Title: Extensive Games with Perfect Information II
1Extensive Games with Perfect Information II
2Outline
- One stage deviation principle
- Rubinstein alternative bargaining game
- Excess optimum
- Two paradoxes
- Chain store paradox
- Centipede game
- Review of the mid term exam
3One-deviation property
- Definition One-Deviation property is satisfied
if no player can increase her payoff by changing
her action at the start of any subgame in which
she is the first-mover, given the other player's
strategies and the rest of her own strategy. - Proposition (One-Deviation Property). Let G be a
(finite or infinite horizon) EGPI. The strategy
profile s is a subgame perfect equilibrium if
and only if it satisfies the one-deviation
property. - proof see Fudenberg and Tirole
- Implication Suppose we are given a strategic
profile for an EGPI, and we wonder if it is
indeed an SPE. The proposition says we need only
check those alternative strategies with one
deviation.
4Infinite horizon
- For the proposition to hold also for infinite
horizon games, we need the following very mild
qualification - Continuity at infinity A game is continuous at
infinity if for each player i the utility
function ui satisfies - This condition says events in the distant future
are relatively unimportant. It will be satisfied
if the overall payoffs are a discounted sum of
per-period payoffs git(at) and the per-period
payoffs are uniformly bounded, i.e., for is a B
such that
5One Stage Deviation Principle (OSDP) an
illustration
- Consider a one-player EGPI.
- You are told that s(A,C,F) is an SPE.
- To check this, according to the definition of
SPE, you need to check s against ALL other
strategies. - However, according to the one deviation
principle, you just need to fare s against
three of them (B,C,F), (A,D,F), and (A,C,E). - So far as each of these alternative strategies
does not give a strictly higher payoff for the
subgame in which the deviation occurs, then s is
in an SPE.
6Rubinstein alternative offer game
- One unit of cake is to be divided
- (x1,x2) be an offer
- Player 1 makes offers in periods t0,2,4,..., and
Player 2 makes offers in periods t1,3,5,....
- An agreement (x1,x2) reached t periods later
gives discounted payoffs of dtx1 and dtx2 to the
two players. - The players are risk neutral the objective of
each player is to maximize his discounted
expected payoff.
7An SPE
- Let x(x1,x2)((1/(1d)),(d/(1d))) and
y(y1,y2)((d/(1d)),(1/(1d))). - Player 1 always proposes x and accepts any offer
in which he is paid (d/(1d)) or more. - Player 2 always proposes y and accepts any offer
in which he is paid (d/(1d)) or more. - Proof Check that nobody can benefit from
unilaterally deviating once. Then by one
deviation property proposition, nobody can
benefit from multiple deviations. This indeed is
an SPE.
8Unique SPE
- Let Gi be a subgame in which i is the proposer.
Different SPEs give different discounted payoffs
to player i. Let Mi and mi be the supremum and
infimum of them. - We claim that M1m1(1/(1d)) and
M2m2(1/(1d)). - If this claim is true, then there is a unique SPE
(not only unique SPE outcome). (verify this)
9Unique SPE (cont.)
- We now turn to show the claim. It takes a few
steps. - Step 1 m21-dM1. Suppose it is 2's turn to make
an offer. If 1 gets a chance to make an offer in
the next period, 1 will get at most M1. This most
optimistic outcome for 1 is worth dM1 now after
discounting. Hence any offer to 1 giving him
dM1? now must be accepted by 1, leaving 1-dM1-?
for player 2. Hence it cannot be the case that
m2lt1-dM1.
10Unique SPE (cont.)
- Step 2 M11-dm2. Suppose it is 1's turn to make
an offer. If 2 gets a chance to make an offer in
the next period, he will get at least m2. Then 2
will not accept an offer giving him dm2-? right
now. Hence, if agreement is to be reached
immediately, 1 cannot make an offer so that
x2ltdm2 or x1gt1- dm2 1's offer has to satisfy
x11- dm2. Suppose 1's offer is rejected, the
supremum of his present value will become
d(1-m2)(1-m2)1- dm2. Whether 1's offer is
accepted now or not, we have M11-dm2 .
11Unique SPE
- Step 1 m21-dM1 and Step 2 M11-dm2
- Also, Step 3 m11-dM2 and Step 4 M21-dm1.
- Combining Steps 1 and 2, we have m2 1-dM1
1-d(1-dm2) (1-d)d²m2. Hence, we have
m2((1-d)/(1-d²))(1/(1d)). Substituting this
back to step 2, we have M1(1/(1d)).Taking into
account of symmetry and the existence of SPE, the
claim is shown.
12Extension Will Excess Optimum always lead to
delay?
- Consider the case where two risk-neutral players
are trying to divide a dollar, which is worth 1
at t0, d?(1/2,1) at t1, and zero afterwards. It
is also common knowledge that each player
believes with probability one that he will be
picked to make an offer at t1 so long as no
agreement is made at t0. Find the unique SPE.
13Extension Will Excess Optimum always lead to
Delay? (cont)
- Now consider a four-period version of the
previous game. The dollar is worth 1, d, d², and
d³ at dates 0, 1, 2, and 3, respectively, where
d?(1/2,1/v2). The dollar is worth 0 afterwards.
Assume that each player is always sure that he
will make all the remaining offers. Find the
unique SPE. - See Yildiz (Econometrica, 2004??)
14Chain-store game
- A chain-store (CS) has branches in K cities,
numbered 1,...,K. - In each city k there is a single potential
competitor, player k. - In period k, competitor k chooses to enter or
not if so CS either fights or cooperates in that
period. That period's payoff is - at every point in the game all players know all
the actions previously chosen. - The payoff of competitor k is its payoff in
period k the payoff of the chain-store in the
game is the sum of its payoffs in the K cities.
15Chain store paradox
- unique SPE
- k always enters
- CS always cooperate after entry of the competitor
- Paradox Suppose upon every time a competitor
entered in the past, it was fought by the
chain-store. Shouldn't the competitor who has the
turn decides not to enter? The SPE says it should
not!!
16Centipede game
Two players 1 and 2 play a 6 stage centipede game.
17Centipede game
- Using backward induction, we find that the game
will end immediately. - unless the number of stages is very small it
seems unlikely that player 1 would immediately
choose S at the start of the game. - After a history in which both a player and his
opponent have chosen to continue many times in
the past, how should a player form a belief about
his opponent's action in the next period? It is
far from clear.
18Summary
- The notion of Nash equilibrium is not
particularly useful for the study of EGPI. - The notion of subgame perfect equilibrium is
introduced to solve this problem. - SPE presumes that a history with zero probability
according to the strategy profile is reached is
viewed as an outcome of mistakes. - The prediction of SPE leads to famous paradoxes
that call for re-examination of assumptions of
the model. - One deviation property theorem
- Alternative bargaining model as a building block
in the modeling of many interesting issues (e.g.,
outside option, threat point, trade bargaining,
bargaining between firm and union, the role of
property rights, debt renegotiation, holdup, etc.)