Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 45
About This Presentation
Title:

Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals

Description:

The maxim is the principle that moves the will to action. The rational maxim of duty is to follow the law even if it thwarts the inclinations ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:40
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 46
Provided by: philosoph
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals


1
Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals
  • Philosophy 1
  • Spring, 2002
  • G. J. Mattey

2
Ethics
  • Material philosophy has to do with specific
    objects and the laws governing them
  • Physics is the science of the laws of nature
  • Ethics is the science of the laws of freedom
  • Ethics has an empirical part, in that its laws
    concern a human will that is affected by nature
  • The moral law concerns what ought to happen but
    may not in fact happen

3
The Moral Law
  • The moral law is the a priori part of ethics
  • It contains nothing empirical
  • It governs with absolute necessity
  • It applies to all rational beings and does not
    depend on the nature of man or the circumstances
    in the world
  • It must be sought in pure reason
  • The moral law must guide our actions if they are
    to be good

4
Good Will
  • Only a good will is good without qualification
  • The virtues of the mind (e.g., intelligence) and
    of temperament (e.g., courage) can become bad if
    the will is bad
  • The same holds for external goods that complete
    the ancient conception of happiness
  • A good will is a necessary condition for being
    worthy of happiness
  • It is good in itself, through its willing, not
    through any utility it might have

5
Reason and Happiness
  • Reason is not well-suited by nature for the
    attainment of happiness
  • Happiness would be better entrusted to instinct
  • So if reason has a purpose, it must be something
    other than happiness
  • Its true function is to produce a good will
  • Good of the will is higher than happiness

6
Duty and Inclination
  • We may act from duty, inclination, or selfish
    purpose
  • Sometimes we do from selfish purpose what duty
    calls for, without inclination
  • A prudent merchant charges a fixed price
  • Sometimes we do from inclination what duty calls
    for
  • Preserving ones own life
  • Sometimes we act purely from duty
  • Preserving ones life when one does not wish to
    live

7
Moral Worth
  • Only actions performed purely from duty have
    moral worth
  • Acts that overcome inclinations and selfish
    purposes and arise from duty have the highest
    moral worth
  • Even promotion of happiness has moral worth only
    insofar as it is done as duty

8
Maxims
  • Moral worth is not found in the end of an action,
    but in the maxim that determines it
  • The maxim is the principle that moves the will to
    action
  • The rational maxim of duty is to follow the law
    even if it thwarts the inclinations
  • The highest moral good is the representation of
    the moral law

9
Respect for Law
  • The moral law motivates us without recourse to
    inclination or effects
  • The only motivating principle remaining is to act
    out of respect for law
  • One should act only on those maxims one can will
    to be a universal law

10
An Example
  • I am in distress, and to alleviate my situation I
    might make a promise with the intention of
    breaking it
  • I might act according to the maxim, make
    dishonest promises when in trouble
  • Making this maxim universal might lead to bad
    consequences for me
  • The moral, rather than practical, reason for
    rejecting it is that the maxim would destroy
    itself if it were made universal

11
Moral Philosophy
  • The moral law is accessible to everyone
  • We do not need science or philosophy to be able
    to tell right from wrong
  • Still, we need to investigate the moral law
    philosophically due to the bad influence of
    inclinations and needs (desire for happiness)
  • This can corrupt the purity of the moral law

12
The Dear Self
  • It is difficult to find cases of acting purely
    from duty
  • Philosophers have thus claimed that our
    motivation for acting is self-love
  • We cannot even tell in ourselves whether this is
    a secret motivation
  • We always seem to find the dear self at the basis
    of our actions
  • Whether we have ever done it or not, we ought to
    do our duty

13
Pure Practical Reason
  • The moral law commands all rational beings
  • It could do so only if is valid with absolute
    necessity, subject to no contingencies
  • Such a law can be found only in pure practical
    reason, not in knowledge of human nature
  • It cannot be derived from examples
  • Even the concept of God as the highest good is
    derived from the idea of moral perfection

