REALISM AND EXTERNAL WORLD OBJECTS - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 51
About This Presentation
Title:

REALISM AND EXTERNAL WORLD OBJECTS

Description:

... the next person I meet on campus will probably be similarly interesting. ... These are different particular facts, and Stace wants to know how could I reason ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:108
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 52
Provided by: JeffSt6
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: REALISM AND EXTERNAL WORLD OBJECTS


1
REALISM AND EXTERNAL WORLD OBJECTS
  • Stace (1886-1967) defines realism as the view
    that some entities sometimes exist without being
    experienced by any mind.
  • realismdf. To be real is to exist apart from
    perception. Gould
  • Both of these assertions about realism concern
    objects in the external world. A realist
    believes, with common sense, that ordinary
    objects like tables dont go out of existence
    when no one is looking at them, touching them and
    so forth.

2
EXISTENCE AND KNOWLEDGE
  • Realists believe that objects exist when no one
    is aware of them. This is because realism asserts
    that knowledge or awareness makes no difference
    to the object - the object might exist without
    being known or whether anyone is conscious of it
    or not.
  • For realism, there is no necessary relation
    between the existence of an external world object
    and mind. (This is something that Berkeley will
    assert is necessary.) Accordingly, realism
    asserts that objects could possibly exist apart
    from minds.
  • But Stace says realists assert more than that
    objects might exist apart from minds. Rather,
    they assert that they do exist apart from minds.

3
EXISTENCE, PERCEPTION, BELIEF, AND PROOF
  • Stace To refute the proposition that objects
    continue to exist apart from perception is to
    refute realism.
  • However, Stace says that he cant prove that
    realism is false, that it is false that objects
    exist when not being perceived. Instead, all he
    can prove, or will attempt to prove is that we
    dont have the slightest reason to believe that
    objects continue to exist when not being
    perceived.
  • And Stace will say that, since we have no
    evidence or reason to believe that things exist
    when we are not perceiving them, we ought not to
    believe that they do exist when not being
    perceived.

4
BURDEN OF PROOF
  • Stace says that, strictly speaking, he cannot
    prove that realism is false. However, he says
    that the realist cannot prove that it is true.
    And Stace thinks that the burden of proof is on
    the realist that objects exist unperceived. This
    is because there is no evidence that they do, and
    there is no reason to believe that they do.
  • For Stace, believing in the existence of
    unperceived objects is like believing in a
    unicorn on Mars. He cant prove that there is no
    unicorn on Mars, but since there is not the
    slightest evidence or reason to believe that
    there is one, we shouldnt believe that there is
    one. (This is like my invisible rhinoceros.)

5
EXTERNAL WORLD OBJECTS AS PHYSICAL
  • Stace It makes no difference to the refutation
    of realism whether or not external world objects,
    like tables and chairs, are physical objects as
    common sense and science both suppose. He says
    he will assume that they are physical.
  • However, even as physical we cannot know that
    they exist unperceived. And because we cannot
    know that they do, there is no reason to assert
    that physical objects do exist when no mind is
    perceiving them.

6
OBJECTS AND KNOWLEDGE
  • For Stace, objects can only be known or proved to
    exist when they are objects of perception and not
    otherwise.
  • Thinking that physical objects exist apart from
    perception is unwarranted, and ought not to be
    believed.
  • Stace Realism can be refuted if it can be shown
    that we do not know that any single entity
    exists unexperienced.

7
HOW COULD WE KNOW THAT OBJECTS EXIST UNPERCEIVED?
  • Even if objects do exist as a matter of fact,
    Stace wants to know how we could possibly know
    that they do. How can a philosopher prove that
    we know that objects exist unperceived?
  • Stace There is no possible way in which we
    could know this, we do not know this, and so we
    have no reason to believe it.
  • Where could a realist have gotten the knowledge
    that his desk existed in his study when he was
    away for the day? And if he says that he knows
    that it did, how could that knowledge be
    justified?

8
SENSE PERCEPTION AND INFERENCE I
  • There are only two ways in which it could be
    asserted that the existence of an external world
    object of perception ( a sense-object) such as
    a desk can be established.
  • 1. By perception.
  • 2. By inference based upon perception.
  • For instance, I think that objects in this room
    now exist because I see them. That is knowledge
    of objects through perception. On the other
    hand, I can infer that a person in the hallway
    exists because I hear footsteps. The object of
    perception is the footsteps. And I can infer
    from the auditory perception of these things that
    a person exists in the hallway.

