Logic - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

About This Presentation
Title:

Logic

Description:

... the conclusion. other examples Does God exist? P1) If there is unnecessary evil in the world, then God does not exist. P2) There is unnecessary evil in the world. – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:44
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 46
Provided by: JenWr5
Category:
Tags: does | exist | logic

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: Logic


1
Logic
2
what is an argument?
  • People argue all the time? that is, they have
    arguments.
  • It is not often, however, that in the course of
    having an argument people actually give an
    argument.
  • Indeed, few of us have ever actually stopped to
    consider what it means to give an argument or
    what an argument is in the first place.
  • Yet, there is a whole discipline devoted to just
    this logic.

3
general definition
  • An argument is a set of statements that includes
  • at least one premise which is intended to support
    (i.e. give reason to believe)
  • a conclusion.
  • So according to this definition is the following
    set of statements an argument?
  • Ms. Mayberry left to go to work this morning.
    Whenever she does this, it rains. Therefore,
    the moon is made of blue cheese.

4
  • Yes. We know this is an argument because of the
    word therefore
  • Ms. Mayberry left to go to work this morning.
    Whenever she does this, it rains. Therefore,
    the moon is made of blue cheese.
  • This typically indicates that the final sentence
    is intended to follow from (that is, be supported
    by) the preceding sentences.
  • Of course, it is easy to see that this is not a
    good argument.
  • The premises of the argument seem to be
    irrelevant to (that is, they do not support) the
    conclusion.

5
other examples
  • Does God exist?
  • P1) If there is unnecessary evil in the world,
    then God does not exist.
  • P2) There is unnecessary evil in the world.
  • C) Therefore, God does not exist.
  • Is ethics absolute or relative?
  • P1) If there were absolute truth about morality,
    then cultures would not disagree about morality.
  • P2) Cultures do disagree about morality.
  • C) Therefore, there is no absolute truth about
    morality.

6
  • The premises in these arguments may be true or
    false.
  • Either way, in each of these examples the
    premises support the conclusion.
  • That is, if they are true, then they give us
    reason to believe the conclusion.
  • But this raises an important question
  • What does it mean to say that premises of an
    argument support the conclusion?

7
  • The move from the premises to the conclusion is
    called an inference.
  • The premises support the conclusion only if the
    inference is good.
  • Our question, then, concerns what it means for an
    inference to be good.

8
validity
  • An argument is valid when it contains a good
    deductive inference.
  • A deductive inference is good just in case, given
    the truth of the premises, the conclusion must
    also be true that is, if there is no way for
    the premises to be true and the conclusion to be
    false.
  • In short, the conclusion must be true, assuming
    the truth of the premises.
  • It is extremely important to note that the above
    definition does not say that the premises of the
    argument are true. Rather we assume that the
    premises are true and try to determine whether,
    given this assumption, the conclusion must be
    true as well.

9
validity
  • P1) If the animal in the barn is a pig, then it
    is a mammal.
  • P2) The animal in the barn is a pig.
  • Therefore, the animal in the barn is a mammal.
  • The truth of the premises guarantees the truth of
    the conclusion.
  • There is simply no rational way to accept the
    truth of both premises and still deny the
    conclusion.
  • That is why it is valid.

10
validity
  • P1) If the animal in the barn is a pig, then it
    is a mammal.
  • P2) The animal in the barn has feathers and lays
    eggs.
  • Therefore, the animal in the barn is a mammal.
  • invalid
  • The premises do not guarantee the conclusion.

11
soundness
  • Of course, valid arguments with obviously false
    or highly controversial premises are of little
    real value.
  • What we must strive for are arguments with
    obviously true or relatively uncontroversial
    premises.
  • That is, what we want are valid arguments with
    true premises i.e., sound arguments.
  • A deductive argument is sound just in case the
    argument is valid and, in addition, all of its
    premises are true.