14
Will and Reason
  • Everything that happens in nature is the result
    of laws
  • Human action is based on our rational conception
    of laws (principles)
  • Human will may be determined by principles
  • Or it may be determined by inclination
  • If determined by principles, it follows the
    command of reason, which determines what one
    ought to do

15
Imperatives
  • A divine will would always obey the moral law, so
    there is nothing it ought to do
  • Humans do not always obey
  • All imperatives command in one of two ways
  • Hypothetically one should do this to accomplish
    that end
  • Categorically one should do this as objectively
    necessary in itself
  • Only a categorical imperative declares what is
    good in itself

16
Hypothetical Imperatives
  • The end in a hypothetical imperative might be
    good or not
  • Children are trained to achieve many varied ends,
    without regard to their good
  • The natural end of human action is happiness
  • Skill in choosing means to the end of happiness
    is prudence

17
Prudence
  • Hypothetical imperatives are possible because
    willing the ends requires willing the means (that
    in ones power) to the ends
  • But how do we will the end of happiness?
  • There is immense confusion over which means will
    promote it
  • Wealth, knowledge, even health all can lead to
    unhappiness
  • So there are only empirical counsels for
    happiness, never commands for happiness

18
Categorical Imperatives
  • Categorical imperatives to not prescribe means to
    an end
  • Apparent categorical imperatives may be disguised
    hypotheticals
  • One may adopt a maxim against telling false
    promises so as to remain credible
  • So, we need to look to pure reason, not examples,
    to see how categorical imperatives are possible
  • The categorical imperative is an a priori
    synthetic principle

19
The Categorical Imperative
  • The only element of a categorical imperative that
    can be determined in advance is conformity to
    universal law
  • This gives the content of a single imperative
    act in such a way that the maxim of the action
    can serve as a universal law
  • Or act as if your maxim were to become a
    universal law of nature through your will

20
Perfect Duties to Ourselves
  • A perfect duty admits of no exception in the
    interests of inclination
  • We have a perfect duty to preserve our own life,
    even if self-love would dictate ending it
  • I cannot universalize the maxim of suicide
    without destroying all of life
  • So one must act on the maxim of preserving ones
    own life, which can be universalized

21
Perfect Duties to Others
  • We have a perfect duty to others to make honest
    promises, even when dishonesty would help us out
    of difficulty
  • I cannot universalize the maxim of making false
    promises without destroying all trust
  • If all trust is destroyed, my promise would not
    then serve my interests
  • So one must act on the maxim that one must make
    honest promises

22
Imperfect Duties to Ourselves
  • An imperfect duty is one which permits exceptions
    in the interests of inclination
  • We have an imperfect duty to develop our talents
  • I cannot universalize the maxim of indulging in
    pleasure
  • Life would go on, but our rational abilities
    would go to waste
  • So one must act on the maxim that one develop
    ones talents to the greatest extent possible

23
Imperfect Duties to Others
  • We have an imperfect duty to help others
  • I cannot universalize a maxim of letting others
    get along on their own
  • Life would go on, with less hypocrisy, but if
    everyone behaved this way, I might find myself
    without help when in need
  • So one must act on the maxim of helping others

24
The Unity of the Duties
  • All duties are derived from a single principle
    that we be able to will the maxim of our action
    to be a universal law
  • Acting against a perfect duty requires a maxim
    which cannot be thought of as a universal law of
    nature
  • Acting against an imperfect duty requires a maxim
    which can be so thought, but which cannot be
    willed to be a universal law of nature

25
Transgression
  • When we transgress our duties, we do not give up
    their claim to be universal law objectively
  • Instead, we subjectively make an exception to the
    law to serve our own inclinations, in which case
    the law is only general
  • There is no contradiction here, since it is
    reason that upholds objective universality and
    inclination that promotes only subjective
    generality
  • So, even transgression of the categorical
    imperative acknowledges its validity

