reason for rejecting
neo-phenomenalism. - The relation between observation-language and
theory that HD requires is that inductively
confirmed generalizations in the observation
language correspond, via the bridge rules, to
theorems in the theoretical language (and no
theorems should correspond to disconfirmed
inductive generalizations). - But this breaks the proposal Sellars earlier
argument against classical phenomenalism showed
that there are no such confirmed generalizations
in the language of sense-contents.
28Where from here?
- Return to direct realism we directly see real
(public) objects, and in seeing them, we see that
they have various sensible properties (that is,
seeing in this sense is an epistemic/
knowledge-producing/ judgment-involving act). - No other form of knowledge is more basic. (This
is where our knowledge of the world begins.) - But this does not mean that we dont have direct
knowledge of other things. - Including that we seem to see something/ and
features of our sensations/ visual impressions.
29Direct?
- Direct knowledge is non-inferential that is, we
dont acquire it by reasoning from other things
we know. - But more knowledge that p requires (on the point
in question) authorization, a right to be
convinced that p. - The inference schema for direct knowledge is
Xs thought that-p occurred in manner M. So
(probably) p. - A label This is trans-level inference, because
it involves a shift from the meta-level at which
we talk of thoughts, their contents, and the
conditions in which they arise, to the level of
endorsing one of those thoughts. - Care is needed to distinguish what is and is not
directly known in familiar cases of perception
the idea, for Sellars, is to avoid
representationalism. (?)
30Directness vs. Security
- There is a temptation to identify directness with
security, and say that we know more directly when
there is less chance that were wrong. - Sellars rejects this directness is a matter of
whether nor not inference is required. So, if I
directly see a book and see of it that it is red
and rectangular on the facing side, that is
direct knowledge of the book. I might then infer
that its also red and rectangular on the hidden
side, but that is not direct knowledge. - But my knowledge that Im seeing a book is less
secure than my knowledge that I seem to be seeing
a book, though it is not any less direct. - Even if I sometimes do infer facts about what Im
seeing from facts about how things appear to me,
this doesnt mean that all knowledge about the
physical objects I see is inferred in this way
(in fact, I learn to make claims about the
sensible features of objects around me directly
long before I learn to talk about how things
appear to me.)
31Parasitism
- In fact, Sellars claims that the frameworks of
qualitative and existential appearings and of
sense impressions are parasitical upon discourse
concerning physical things.(89) - The phenomenal world of these things and their
perceptible qualities does obey regularities, and
provides an observational starting point for
scientific theorizing.
32Learning to perceive the world
- An abstractive account of concept-formation holds
that we come by concepts like red by means of
experience of red things. (This makes the notion
that having the sensation of red is the key, and
even that the sensation of red is the original
from which the idea of red is abstracted. See
Hume!) - Sellars claims instead that coming to have a
perception of something red as red, that is, a
perception that involves the judgment this is
red, is not just a matter of having the relevant
sensation. - It requires also a rich background of language
learning and dispositions to accurately report
the colours of things and to distinguish one
colour from other colours, this thing from that
thing, etc. - This logical space of things and their properties
is an evolutionary development, culturally
inherited. (90)
33The process
- When I know something about an object by
perceiving it, there is a link between the object
and my knowledge of it the sensation it causes
in me. - This sensation is what I respond to, but its
effect is causal I dont infer from facts I
directly perceive about my sensation to
conclusions about its cause. - Instead, my having the sensation is one causal
factor (another is my possessing the right
conceptual framework to respond correctly to the
sensation in those circumstances itself a
product of normal development and
language-learning) leading me to judge that some
claim about the perceptible qualities of the
object is true.
34A familiar idea, again
- Sense impressions are postulated, in order to
explain how things appear to us. - But for Sellars, if a theory is a good theory, we
should believe in the entities that theory
posits. - So for Sellars, there really are sense
impressions. - But they are not sense data, that is, they are
not cognitive states that form the premises on
which our theory of everyday things and their
sensible properties is built. - Here we should pause to consider the pragmatic
theory of observation.