9
SENSE PERCEPTION AND INFERENCE II
  • Knowledge of objects in perception is stronger
    epistemologically than inference, since it is
    always possible that the inference is incorrect.
    For instance, maybe a tape recorder has been left
    in the hall which plays sounds of footsteps when
    no one is really there.
  • Of course, even direct perception is not
    conclusive evidence that external world objects
    exist. This is because of the kind of skeptical
    arguments which we have already seen. Stace does
    not pursue this, since his aim is not to try to
    prove what we do know, but what we dont know -
    namely, that objects exist apart from perception.

10
SENSE PERCEPTION AND KNOWLEDGE OF UNPERCEIVED
OBJECTS
  • We cannot confirm that an object exists apart
    from perception in perception, since this would
    be to say that we are both perceiving and not
    perceiving the same object at the same time.
  • That is, if I want to know if my desk exists
    apart from my perceiving it, I cant use
    perception to see that it exists unperceived,
    since if I am perceiving it, then I am not also
    not perceiving it. And if I am not perceiving
    it, then I am not also perceiving it.
  • (Both of the two previous assertions involve a
    law of logic. What is it?)

11
DEDUCTION
  • Induction and deduction are both kinds of
    inference, or kinds of reasoning from premises to
    conclusions.
  • If the premises of a deductive argument are true,
    then its conclusion follows necessarily from its
    premises. Or, the premises cannot be true while
    the conclusion is false. An example is All
    people are mortal, Socrates is a person,
    therefore Socrates is mortal. It cannot be true
    that all people die, and that Socrates is a
    person without its being the case that Socrates
    will die.

12
INDUCTION
  • There is no such necessary relation between
    premises and conclusion in an inductive argument.
    That the conclusion follows from the premises is
    probable only, not certain. I reason inductively
    when I say Most of the people who I have met to
    this point at IPFW have been interesting people.
    Therefore I expect that the next person I meet on
    campus will probably be similarly interesting.

13
INDUCTIVE INFERENCE AND KNOWLEDGE OF UNPERCEIVED
OBJECTS I
  • Stace Inductive reasoning proceeds always upon
    the basis that what has been found in certain
    observed cases to be true will also be true in
    unobserved cases. For instance, if every stop
    sign that I have seen has been red, I reason
    inductively that stop signs that I have not seen
    are also red.
  • However, I cannot observe that an object, like
    the desk in my study, exists when I am not there
    to observe it. Since inductive reasoning depends
    on observed instances to formulate a conclusion,
    and I cant observe something which I am not
    observing, there is no way for me to formulate an
    inductive generalization about the existence of
    unobserved entities.

14
INDUCTIVE INFERENCE AND KNOWLEDGE OF UNPERCEIVED
OBJECTS II
  • In inductive reasoning we expect the future to
    resemble the past. For example, we reason
    inductively about a particular object like the
    sun when we expect it to come up tomorrow. And
    we reason inductively about a kind of object like
    apples when we expect future apples to taste like
    past apples.
  • However, this reasoning is probable only, not
    certain, based on our past experience. Perhaps
    the sun will not come up tomorrow, and perhaps
    the next apple I eat will taste like a bowl of
    chili. Each of these is logically possible, that
    is, is not intrinsically contradictory.

15
INDUCTIVE INFERENCE AND KNOWLEDGE OF UNPERCEIVED
OBJECTS III
  • I cannot reason inductively from the fact that I
    see my desk each time that I enter my study that
    it exists when I am not in my study to see it.
    These are different particular facts, and Stace
    wants to know how could I reason from the fact of
    the first kind to the fact of the second kind?
  • Here is what I can say Each time I have entered
    my study I have seen my desk. Therefore, the
    next time that I go into my study I will probably
    see my desk.
  • Here is what I cannot say Each time I have
    entered my study I have seen my desk. Therefore,
    my desk exists when I am not perceiving it.

16
DEDUCTIVE INFERENCE AND KNOWLEDGE OF UNPERCEIVED
OBJECTS I
  • Deductive inference is formal inference, and
    Stace notes that deductive inference depends on
    the principle of consistency. From PeQ (if P
    then Q) all that we can deduce is that P and Q
    (not-Q) are inconsistent or that P cant be true
    and Q false or that we cant hold P and Q
    together, although either can be held separately.
  • If P cannot be true while Q is false, then there
    is a necessary or analytic relation between P and
    Q.

