Title: Logic
1Logic
2what is an argument?
- People argue all the time? that is, they have
arguments. - It is not often, however, that in the course of
having an argument people actually give an
argument. - Indeed, few of us have ever actually stopped to
consider what it means to give an argument or
what an argument is in the first place. - Yet, there is a whole discipline devoted to just
this logic.
3general definition
- An argument is a set of statements that includes
- at least one premise which is intended to support
(i.e. give reason to believe) - a conclusion.
- So according to this definition is the following
set of statements an argument? - Ms. Mayberry left to go to work this morning.
Whenever she does this, it rains. Therefore,
the moon is made of blue cheese.
4- Yes. We know this is an argument because of the
word therefore - Ms. Mayberry left to go to work this morning.
Whenever she does this, it rains. Therefore,
the moon is made of blue cheese. - This typically indicates that the final sentence
is intended to follow from (that is, be supported
by) the preceding sentences. - Of course, it is easy to see that this is not a
good argument. - The premises of the argument seem to be
irrelevant to (that is, they do not support) the
conclusion.
5other examples
- Does God exist?
- P1) If there is unnecessary evil in the world,
then God does not exist. - P2) There is unnecessary evil in the world.
- C) Therefore, God does not exist.
- Is ethics absolute or relative?
- P1) If there were absolute truth about morality,
then cultures would not disagree about morality. - P2) Cultures do disagree about morality.
- C) Therefore, there is no absolute truth about
morality.
6- The premises in these arguments may be true or
false. - Either way, in each of these examples the
premises support the conclusion. - That is, if they are true, then they give us
reason to believe the conclusion. - But this raises an important question
- What does it mean to say that premises of an
argument support the conclusion?
7- The move from the premises to the conclusion is
called an inference. - The premises support the conclusion only if the
inference is good. - Our question, then, concerns what it means for an
inference to be good.
8validity
- An argument is valid when it contains a good
deductive inference. - A deductive inference is good just in case, given
the truth of the premises, the conclusion must
also be true that is, if there is no way for
the premises to be true and the conclusion to be
false. - In short, the conclusion must be true, assuming
the truth of the premises. - It is extremely important to note that the above
definition does not say that the premises of the
argument are true. Rather we assume that the
premises are true and try to determine whether,
given this assumption, the conclusion must be
true as well.
9validity
- P1) If the animal in the barn is a pig, then it
is a mammal. - P2) The animal in the barn is a pig.
- Therefore, the animal in the barn is a mammal.
- The truth of the premises guarantees the truth of
the conclusion. - There is simply no rational way to accept the
truth of both premises and still deny the
conclusion. - That is why it is valid.
10validity
- P1) If the animal in the barn is a pig, then it
is a mammal. - P2) The animal in the barn has feathers and lays
eggs. - Therefore, the animal in the barn is a mammal.
- invalid
- The premises do not guarantee the conclusion.
11soundness
- Of course, valid arguments with obviously false
or highly controversial premises are of little
real value. - What we must strive for are arguments with
obviously true or relatively uncontroversial
premises. - That is, what we want are valid arguments with
true premises i.e., sound arguments. - A deductive argument is sound just in case the
argument is valid and, in addition, all of its
premises are true.
12- P1) If the animal in the barn is a pig, then it
is a mammal. - P2) The animal in the barn is a pig.
- C) Therefore, the animal in the barn is a mammal.
- valid
- sound
- P1) If the animal in the barn is a pig, then it
is purple. - P2) The animal in the barn is a pig.
- C) Therefore, the animal in the barn is purple.
- valid
- NOT sound
13deductive logical structure
- There is an important difference the form and the
content of an argument. - The form is its logical structure.
- The content is its subject matter, or what its
about. - Deductive arguments are valid because they
involve the right sort of logical structure. - Content is irrelevant for validity
- But not for soundness (why?).
14if-then conditionals
- The if-then conditional plays an important role
in many deductive arguments - P1) If Joe is a father, then he is a male.
- P2) Joe is a father.
- C) Therefore, he is a male.
- (P1 is a conditional) conditionals have two
parts - If Joe is a father (antecedent),
- then he is a male (consequent).
15- If Joe is a father, then he is a male.
- There are two valid things you can do with a
conditional - you can affirm the antecedent,
- or you can deny the consequent.
16modus ponens (affirming the antecedent)
- P1) If the moon is made of blue cheese, then pigs
fly. - P2) The moon is made of blue cheese.
- C) Therefore, pigs fly.
- P1) If its raining, then the streets are wet.
- P2) Its raining.
- C) Therefore, the streets are wet.
- These arguments bear an obvious similarity to one
another. This is because they both have the same
form. Roughly - P1) If this, then that. P1) p ? q
- P2) This. P2) p
- C) Therefore, that. C) Therefore, q.