12
  • P1) If the animal in the barn is a pig, then it
    is a mammal.
  • P2) The animal in the barn is a pig.
  • C) Therefore, the animal in the barn is a mammal.
  • valid
  • sound
  • P1) If the animal in the barn is a pig, then it
    is purple.
  • P2) The animal in the barn is a pig.
  • C) Therefore, the animal in the barn is purple.
  • valid
  • NOT sound

13
deductive logical structure
  • There is an important difference the form and the
    content of an argument.
  • The form is its logical structure.
  • The content is its subject matter, or what its
    about.
  • Deductive arguments are valid because they
    involve the right sort of logical structure.
  • Content is irrelevant for validity
  • But not for soundness (why?).

14
if-then conditionals
  • The if-then conditional plays an important role
    in many deductive arguments
  • P1) If Joe is a father, then he is a male.
  • P2) Joe is a father.
  • C) Therefore, he is a male.
  • (P1 is a conditional) conditionals have two
    parts
  • If Joe is a father (antecedent),
  • then he is a male (consequent).

15
  • If Joe is a father, then he is a male.
  • There are two valid things you can do with a
    conditional
  • you can affirm the antecedent,
  • or you can deny the consequent.

16
modus ponens (affirming the antecedent)
  • P1) If the moon is made of blue cheese, then pigs
    fly.
  • P2) The moon is made of blue cheese.
  • C) Therefore, pigs fly.
  • P1) If its raining, then the streets are wet.
  • P2) Its raining.
  • C) Therefore, the streets are wet.
  • These arguments bear an obvious similarity to one
    another. This is because they both have the same
    form. Roughly
  • P1) If this, then that. P1) p ? q
  • P2) This. P2) p
  • C) Therefore, that. C) Therefore, q.

17
modus tollens (denying the consequent)
  • P1) If the moon is made out of blue cheese, then
    pigs fly.
  • P2) Pigs dont fly.
  • C) Therefore, the moon is not made out of blue
    cheese.
  • P1) If my car can get us to Denver, then it is
    working properly.
  • P2) My car is not working properly.
  • C) Therefore, my car cannot get us to Denver.
  • Once again, these arguments bear an obvious
    similarity to one another, which is the form
  • P1) If this, then that. P1) p ? q
  • P2) Not that. P2) q
  • C) Therefore, not this. C) Therefore, p

18
  • If Joe is a father, then he is a male.
  • There are two invalid things you can do with a
    conditional
  • you can deny the antecedent,
  • or you can affirm the consequent.

19
affirming the consequent
  • P1) If the moon is made out of blue cheese, then
    pigs fly.
  • P2) Pigs fly.
  • C) Therefore, the moon is made out of blue
    cheese.
  • P1) If my car can get us to Denver, then it is
    working properly.
  • P2) My car is working properly.
  • C) Therefore, my car can get us to Denver.
  • Once again, these arguments bear an obvious
    similarity to one another, which is the form
  • P1) If this, then that. P1) p ? q
  • P2) That. P2) q
  • C) Therefore, this. C) Therefore, p.

20
denying the antecedent
  • P1) If the moon is made of blue cheese, then pigs
    fly.
  • P2) The moon is not made of blue cheese.
  • C) Therefore, pigs dont fly.
  • P1) If its raining, then the streets are wet.
  • P2) Its not raining.
  • C) Therefore, the streets are not wet.
  • These arguments bear an obvious similarity to one
    another. This is because they both have the same
    form. Roughly
  • P1) If this, then that. P1) p ? q
  • P2) Not This. P2) p
  • C) Therefore, not that. C) Therefore, q.

21
four if-then structures
Valid P1) If p, then q. P2) p. C) Therefore, q. Valid P1) If p, then q. P2) not q. C) Therefore, not p.
Invalid P1) If p, then q. P2) not p. C) Therefore, not q. Invalid P1) If p, then q. P2) q. C) Therefore, p.
22
a question
  • So, why is it valid to
  • affirm the antecedent (modus ponens)
  • deny the consequent (modus tollens)
  • But not to
  • affirm the consequent
  • deny the antecedent

23
  • Consider the following premise
  • If Joe is a father, then he is a male.
  • If Joe is a father, does it follow that he is a
    male? Yes.
  • This is modus ponens.
  • If Joe is not a male, does it follow that he is
    not a father? Yes.
  • This is modus tollens.