17
DEDUCTIVE INFERENCE AND KNOWLEDGE OF UNPERCEIVED
OBJECTS II
  • For instance, let Px is a triangle, and let Qx
    has three sides. Then our deductive inference
    is if x is a triangle, then x has three sides
    (PeQ). P cannot be true and Q false, since then
    our inference would read if x is a triangle,
    then it is false that x has three sides (PeQ).
  • Now let Pmy desk exists when I am looking at it,
    and let Qmy desk exists when I am not looking at
    it. Now, PeQ reads like this if it is true
    that my desk exists when I am looking at it, then
    it is false that it exists when I am not looking
    at it. But this is not internally inconsistent,
    and it simply means that it is logically possible
    that my desk exists when I am perceiving it, but
    does not exist when I am not perceiving it.

18
DEDUCTIVE INFERENCE AND KNOWLEDGE OF UNPERCEIVED
OBJECTS III
  • Thus, whereas there is a necessary or analytic
    relation between triangularity and
    three-sidedness, there is no similar necessary or
    analytic relation between some things existing
    when it is perceived, and that same things
    existing when it is not being perceived.
  • There is nothing contradictory in maintaining
    that no external world object exists when not
    being perceived that does exist when it is being
    perceived.
  • And so we cant use deduction to establish the
    existence of unperceived objects.

19
CONCLUSIONS ABOUT INFERRING THE EXISTENCE OF
EXTERNAL WORLD OBJECTS APART FROM PERCEPTION
BASED ON PERCEPTION
  • Stace No valid inference from an experienced to
    an unexperienced existence is possible.
  • Stace quotes Russell, a realist, here in defense
    of this position Belief in the existence of
    things outside of my own biography must, from the
    standpoint of theoretical logic, be regarded as a
    prejudice, not as a well-grounded theory.
  • Therefore Stace says that the burden of proving
    that we know that objects exist apart from
    perception is on the realist who asserts it, and
    not on the philosopher who wants to know how it
    is possible to know that they do.

20
LOVEJOYS CAUSAL ARGUMENT
  • A. O. Lovejoy attempted to prove that objects
    exist unperceived by arguing that causal
    relations which hold between objects which are
    being perceived continue to hold when they are
    not being perceived.
  • For Lovejoy, if causal laws continue to operate
    when we are not aware of them, then the objects
    which such causal operations concern must also
    exist when we are not perceiving them.

21
AN EXAMPLE OF LOVEJOYS CAUSAL ARGUMENT
  • For example, a causal law of combustion holds
    when we watch fire burn logs and turn them to
    ashes. Suppose then that we light a fire, leave
    the room for a couple of hours, and come back and
    find ashes. Lovejoy says that we have a right to
    infer that the causal law of combustion relevant
    here - that fire turns logs to ashes - which
    operates when we watch fires burn, continues to
    operate in our absence.

22
STACES RESPONSE TO LOVEJOYS CAUSAL ARGUMENT I
  • For Lovejoy, because we left burning logs and
    returned to find ashes, we can infer that the
    fire continued to exist when not being perceived,
    and we can assume that causality continued to
    operate as normal. He takes this to prove the
    existence of unperceived objects.
  • Stace correctly notes that this is a petitio
    principii - begging the question. What
    Lovejoys argument is attempting to prove is that
    the fire burns in our absence, but this is
    precisely what the argument assumes.
  • Stace wants to know how can we know that
    causality continues to operate apart from
    perception as it does in perception? Arent we
    simply assuming that it does?

23
STACES RESPONSE TO LOVEJOYS CAUSAL ARGUMENT II
  • Stace points out that unexperienced processes -
    like the burning of logs - and unexperienced laws
    - like a law of combustion - are in the same
    position epistemologically as unexperienced
    objects like desks.
  • We cant prove that causal laws continue to
    operate in the way in which they have operated
    when we have observed objects which they concern.
    We cant infer that a law of causality continues
    to operate apart from minds simply because we
    have evidence for that law operating when we are
    perceiving objects.

24
STACES RESPONSE TO LOVEJOYS CAUSAL ARGUMENT III
  • It is logically possible - not inconsistent -
    that you left the room with a burning fire and
    came back to find ashes, and that nothing
    continued to exist in your absence.
  • Leaving a burning fire and returning to find
    ashes is consistent with nothing at all existing
    in the time that you are gone. This is as
    possible as that logs continued to burn in your
    absence. You are simply assuming that the latter
    is the case, not the former. But Stace says that
    you have no philosophical right to make that
    assumption.

