Measuring Societal Welfare: Concepts and Objections. - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 16
About This Presentation
Title:

Measuring Societal Welfare: Concepts and Objections.

Description:

This course is about measuring and comparing aspects of wellbeing. ... NO INTER-PERSONAL COMPARISONS OF UTILITY! ... To compare societies we can borrow ideas ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:92
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 17
Provided by: chassUt
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: Measuring Societal Welfare: Concepts and Objections.


1
Measuring Societal Welfare Concepts and
Objections.
  • This course is about measuring and comparing
    aspects of wellbeing. Before we do so we need to
    look at some theoretical foundations for, and
    objections to, the activity.

2
The Social Welfare Function
  • A long tradition of the notion of The Common
    Good comparatively recently articulated in the
    Samuelson (1947) Bergson (1938) Social Welfare
    Function.
  • N agents i1,..,N with Utility finctions Ui(x)
    defined over all social states x (a list of all
    of the things that define a particular state for
    all individuals) and a benign impartial
    administrator who chooses x to maximize SWF
    F(U1(x), U2(x),..,UN(x)) where F is some
    increasing function of the Uis
  • Fomented a huge debate over its nature and very
    existence in the mid 1900s.
  • Many views as to what form it should take and how
    it should be represented. Three examples,
    Benthamite, Daltonian and Rawlsian dominate the
    stage.

3
The Benthamite Tradition
  • Utilitarians, the first welfarists, did not
    contemplate measurement as a problem
  • Utilitarianism The Greatest Good for the
    Greatest Number (Just add it up across the
    population!)
  • Ideas born in the Scottish Enlightenment in the
    mid 1700s (Hume (1711-1776) sketched the idea in
    his many philosophical writings).
  • Formally articulated by Jeremy Bentham
    (1748-1832) in An Introduction to the Principles
    and Morals of Legislation (1789) and developed by
    Mill, Edgworth, Sidgwick and Pigou through the
    1800s and early 1900s.
  • Requires that we can identify Good or Utility
    and can aggregate it.

4
The Daltonian Principle Inequality is a bad
thing.
  • Dalton (1925) Inequality of Incomes, Pigou(1912)
    Wealth and Welfare
  • For Constant Aggregate Income Levels, a more
    equal distribution of utility is to be preferred.
  • Captured in the Pigou-Dalton Principle of
    Transfers (any transfer from a poor man to a rich
    man increases inequality).
  • For a society of identical agents with U gt 0 and
    U lt 0, Utilitarianism has a Daltonian flavour
    since an equal distribution of aggregate income
    will maximize aggregate utility.

5
The Rawlsian Principle
  • Social Welfare is simply the welfare of the
    poorest person.(Rawls Theory of Justice 1971)
  • The Maximin Rule. Maximize the income of the
    poorest person.
  • For a society of identical agents with U gt 0 and
    U lt 0, Utilitarianism has a Rawlsian flavour
    since an equal distribution of aggregate income
    will maximize aggregate utility.

6
The Pretense toward Scientific method and
Measurement Problem
  • Happiness, felicity, satisfaction, utility, well
    being, ophelimity we have many words for
    something (U(x)) we can not measure cardinally!
  • Robbins, Hicks, Samuelson argued that since only
    ordinal measurement made sense statements like
    Agent I is happier than agent j under x did not
    make sense. NO INTER-PERSONAL COMPARISONS OF
    UTILITY!
  • All is not lost, to understand the actions of the
    individual we only require that she be able to
    order or rank states in order of preference.
    Utility Theory does the rest.
  • To compare societies we can borrow ideas from
    utility theory for analyzing social states
    providing we can get round the interpersonal
    comparisons thing.
  • One such attempt was Harsanyis veil of
    ignorance, i.e. which state would you choose if
    you did not know which agent you were all you
    knew was that you would be randomly allocated one
    of the positions in that society. (Ethically
    Defensible?)