24
  • Consider the following premise
  • If Joe is a father, then he is a male.
  • If you know that Joe is a male, then can you
    conclude that he must be a father? No.
  • This is affirming the consequent.
  • If Joe is not a father, does it follow that he is
    not a male? No.
  • This is denying the antecedent.

25
formal fallacies
  • It is important to realize that the reason that
    these arguments forms are invalid is that their
    logical structures do not guarantee the truth of
    their conclusions.
  • Hence, these argument forms are always invalid.
  • Because affirming the consequent and denying the
    antecedent are fallacies that arise simply in
    virtue of argument form, they are called formal
    fallacies.

26
necessary sufficient conditions
  • An if-then conditional is composed of two
    propositions, p and q, related by the connective
    if, then (or ?).
  • The first proposition (i.e., the one that follows
    the if) is part of the antecedent of the
    conditional
  • The second proposition (i.e., the one that
    follows the then) is part of the consequent.

27
sufficient conditions
  • Suppose I say, If you give birth to a baby, then
    you are a mother.
  • What I am saying is that the antecedent (i.e.,
    giving birth to a baby) is enough (it is all you
    need) to make it true that you are a mother.
  • In general, we will say that the antecedent of a
    conditional is a sufficient condition for its
    consequent.
  • Thus, giving birth to a baby is a sufficient
    condition for being a mother.
  • This is why modus ponens is deductively valid.
  • p ? q
  • p
  • ? q

28
necessary conditions
  • p ? q means that p is enough (sufficient) for q
  • It also means that q is required (necessary) for
    p
  • So, if you give birth to a baby, you must be a
    mother (being a mother is required). That is, you
    cant have given birth to a baby, but not be a
    mother.
  • In this way, the consequent of the conditional is
    a necessary condition for its antecedent. If the
    antecedent is true, then the consequent must be
    true as well
  • Being a mother is a necessary condition for
    giving birth to a baby.
  • This is why modus tollens is deductively valid.
  • p ? q
  • q
  • ? p

29
  • If you give birth to a baby, then youre a
    mother.
  • You giving birth is a sufficient condition for
    being a mother.
  • So, youve given birth to a baby only if you are
    a mother.
  • You being a mother is a necessary condition for
    giving birth.
  • So, you are a mother if youve given birth to a
    baby.

30
another example
  • P1) If Maria is alive, then shes breathing.
  • The conditional (1st premise) states that
  • Marias being alive is a sufficient condition for
    her breathing.
  • So, on the assumption that we have the following
    premise
  • P2) Maria is alive.
  • It follows that
  • C) She is breathing. (modus ponens)
  • Conversely, Marias breathing is a necessary
    condition for her being alive.
  • P2) Marias not breathing.
  • C) Maria is not alive. (modus tollens)

31
  • If Maria is alive, then Maria is breathing.
  • Marias being alive is a sufficient condition for
    her breathing.
  • So, more generally, x is alive only if x is
    breathing.
  • Marias breathing is a necessary condition for
    her being alive.
  • So, more generally, x is breathing if x is alive.

32
natural language if-thens
  • If p, then q.
  • Assuming p, q.
  • Whenever p, q.
  • Given p, q.
  • Provided p, q.
  • p only if q. (or Only if q, p.)
  • A necessary condition of p is q.

33
  • p if q.
  • This translates as if q, then p.
  • So does
  • p when q.
  • p since q.
  • p in case q.
  • p so long as q.
  • A sufficient condition of p is q.

34
counterexamples
  • An if-then conditional p ? q is false just in
    case
  • p is not sufficient for q, or
  • q is not necessary for p, or
  • p is true while q is false.
  • So, to show that a conditional is false, you must
    show that the antecedent (p) is true but the
    consequent (q) is false.
  • Such a situation is called a counterexample.