25
CAUSALITY, PERCEPTION, AND DEDUCTION
  • You cannot perceive that the logs continued to
    burn in your absence since, as absent, you were
    not there to perceive it.
  • You cannot infer deductively that, because fire
    consumes logs in your presence (P), therefore
    fire consumes logs in your absence (Q). This is
    because P and Q, is not inconsistent, or there
    is no logical reason why causality which operates
    in perception must operate apart from perception.
    The burden of proof is on the realist who
    maintains that things continue to exist
    unperceived, and that causality continues to
    operate in cases where it is not observed to
    operate.

26
CAUSALITY AND INDUCTION
  • You cannot infer inductively that logs continued
    to burn in your absence since you are trying to
    connect different kinds of thing. You can reason
    inductively like this each time that I have
    built a fire and watched it burn, the fire
    consumes the logs and turns them to ashes.
    Therefore, the next time that I light a fire, it
    will probably convert the logs to ashes. But you
    cannot reason like this each time that I have
    built a fire and watched it burn, the fire
    consumes the logs and turns them to ashes.
    Therefore, the fire continues to burn in my
    absence.

27
MOORE AND THE ACT-OBJECT DISTINCTION I
  • We have seen that we need to make a distinction
    between the act or event of perception and the
    object of perception - your seeing of this slide
    is one thing and the slide seen is another.
  • G. E. Moore (1873-1958) says that a sense datum
    like green is distinct from the awareness of
    green. He reasons like this a green sense datum
    is different from a blue sense datum, and yet
    each has awareness in common. Our awareness
    (sensation) of green is not blue, and our
    awareness of blue is not green. Since each sense
    datum is different, and each has visual sensation
    in common, then we have to make a distinction
    between the act of awareness and the object of
    awareness.

28
MOORE AND THE ACT-OBJECT DISTINCTION II
  • If a sense datum is distinct from the sensation
    of it, then the sense datum could exist apart
    from the sensation of it - e.g. if green is
    distinct from the awareness of green, then green
    could exist independently of any awareness of it.
  • Stace Possibly this argument of Moores
    proves that green is not mental. I do not know
    whether it proves this or not, but the point is
    unimportant, since I have already admitted that
    sense data like patches of green are not
    mental. He has also admitted that objects like
    desks and logs are physical, not mental.

29
STACE ON MOORE
  • Stace Whatever Moores argument proves, it
    certainly does not prove that unexperienced
    entities exist.
  • Even if green is physical, independent of mind,
    or exists when being perceived, it does not
    follow that it is physical, independent of mind,
    or continues to exist when it is not being
    perceived.
  • Perhaps an object begins to exist when an act of
    perceiving it begins, continues to exist for the
    duration of the act of perception, and ceases to
    exist when the act of perceiving it ceases. This
    is logically possible, and, Stace says, this is
    exactly what we find in experience.

30
THE EXISTENCE OF OBJECTS AND OTHER MINDS I
  • What is Staces position about the existence of
    external world objects in relation to other
    minds? He does not directly say, but seems to
    imply that he will accept the testimony of others
    that an object exists when he, Stace, is not
    aware of it. That is, Stace seems to accept that
    a table exists which he is not perceiving it, as
    long as someone else is perceiving it.
  • Note the following language in relation to the
    existence of a piece of paper which he, Stace, is
    not perceiving I am at this moment experiencing
    it, and at this moment it exists, he knows that
    because he is perceiving it but how can I know
    that it existed last night in my desk when, so
    far as I know, no mind some mind other than his
    own was experiencing it? How can I know that it
    will continue to exist tonight when there is no
    one in the room? Stace or anyone else.

31
THE EXISTENCE OF OBJECTS AND OTHER MINDS II
  • The language of the preceding quote seems to
    suggest that Stace is willing to accept the
    testimony of others that objects exist of which
    he, or any particular person, is not aware.
    Thus, although you are here on campus, and so not
    perceiving any of your furniture at home, you
    could accept that those items of furniture exist
    of which someone other than you is aware.
  • This would mean that a sufficient condition of
    any objects existing is that at least one person
    is aware of it in perception. If that is the
    case, then it is not a necessary condition that I
    am aware of it for it to exist.