35Learning the language of sensations
- To learn to describe our sensations, both we and
our instructors must know - How to report/ describe the sensible properties
of things in the physical world. - How we describe sensations by analogical use of
these sensible properties. - Then we can be trained to use seems talk and
other ways of describing our sensations, and even
to report our sensations directly.
36Two links between sensations and physical objects
- A sensation of a red triangle is a sensation that
is normally caused, under standard conditions, by
the presence of a red triangle before our eyes. - Impressions of red/blue/yellow triangles resemble
and differ in ways analogous to the ways
triangles that are red/blue/yellow resemble and
differ. - The same goes for different shapes of a given
colour. - So we get families of predicates for properties
of sensations, each based on the predicates for
the corresponding sensible properties of physical
things. - Since these new predicates are predicates for
features of an episode (which is occurring in a
person), i.e. features of something that is going
on, they are correctly said to be adverbial. They
pick out kinds of sensings.
37But one more thing
- A theory aims to account for the inductively
supported generalizations belonging to some
observation language. - Why believe in its entities, if its really just
used as a calculational device to capture such
generalizations? - Sellars says, if the generalizations really hold
up to the level of epistemic variance, then
there really is no reason to take the theory as
more than this. - But 1. We dont really know the things of the MI
exist, as we conceive them in the MI. - And 2. If they dont, then theres no guarantee
that the laws of a successful theory will
correspond to inductively justified
generalizations in the MI. - Instead, Sellars suggests that the SI will
explain why the things of the MI obey certain
generalizations, to the extent that they do. No
strict generalizations cast in MI terms survive
detailed careful examination.
38Towards Scientific Realism
- In principle, the SI could replace the MI in all
its uses, from observation to decision-making. - But this is not the time The MI provides a
constant background against which we can
check/compare the successes of scientific
theories. We dont want to lock in a particular
body of scientific theory yet. - But we still have some questions here. Just what
do we do with the (occurrent) properties of
physical objects, if we dont think anything
really has them, but we describe our sensations
in terms of an analogy with them?
393 Stages
- 1. Nothing is really coloured (only public
objects could be, and they are not). - 2. Sensations will persist, in some form, in the
SI but weve said they have properties analogous
to colour (etc.). So colours in some sense may
persist in the SI as features of states of
conscious, perceiving organisms. - 3. Persons in the MI are single logical subjects.
Thoughts and sense impressions, in particular,
are attributed to a single subject. The
framework in which we think this way must be
reconciled with a scientific description of
persons as complex structures built of many
separate parts.
40The place of persons
- But because these complex structures think of
themselves as subjects, the single logical
subject, a person, is important in their thinking
and behaviour. (The neo-Hobbesian position comes
in here 101f) - This is no longer a matter of describing what a
person is, but instead a matter of identifying a
subject for normative purposes. - To cope with sensations now, in our descriptive
theory, we need to separate them from the
grammatical subject (the I) who is said to have
them.
41Counterparts
- When we think of two theories that aim to
characterize the same thing, we can think of the
items/structures they each propose as
counterparts. - So here were concerned to identify the
counterparts of sensations as states of
perceivers, in the scientific image. - So where are these sensa? In the brain (i.e.
where the relevant physical events in the brain
are occurring). When I seem to see a red
triangle, a red-triangular sensum is occurring
in some (visual) region of my brain. - They dont seem to be in the brain, sure but
then, they dont seem at all we dont perceive
brain events in propria persona, in fact, we
dont really perceive them at all these things
are awarenesses (or something like that) not
items we are aware of. - Are we stuck with the primitive predicates of the
MI? Clearly not. Form must have content, but
content comes in other varieties than the
familiar ones.
42More on the SI view of ourselves
- Theories dont get their meanings from the
observation language they get meanings from
applications use. So the bridge laws (see
above) dont work as partial definitions, leaving
the rest of the theorys content up for grabs.
They merely coordinate different conceptual
frameworks, and allow us to use our grasp of one
to learn to apply/use the other. - The qualities of sensa may be found among the
contents of a scientific description of states
that occur in the brains of organisms like us. - The scientific image converts us into complexes,
multiplicities, even though we think of ourselves
as individuals. All the descriptive facts about
us must be re-framed to fit with this logical
shift the normative view of things is something
different, though.