35
lets consider some examples
  • Being red is a ? condition for being scarlet.
  • Being a horse is a ? condition for being a
    mammal.
  • Being a female is a ? condition for being a
    sister.
  • Being a father is a ? condition for being a
    male.
  • Being tall is a ? condition for being a good BB
    player.

36
lets consider some examples
  • Being red is a necessary condition for being
    scarlet.
  • Being a horse is a sufficient condition for
    being a mammal.
  • Being a female is a necessary condition for
    being a sister.
  • Being a father is a sufficient condition for
    being a male.
  • Being tall is a NEITHER condition for being a
    good BB player.

37
  • Being red is a necessary condition for being
    scarlet.
  • If the ball is scarlet, then it is red.
  • If the ball is red, then it is scarlet.
  • Being a father is a sufficient condition for
    being a male.
  • If he is male, then he is a father.
  • If he is a father, then he is male.
  • Being a three sided figure is a BOTH for being
    a triangle.
  • If it is a 3-sided figure, then it is a triangle.
  • If it is a triangle, then it is a 3-sided figure.

38
bi-conditionals
  • x is a triangle only if x is a three-sided figure
    (necessity)
  • x is a triangle if x is a three-sided figure
    (sufficiency)
  • x is a triangle if and only if x is a three-sided
    figure
  • The last says that being a three sided figure is
    both necessary and sufficient for being a
    triangle.
  • Since its the combination of two conditionals,
    this is called a biconditional.
  • Conditional 1 x is a triangle ? x is a
    three-sided figure
  • Conditional 2 x is a three-sided figure ? x is a
    triangle
  • Bi-conditional x is a triangle ?? x is a
    three-sided figure

39
analysis
  • In certain cases, to give necessary and
    sufficient conditions is to give a definition or
    an analysis.
  • To give an analysis of x is to state what x is.
  • Analyses or definitions in our sense are not to
    be confused with what you find in dictionaries,
    which often simply list various uses of words
    without stating what it is to be that to which
    the words refer.
  • Since one of the primary aims of philosophy is to
    understand the nature of things (to state what
    they are), philosophers are particularly
    interested in such biconditionals.

40
  • Consider a simple example of an analysis
  • x is a bachelor if and only if
  • (i) x is an adult,
  • (ii) x is male, and
  • (iii) x is unmarried.
  • The first thing to notice is that the analysis is
    stated as a biconditional (if and only if).
  • The second thing to notice is that we want
    analyses to hold necessarily.

41
  • For example, it turns out that no bachelors are
    over ten feet tall.
  • Does this mean that the following is a good
    analysis?
  • x is a bachelor if and only if
  • (i) x is an adult,
  • (ii) x is male,
  • (iii) x is unmarried, and
  • (iv) x is under ten feet tall.
  • This is not a good analysis.
  • Why? Because an adult unmarried male over ten
    feet tall would still be a bachelor.
  • In other words, being under ten feet tall is not
    essential to being a bachelor its not part of
    what it is to be a bachelor.

42
counterexamples, again
  • An analysis is false just in case
  • there is a possible situation in which one side
    holds while the other does not.
  • To show that an analysis is false you simply have
    to find a possible situation in which one side of
    the biconditional is true while the other side is
    false that is, a possible situation in which
    the truth-values of the two sides differ.
  • Again, this is called a counterexample.

43
a philosophical example
  • What is it to know that p (where p is any
    proposition)?
  • Consider the view that knowledge is true belief.
  • x knows that p iff
  • (i) x believes that p, and
  • (ii) it is true that p.
  • In order to see if this is a good analysis, we
    need to evaluate this biconditional.
  • To do this, we must ask
  • Is each condition on the right hand side
    necessary for knowledge?
  • Are the conditions on the right hand side jointly
    sufficient for knowledge?

44
in-class exercise
  • Give an analysis of love.
  • x loves y iff ?

45
extra credit
  • Evaluate the following analysis of parent
  • x is a (biological) parent of y iff
  • (i) x is an ancestor of y, and
  • (ii) x is not an ancestor of an ancestor of y.
  • Find a counterexample to this analysis. (There is
    at least one.)
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com