32
THE EXISTENCE OF OBJECTS AND OTHER MINDS III
  • A more thoroughgoing skeptic might challenge
    Stace here, and suggest that the existence of
    other minds are in the same position, relative to
    his own mind, as is the existence of tables and
    chairs apart from awareness. That is, we can
    only perceive directly the body of another
    person, not her mind. Why then should we accept
    the testimony of another person if we have no way
    to confirm that she can perceive things at all?
  • On the other hand, if a person were not to accept
    the testimony of others, then the existence of
    all objects in the external world would be tied
    to his perception of them, and he would be locked
    epistemologically in the egocentric predicament -
    external world objects would be strictly relative
    to his perception of them, and he would not be
    able to argue beyond the sphere of his own
    experience.

33
SUMMARY OF STACES VIEW
  • Stace maintains that we only have evidence that
    external world objects exist when we are
    perceiving them, and that we cannot reason that
    they exist apart from perception by using
    deductive, inductive, or causal arguments.
  • Because we have no evidence that objects exist
    apart from perception, and no argument can be
    provided that they exist unperceived, we ought
    not to believe that they exist apart from
    perception. Instead, we should believe that
    their existence is strictly correlated with our
    acts of perceiving them, such that, when our
    event of perceiving an object begins, so that
    object begins to exist, and when our perceiving
    it ends, so the object ceases to exist.
  • This thesis is supported by experience and that
    is what we ought to believe.

34
DIAGRAM OF STACES POSITION
  • Object x at t1 Object x at t2
  • 8 8
  • Act a at t1 Act b at t2
  • Object x is an external world object like a desk.
    Both act a and act b are acts of perceiving it,
    such as seeing it or touching it. Time t2 is
    some time later than t1, and the interval between
    t1 and t2 could be a second, a minute, an hour,
    or whatever. For Stace there is no reason to
    suppose that x exists at any time between t1 and
    t2..Instead, we should expect that x comes into
    existence at t1 when a begins and ceases to exist
    when a ceases to exist. It then comes into
    existence again at t2 when b begins, and ends
    whenever b ends. Thus, the existence of objects
    is strictly correlated with (8) their perception.

35
STACE AND THE VIDEO CAMERA I
  • Recall Staces objection to Lovejoy, that he is
    simply assuming that causality continues to
    operate apart from perception as it does in
    perception. Stace says that we can no more know
    that causal laws continue to hold apart from
    awareness than we can know that the objects which
    the laws are supposed to concern continue to
    exist.
  • A variation on Lovejoy Imagine that a video
    camera were set up in front of the fire with a
    blank tape and was set to record the burning of
    the logs. You leave the room with the fire
    burning and return two hours later to find ashes
    where the logs were. You remove the tape from the
    camera, place it in a VCR, and watch a two hour
    tape of a fire burning. At the end of the tape
    the logs have been converted to ashes. Let us
    further assume that there are no ways into or out
    of the room other than a single door, and two
    guards are posted outside of the door during the
    period of recording.

36
STACE AND THE VIDEO CAMERA II
  • Does this prove conclusively that the fire
    continued to burn in your absence? If the proof
    is not conclusive, does it nevertheless add
    support to the realists hypothesis? How might
    Stace respond to the suggestion that the camera
    adds support to realism? Notice that the camera
    is being considered as a kind of surrogate
    perceiver, or another kind of non-human mind. Do
    you think that Stace would be willing to see a
    camera as a legitimate source of knowledge of the
    external world? If not, what property or
    properties does a human mind have which a camera
    lacks which makes it credible to tie the
    existence of external world objects to such a
    mind and not to a camera?

37
OBJECTIONS TO STACE I
  • Stace Saying that objects exist unperceived is
    like saying that a unicorn exists on Mars. The
    two are alike, he thinks, because there is no
    evidence for either, but is that really the case?
    And are the two really alike?
  • It would not seem so. The difference is the way
    in which data relates to each hypothesis. The
    hypothesis that a unicorn exists on Mars, is not
    supported by the data. However, the hypothesis
    that objects continue to exist unperceived is
    supported by the data.

38
OBJECTIONS TO STACE II
  • That is, if objects do exist apart from
    perception, then wouldnt I expect to see my desk
    each time that I enter my study? And isnt that
    exactly what I do find? This is what I mean by
    saying that the hypothesis is supported by the
    data.
  • On the other hand, if a unicorn did exist on Mars
    we would expect to find data that we do not in
    fact find. Thus the cases are not the same.