7
The Axioms of Individual Choice over a collection
of goods q given income x and prices p
8
(No Transcript)
9
The Budget Constraint, Indirect Utility Function
and Cost Function
  • Given an agents preference structure accords with
    the above axioms we can develop consumer demand
    functions as functions relating observable
    entities to observable entities via the budget
    constraint and the indirect utility and cost
    functions.
  • The solution to Maximising Utility subject to the
    budget constraint yields Marshallian Demand
    Functions q g(x,p). When these are substituted
    into V(q) they yield an Indirect Utility Function
    U(x,p) which can be inverted to yield a cost
    function x C(U,p) which corresponds to the cost
    of achieving U when confronting prices p.
    Minimzing this cost function for a given U yields
    Hicksian demand functions qh(U,p). Duality
    theory highlights the equivalence of minimizing
    C() for a given U with maximizing U for a given
    x.
  • Consistency with the axioms and the budget
    constraint will impose some structure on the
    demand functions g() through these relationships
    which can thus be examined empirically to see if
    agents conform to the rationality hypothesis.

10
Implications of The Budget Constraint
11
Implications of the Axioms and the budget
constraints
  • Adding up x pg(x,p) ph(U,p)
  • Homogeneity h(U,?p) h(U,p) g(?x,?p) g(x,p)
  • Symmetry ?hi/?pk ?hk/?pi (for testability this
    has to be represented in terms of the marshallian
    demands which can be done).
  • Negativity SiSkwiwk?hi/?pk 0 (again for
    testability this has to be represented in terms
    of the marshallian demands which can be done).

12
Separability and Inter-temporal Welfare
  • Analysis is greatly facilitated if U(q) can be
    written as U(U1(q1),U2(q2),..,Un(qn)) where
    q1,q2,..,qn mutually exclusive and exhaustive
    sub-vectors of q.
  • Types of Separability Weak and Strong (or
    Additive) separability. Has considerable
    implications for the structure of preferences.
  • For any goods k and j from two different
    subgroups F and C respectively weak separability
    implies skjµFC?qk/?x.?qj/?x (strong separability
    implies µFCµ i.e. independent of subgroups).
  • Introduces the idea of two stage budgeting, i.e.
    allocating budgets to the Uis at the first stage
    (based upon aggregated price indices) and then
    maximize Uis individually the subject to their
    respective budgets.
  • Inter-temporal choice, is associated with time
    periods where the budget constraint is lifetime
    wealth.
  • Note the similarity of these structures with the
    SWF. Utilitarianism is like strong separability
    in individual utilities if the the x in each
    Ui(x) is confined to only those goods consumed by
    i.

13
So Can We Contemplate an SWF (Social Welfare
Function)?
  • Robbins argued that rigorous adherence to the
    strictly ordinal notion of utility precluded any
    interpersonal comparisons of utility.
  • We cannot add up utilities like the Utilitarians
    did.
  • The only societal welfare improvements or
    deteriorations that economists could proclaim
    were Paretian ones no one is worse of and at
    least one person is better off or no one is
    better off and at least one person is worse off.
  • The problem is we cannot give a numeric value to
    U(q). Suppose we could, what about SWF F(U1(q),
    U2(q),,Un(q))?

14
Arrows Impossibility Theorem The Reasonable
Conditions
  • Collective Rationality The collective choice is
    represented by an ordering over all states that
    is complete and transitive.
  • Universal Domain The domain of the welfare
    function should contain all logically possible
    orderings of individuals.
  • Pareto Inclusiveness If all individuals prefer a
    to b then the welfare function should prefer a to
    b.
  • Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives The
    ranking of two alternatives depends solely on
    information on how individuals rank those
    alternatives (i.e. not on a direct comparison of
    the individuals happinesss).
  • Anonymity No identifiable individual should be
    able to determine the social choice in all
    circumstances.

15
The Implications
  • The Only SWF satisfying all these conditions must
    make all Pareto Incomparable States socially
    indifferent, i.e. Pareto comparisons are the only
    basis for social choice.
  • Even if one agent has a mild preference for xa
    whereas all other agents have a strong preference
    for state xb, xa and xb must be declared socially
    indifferent.
  • Rules out democracies and dictatorships as a
    social planning mechanisms.

16
What to do now?
  • Arrows theorem makes Pareto Judgments the only
    basis for social choice.
  • If we want to be Democrats or Dictators,
    Utilitarians, Daltonians or Rawlsians for that
    matter, we have to reject at least one of the
    principles.
  • Harsanyis veil of Ignorance postulate.
  • Hiding behind Sen (it was his idea!) well reject
    the no interpersonal comparisons constraint.
    Follow Harsanyi and maximise E(U(x)).
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com