Title: Game Theory Static Bayesian Games
1Game Theory Static Bayesian Games
- Univ. Prof.dr. M.C.W. Janssen
- University of Vienna
- Winter semester 2009-10
- Week 49 (November 30, December 1)
2In Many Situations Players do not have pay-off
relevant information
- Buyer and Seller negotiating about price
- Willingness to pay, cost (willingness to sell)
- Oligopoly competition
- Cost of other firms in Bertrand, Cournot
- Auctions
- Value of other bidders
- .
- Here, we consider static games
- Later, sequential games and updating (actions may
then reveal private information)
3Framework
- Players can be of different types ?i ? Ti
- A firm can have different cost, a buyer may have
different willingness to pay - Strategy player i si ?i ? Ai
- can condition action on private information
- Prior probability of types F(?1,.., ?n)
- Updating if types are correlated p(?-i / ?i )
- If types are uncorrelated, knowing your own type
does not reveal information about types of other
players posterior prob. prior prob.
4Example Auction
- Players valuations are uniformly and
independently distributed over interval 0,1
this is the prior distribution, vi ? 0, 1 - Valuations are private information and the action
each player chooses is her bid bi. - Strategy is function si vi ? bi bi(vi)
- What is then an equilibrium?
5Bayes-Nash Equilibrium definition
- For def. 1 we define ui (si (.) ,s-i (.))
E? ui (si (.) ,s-i (.) ?i ) - Def 1. A strategy combination (si (.) ,s-i (.))
is a Bayes-Nash equilibrium if ui (si (.) ,s-i
(.)) ? ui (si (.) ,s-i (.)) for all i and all
si ?Si - Def 2 A strategy combination (si (.) ,s-i (.))
is a Bayes-Nash equilibrium if given s-i each
type ?i chooses an optimal action (action that
maximizes expected profits taking p(?-i / ?i )) - Definitions are equivalent
- Profits of types are independent of each other
6Examples Battles of the Sexes game I
- Consider battles of the sexes game where there is
some uncertainty about both players pay-off - t, t ? 0,x
- What is a strategies? Choose B or F depending on
value of t, t - Proposal player 1 chooses B iff t gt t player 2
chooses F iff t gt t - Reasonable proposal?
7Examples Battles of the Sexes game II
- For player 2 it looks as if player 1 chooses B
with probability (x-t)/x - Equilibrium? Check for player 2
- Ep(B) (x-t)/x 1 t/x 0
- Ep(F) (x-t)/x 0 t/x (2t)
- B optimal iff t lt -3 x/t
- This has to be equal to t
- Similarly, player 1 B optimal if t gt -3 x/t
t - t is solution to t2 3t x 0
8First-Price Sealed-Bid Auction
- Highest bidder wins and pays his own bid.
- Players valuations are uniformly and
independently distributed over interval 0,1. - What is equilibrium with n players?
- Pay-off to player i is (vi-bi)Pr(bi gt max bj)
- Suppose strategies are linear, then Pr(bi gt bj)
Pr(bi gt aßvj) Pr(vj lt (bi a)/ß) (bi a)/ß
and Pr(bi gt max bj) (bi a)/ßn-1 - Maximizing pay-off wrt bi yields - (bi
a)/ßn-1 (n-1) (bi a)/ßn-2 (vi-bi)/ß 0 - Solving yields (bi a) (n-1)(vi-bi) or bi
((n-1)via))/n - Linearity requires a0, ß(n-1)/n
9Second-price sealed-bid auction
- This we already discussed (week 2)
- Strategies are also bids dependent on valuations
and dominant strategy is to bid valuation bi
vi - This is thus also a Bayes-Nash equilibrium
10Double Auction set-up
- Sellers (Player 1) cost is c buyers valuation
(Player 2) is v. Both are uniformly distributed
over 0,1. Both make a bid. If b1b2 then they
trade at price p (b1b2)/2 otherwise no trade - Pay-offs
- Seller (b1b2)/2 c if b1b2 otherwise 0
- Buyer v - (b1b2)/2 if b1b2 otherwise 0
- Without asymmetric information, continuum of
equilibria where both players bid t ? c,v
11Double Auction asymmetric info I
- Buyer chooses p2 to maximize
- (v-p2E(p1/p1ltp2)/2) Pr (p1 lt p2)
- Seller chooses p1 to maximize
- (p1E(p2/p2gtp1)/2 - c) Pr (p1 lt p2)
- First, consider again linear strategies p1 a1
b1c so that E(p1/p1ltp2) (a1p2)/2 - Buyers problem reduces to max
- (v-p2(a1p2)/2/2) (p2-a1)/b1
- Solution p2 (2va1)/3
- Similarly for seller p1 (2c(a2b2))/3
12Double Auction asymmetric info II
- Solution for buyer p2 (2va1)/3 implies that
b22/3 and a2(a1)/3 - Solution for seller p1 (2c(a2b2))/3 implies
that b12/3 and a1(a22/3)/3 - Thus, a21/12 and a11/4
- In linear equilibrium trade occurs if v c ¼
- Inefficiency
- Other Bayes-Nash equilibria exist, such as
- Buyer offer price p if v p otherwise offer 0
- seller offer price p if p c otherwise offer
1 - All other equilibria are also inefficient
13Purification theorem for Mixed Strategy
equilibrium an illustration
- If t0, mixed strategy equilibrium where player 1
plays B with prob 2/3 - In Bayes-Nash eq. of private info game t, t ?
0,x, player 1 plays B is if t gt t, with prob. - What happens when x becomes very small?
Probability converges to 2/3
14Purification theorem for Mixed Strategy
equilibrium set-up
- Mixed strategy can be considered as the limit of
a pure strategy Bayes-Nash equilibrium where
uncertainty disappears. - Is this a general phenomenon?
- Harsanyi (1973) yes
- Harsanyis set-up perturb pay-offs as follows
?si -1,1 e is positive number (going to 0).
Then ui (s,?i ) ui (s) e?i (Pi is
continuous distribution of ?i
15Purification theorem for Mixed Strategy
equilibrium result
- Best reply is essentially unique and in pure
strategies - If ?i is continuously distributed it is rare
event that best replies coincide for interval of
?i values - Any equilibrium for unperturbed pay-offs ui (s)
is the limit as e?0 of a sequence of pure
strategy equilibria of the perturbed game ui (s) - Holds for pure and mixed strategy equilibria,
- But not for pure strategy equilibria in weakly
dominated strategies
16Exercises
- Make exercises 6.1
- Pay-offs are either as in the upper matrix or as
in the lower matrix (see right). The Row player
knows the pay-offs, Column player does not know.
Prior probability of each matrix is equally
likely. What are the Bayes-Nash eq? - Consider the linear Cournot duopoly where players
have cost c1 and c2. Player 1 knows all cost, but
player 2 only knows its own cost and it thinks
player 1 has high cost cH with prob a and low
cost cL with prob. 1-a.