39
RUSSELL VS. STACE ON REALISM I
  • Recall that Russell says that Belief in the
    existence of things outside of my own biography
    must, from the standpoint of theoretical logic,
    be regarded as a prejudice, not as a
    well-grounded theory. This means that, although
    we believe it to be true, we cannot prove that it
    is true. Why then is Russell a realist?
  • Although Russell would admit that it is logically
    possible that objects come into and go out of
    existence with our perceptions of them, that
    there is no reason to suppose that it is true.

40
TWO POSSIBLE THEORIES
  • Theory 1 is that objects like desks come into
    existence when we perceive them, and go out of
    existence when we cease to perceive them. Theory
    2 is that objects like desks exist whether we
    perceive them or not.
  • Remember that Stace says that we cannot prove
    that objects exist unperceived, and that the
    hypothesis that their existence is paired with
    our perceptions of them is what we find in fact
    in experience. (Theory 1.)
  • However, even though the evidence is consistent
    with this hypothesis, it is also consistent with
    the hypothesis that objects which we perceive
    were waiting there to be found by perception.
    This is logically possible too, and is also
    consistent with our experience. (Theory 2.)

41
OCKHAMS RAZOR
  • Ockhams razordf. Entities are not to be
    multiplied beyond necessity.
  • Ockhams razor means the following things Do not
    use anything in your theory which you do not
    need. Keep it simple. Do not introduce
    complexity to account for whatever it is which
    you are trying to explain unless it is absolutely
    necessary. Less is (usually) more.
  • This is a principle of simplicity or economy.
    Applied to theories it says this Of any two
    theories which explain the phenomena equally, the
    simpler of the theories is to be preferred.

42
RUSSELL VS. STACE ON REALISM II
  • Russell says that Theory 2 is simpler than Theory
    1, and therefore better.
  • Isnt it simpler for objects to continue to exist
    whether anyone is aware of them or not? Why
    should they go into and out of existence strictly
    correlated with events of perception? Doesnt it
    make science simpler to suppose that the
    existence of objects is independent of
    perception?
  • Because each theory accounts for the phenomena,
    but Theory 2 is simpler than Theory 1, Theory 2
    is to be preferred to Theory 1.

43
RUSSELL VS. STACE ON REALISM III
  • According to Russell, not only does the principal
    of simplicity favor the existence of unperceived
    objects (Theory 2), but Theory 2 leaves
    undiminished our instinctive belief that there
    are objects corresponding to our sense-data.
  • For Russell, because Theory 2 leads to no
    philosophical difficulties, is simpler than
    Theory 1, and accords with common sense notions
    which accord with instinctive beliefs, there is
    no reason for rejecting it.
  • Further, Russell says that all knowledge must be
    built up upon our instinctive beliefs, and if
    these are rejected, nothing is left. except
    extreme skepticism

44
NAIVE REALISM
  • Naive realismdf. Objects retain the properties
    which they have in perception apart from
    perception. For instance, a table which is both
    brown and rectangular in perception is brown and
    rectangular when no one is looking at it.
  • Many philosophers maintain that naive realism is
    false, while holding that some version of realism
    is true. For instance, a representative realist
    like Locke will maintain that only some
    properties of an object like a table which are
    known in perception are retained by the object
    apart from perception. Those which are retained
    by the object whether anyone is aware of them or
    not are called primary qualities. Those which
    are not retained by the object when it is not
    being perceived are called secondary qualities.
    (See the handout on this.)
  • Other realists, such as Russell, maintain that
    physical objects are vastly different from what
    we are aware of in perception, and do not retain
    either the secondary or the primary qualities
    which they have in perception when they are not
    being perceived. Russell is a scientific
    realist.

45
SCIENTIFIC REALISM I
  • Scientific realismdf. There is a
    mind-independent reality which the physical
    sciences, such as physics, investigate. This
    mind-independent reality is the external world.
    As mind-independent, no particular scientist has
    privileged access to the external world. In this
    sense it is a public space equally accessible to
    investigating intellects. The publicity of the
    external world contrasts with the privacy of each
    person's internal world, the world to which
    he/she alone has privileged access.
  • Our understanding of the nature of the physical
    world can change in accordance with the
    development of new models for interpreting
    reality. With these models can come a different
    understanding of the fundamental constituents of
    matter. Professor Duchovic "The entities we call
    electrons, protons, neutrons, and quarks are
    simply our BEST MODEL of this external world.
    This model may change in the future when there is
    collective evidence suggesting that the external
    world is not well-represented by the prevailing
    model."