17modus tollens (denying the consequent)
- P1) If the moon is made out of blue cheese, then
pigs fly. - P2) Pigs dont fly.
- C) Therefore, the moon is not made out of blue
cheese. - P1) If my car can get us to Denver, then it is
working properly. - P2) My car is not working properly.
- C) Therefore, my car cannot get us to Denver.
- Once again, these arguments bear an obvious
similarity to one another, which is the form - P1) If this, then that. P1) p ? q
- P2) Not that. P2) q
- C) Therefore, not this. C) Therefore, p
18- If Joe is a father, then he is a male.
- There are two invalid things you can do with a
conditional - you can deny the antecedent,
- or you can affirm the consequent.
19affirming the consequent
- P1) If the moon is made out of blue cheese, then
pigs fly. - P2) Pigs fly.
- C) Therefore, the moon is made out of blue
cheese. - P1) If my car can get us to Denver, then it is
working properly. - P2) My car is working properly.
- C) Therefore, my car can get us to Denver.
- Once again, these arguments bear an obvious
similarity to one another, which is the form - P1) If this, then that. P1) p ? q
- P2) That. P2) q
- C) Therefore, this. C) Therefore, p.
20denying the antecedent
- P1) If the moon is made of blue cheese, then pigs
fly. - P2) The moon is not made of blue cheese.
- C) Therefore, pigs dont fly.
- P1) If its raining, then the streets are wet.
- P2) Its not raining.
- C) Therefore, the streets are not wet.
- These arguments bear an obvious similarity to one
another. This is because they both have the same
form. Roughly - P1) If this, then that. P1) p ? q
- P2) Not This. P2) p
- C) Therefore, not that. C) Therefore, q.
21four if-then structures
Valid P1) If p, then q. P2) p. C) Therefore, q. Valid P1) If p, then q. P2) not q. C) Therefore, not p.
Invalid P1) If p, then q. P2) not p. C) Therefore, not q. Invalid P1) If p, then q. P2) q. C) Therefore, p.
22a question
- So, why is it valid to
- affirm the antecedent (modus ponens)
- deny the consequent (modus tollens)
- But not to
- affirm the consequent
- deny the antecedent
23- Consider the following premise
- If Joe is a father, then he is a male.
- If Joe is a father, does it follow that he is a
male? Yes. - This is modus ponens.
- If Joe is not a male, does it follow that he is
not a father? Yes. - This is modus tollens.
24- Consider the following premise
- If Joe is a father, then he is a male.
- If you know that Joe is a male, then can you
conclude that he must be a father? No. - This is affirming the consequent.
- If Joe is not a father, does it follow that he is
not a male? No. - This is denying the antecedent.
25formal fallacies
- It is important to realize that the reason that
these arguments forms are invalid is that their
logical structures do not guarantee the truth of
their conclusions. - Hence, these argument forms are always invalid.
- Because affirming the consequent and denying the
antecedent are fallacies that arise simply in
virtue of argument form, they are called formal
fallacies.
26necessary sufficient conditions
- An if-then conditional is composed of two
propositions, p and q, related by the connective
if, then (or ?). - The first proposition (i.e., the one that follows
the if) is part of the antecedent of the
conditional - The second proposition (i.e., the one that
follows the then) is part of the consequent.
27sufficient conditions
- Suppose I say, If you give birth to a baby, then
you are a mother. - What I am saying is that the antecedent (i.e.,
giving birth to a baby) is enough (it is all you
need) to make it true that you are a mother. - In general, we will say that the antecedent of a
conditional is a sufficient condition for its
consequent. - Thus, giving birth to a baby is a sufficient
condition for being a mother. - This is why modus ponens is deductively valid.
- p ? q
- p
- ? q
28necessary conditions
- p ? q means that p is enough (sufficient) for q
- It also means that q is required (necessary) for
p - So, if you give birth to a baby, you must be a
mother (being a mother is required). That is, you
cant have given birth to a baby, but not be a
mother. - In this way, the consequent of the conditional is
a necessary condition for its antecedent. If the
antecedent is true, then the consequent must be
true as well - Being a mother is a necessary condition for
giving birth to a baby. - This is why modus tollens is deductively valid.
- p ? q
- q
- ? p
29- If you give birth to a baby, then youre a
mother. - You giving birth is a sufficient condition for
being a mother. - So, youve given birth to a baby only if you are
a mother. - You being a mother is a necessary condition for
giving birth. - So, you are a mother if youve given birth to a
baby.
30another example
- P1) If Maria is alive, then shes breathing.
- The conditional (1st premise) states that
- Marias being alive is a sufficient condition for
her breathing. - So, on the assumption that we have the following
premise - P2) Maria is alive.