46
SCIENTIFIC REALISM II
A Table as Seen  
  The Atomic Picture of a Section of a Table Á
an atom with a nucleus ()  

Á Á Á Á

Á
Á Á
Á Á

Á Á
Á Á Á
Á
Á Á Á Á


Á
Á Á Á Á

Á Á Á
Á
Although science is realistic, as common sense
is, the mind-independent entities of physics are
very different from ordinary macroscopic objects
like tables and chairs, apples and trees.
Current physical theory tells us that ordinary
macroscopic objects of these kinds are mostly
empty space, consisting of matter too small to be
seen, in rapid motion.
47
SCIENTIFIC REALISM III
  • A model of the atom suggests that an atom
    consists of various subatomic particles. The dot
    at the center of the picture to the left
    represents the nucleus of the atom. The nucleus
    of an atom consists of protons and neutrons.
    Both the proton and the neutron are in turn
    composed of three quarks. The circle in the
    diagram represents the parts of the atom which
    are not parts of the nucleus. These are
    electrons. All the objects of the external world
    consist of these entities too small to be seen
    electrons and quarks.

An atom Á
48
SCIENTIFIC REALISM IV
  • For scientific realism, Russells table, when
    unperceived, is more like the space of this room,
    in being empty, than it is like the colored,
    substantial object we are aware of in perception.
  • In addition, we are not aware of any movement of
    any parts of the table in perception, but there
    is movement going on at the subatomic level.
    Physicist James Trefil says that the nucleus of
    an atom is not static, like the table it helps to
    compose, but is a dynamic place. In this
    place, all kinds of particles are whizzing
    around, bashing into each other, and being
    created and destroyed as their energy is
    converted into mass and their mass is converted
    into energy. Being inside a nucleus is probably
    more like being in the middle of a fireworks
    display on the Fourth of July than anything
    else. (Trefil, James 1001 Things Everyone
    Should Know About Science, pp. 178-179)

49
SCIENTIFIC REALISM V
Light from a Source(s) Strikes the Atoms ( Á )
of the Table
Á
Á
Á
Á
Á
Á
Light travels from the atoms of the table to the
retina of the eye, where it is converted into an
electro-chemical impulse which reaches the visual
cortex of the brain through the optic nerve. The
visual cortex interprets this impulse as a brown,
rectangular object, and the person whose cortex
it is has the experience of seeing the table. The
atoms of the table are neither brown nor
rectangular. Accordingly, properties of the
subject, including properties of her eyes
(electro-chemical impulses) and brain (the
interpretive action of the visual cortex), are
relevant to seeing the table as a complex of
brown and rectangular sense data.
50
SEEING THE PAST I
  • Because light travels at a finite rate of speed
    (186,000 miles per second), in seeing an object,
    we are always seeing a past stage of the object.
    If an object were 186,000 miles from us, then we
    would be seeing it as it looked one second ago.
    An object 93,000 miles from us would appear to us
    as it did one-half a second ago, an object 46,500
    miles from us one-quarter a second ago, and so
    forth. Because light travels at such a great
    rate of speed, for an object which is close to
    us, the difference between the image of the
    object in the brain and the object which the
    image is of is so slight as to be virtually
    instantaneous.

51
SEEING THE PAST II
  • Because the sun is about 93,000,000 miles from
    earth, we see the sun as it was about 500
    seconds, or about 8 minutes, ago. Accordingly,
    if the sun were to go out of existence, we would
    not know it for 8 minutes. Because of the
    vastness of the universe, and the finite rate of
    speed of light, some of the stars which you see
    in the night sky may no longer exist.
  • The time-lag argument in philosophy of perception
    notes what we have seen, that there is always
    some amount of time, however short, between our
    seeing of an object and the object seen.
    Philosophers like Bertrand Russell take this to
    be further evidence that what we are immediately
    aware of in sensation is sense data, not the
    physical objects to which sense data are causally
    related. Because it is possible that an object,
    like a star, may no longer exist which we
    nevertheless see, even perception itself cannot
    be taken as conclusive evidence that the object
    of perception exists.
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com