- It follows that
- C) She is breathing. (modus ponens)
- Conversely, Marias breathing is a necessary
condition for her being alive. - P2) Marias not breathing.
- C) Maria is not alive. (modus tollens)
31- If Maria is alive, then Maria is breathing.
- Marias being alive is a sufficient condition for
her breathing. - So, more generally, x is alive only if x is
breathing. - Marias breathing is a necessary condition for
her being alive. - So, more generally, x is breathing if x is alive.
32natural language if-thens
- If p, then q.
- Assuming p, q.
- Whenever p, q.
- Given p, q.
- Provided p, q.
- p only if q. (or Only if q, p.)
- A necessary condition of p is q.
33- p if q.
- This translates as if q, then p.
- So does
- p when q.
- p since q.
- p in case q.
- p so long as q.
- A sufficient condition of p is q.
34counterexamples
- An if-then conditional p ? q is false just in
case - p is not sufficient for q, or
- q is not necessary for p, or
- p is true while q is false.
- So, to show that a conditional is false, you must
show that the antecedent (p) is true but the
consequent (q) is false. - Such a situation is called a counterexample.
35lets consider some examples
- Being red is a ? condition for being scarlet.
- Being a horse is a ? condition for being a
mammal. - Being a female is a ? condition for being a
sister. - Being a father is a ? condition for being a
male. - Being tall is a ? condition for being a good BB
player.
36lets consider some examples
- Being red is a necessary condition for being
scarlet. - Being a horse is a sufficient condition for
being a mammal. - Being a female is a necessary condition for
being a sister. - Being a father is a sufficient condition for
being a male. - Being tall is a NEITHER condition for being a
good BB player.
37- Being red is a necessary condition for being
scarlet. - If the ball is scarlet, then it is red.
- If the ball is red, then it is scarlet.
- Being a father is a sufficient condition for
being a male. - If he is male, then he is a father.
- If he is a father, then he is male.
- Being a three sided figure is a BOTH for being
a triangle. - If it is a 3-sided figure, then it is a triangle.
- If it is a triangle, then it is a 3-sided figure.
38bi-conditionals
- x is a triangle only if x is a three-sided figure
(necessity) - x is a triangle if x is a three-sided figure
(sufficiency) - x is a triangle if and only if x is a three-sided
figure - The last says that being a three sided figure is
both necessary and sufficient for being a
triangle. - Since its the combination of two conditionals,
this is called a biconditional. - Conditional 1 x is a triangle ? x is a
three-sided figure - Conditional 2 x is a three-sided figure ? x is a
triangle - Bi-conditional x is a triangle ?? x is a
three-sided figure
39analysis
- In certain cases, to give necessary and
sufficient conditions is to give a definition or
an analysis. - To give an analysis of x is to state what x is.
- Analyses or definitions in our sense are not to
be confused with what you find in dictionaries,
which often simply list various uses of words
without stating what it is to be that to which
the words refer. - Since one of the primary aims of philosophy is to
understand the nature of things (to state what
they are), philosophers are particularly
interested in such biconditionals.
40- Consider a simple example of an analysis
- x is a bachelor if and only if
- (i) x is an adult,
- (ii) x is male, and
- (iii) x is unmarried.
- The first thing to notice is that the analysis is
stated as a biconditional (if and only if). - The second thing to notice is that we want
analyses to hold necessarily.
41- For example, it turns out that no bachelors are
over ten feet tall. - Does this mean that the following is a good
analysis? - x is a bachelor if and only if
- (i) x is an adult,
- (ii) x is male,
- (iii) x is unmarried, and
- (iv) x is under ten feet tall.
- This is not a good analysis.
- Why? Because an adult unmarried male over ten
feet tall would still be a bachelor. - In other words, being under ten feet tall is not
essential to being a bachelor its not part of
what it is to be a bachelor.
42counterexamples, again
- An analysis is false just in case
- there is a possible situation in which one side
holds while the other does not. - To show that an analysis is false you simply have
to find a possible situation in which one side of
the biconditional is true while the other side is
false that is, a possible situation in which
the truth-values of the two sides differ. - Again, this is called a counterexample.
43a philosophical example
- What is it to know that p (where p is any
proposition)? - Consider the view that knowledge is true belief.
- x knows that p iff
- (i) x believes that p, and
- (ii) it is true that p.
- In order to see if this is a good analysis, we
need to evaluate this biconditional. - To do this, we must ask
- Is each condition on the right hand side
necessary for knowledge? - Are the conditions on the right hand side jointly
sufficient for knowledge?
44in-class exercise
- Give an analysis of love.
- x loves y iff ?
45extra credit
- Evaluate the following analysis of parent
- x is a (biological) parent of y iff
- (i) x is an ancestor of y, and
- (ii) x is not an ancestor of an ancestor of y.
- Find a counterexample to this analysis. (There is
at least one.)