26
Justification
  • Is there a categorical imperative that is binding
    on all rational beings?
  • Justification cannot depend on an account of
    human nature, but must be a priori
  • A principle based on human nature could not be an
    objective law valid for all rational beings
  • But it is tempting to appeal to empirical motives
    and laws, given the difficulty of justifying
    objective laws a priori

27
Ends
  • Ends are what determine the will to action
  • There are two kinds of ends
  • Objective ends, which are valid for every
    rational being, based on reason alone, and
    depending on motives
  • Subjective ends, which are arbitrarily proposed
    as the effect of ones action, based on desire,
    and depending on incentives
  • Subjective ends can be grounds for only
    hypothetical imperatives

28
An End in Itself
  • An objective end could be a ground for a
    categorical imperative
  • Rational beings (persons) are objective ends,
    ends in themselves
  • It is a categorical imperative that they may not
    be arbitrarily used as means to some other ends
  • Non-rational beings are not ends in themselves
    and may be used as means

29
The Examples Revisited
  • Suicide is not permitted because it treats ones
    self as a means to an end (relief)
  • Making false promises requires using another
    person as a means to my ends
  • Neglecting to develop ones capacities is
    inconsistent with the advancement of the end of
    humanity
  • Not furthering the ends of others is inconsistent
    with the fact that because they are ends in
    themselves, their ends are my ends

30
Legislation
  • Insofar as everyone must be treated as an end in
    itself, we are not free to treat them as our
    subjective inclinations dictate
  • The law constraining inclination is a universal
    law
  • The universal law comes from the rational will
  • So, a categorical imperative is to act only on a
    maxim that is consistent with a law which is
    legislated by the rational will
  • When we act out of duty, we act in a way that is
    not based on any interest

31
Autonomy
  • The will acts autonomously when it dictates a law
    for itself
  • If it acts for some interest, then it acts
    heteronomously
  • Previous attempts to discover the moral law all
    presume a heteronomous will
  • For example, divine law is backed by a system of
    rewards and punishment
  • As such, they were all doomed to failure

32
The Kingdom of Ends
  • A kingdom is a systematic union of different
    rational beings under common laws
  • The moral law requires that we treat other
    rational beings as ends in themselves
  • So, it presupposes the possibility of a kingdom
    of ends
  • Each rational being is a legislator in the
    kingdom
  • Each rational being is subject to the laws of
    reason
  • The laws of the kingdom of ends have in view the
    relation to one another as ends in themselves

33
Dignity
  • Everything in the kingdom of ends has a price or
    a dignity
  • A price is worth based on inclination
  • A dignity is an intrinsic worth based on
    somethings being an end in itself, beyond all
    price
  • Only morality and humanity have dignity, based on
    autonomy
  • All the other virtues have a price of some sort
    (skill at work, wit, etc.)
  • Keeping of promises, e.g., provides immediate
    favor and delight, as well as respect

34
Absolutely Good Will
  • A will is absolutely good when it cannot be evil
  • Its maxim cannot be in conflict with itself it
    willed to be a universal law
  • The categorical imperative is the supreme law of
    an absolutely good will
  • Obedience to the categorical imperative is the
    only way to avoid self-conflict
  • The end of the actions of a good will must be an
    end in itself
  • The good will legislates universal law

35
Happiness
  • Moral principles based on the promotion of
    happiness are based on experience
  • Happiness is construed as a physical or moral
    feeling
  • The worst form of such a principle is that of
    ones own happiness (egoism)
  • There are three problems
  • Being well is not the same as doing well
  • Being prudent is not the same as being morally
    virtuous
  • Motives of virtue are on a par with motives of
    vice

36
Moral Feeling
  • The principle that the good act is one that
    elicits happy moral feeling is superior to egoism
  • It values morality for its own sake
  • But appeal to it is superficial
  • Due to variation in people, are not a uniform
    standard of moral appraisal
  • No one persons feelings can be the basis of the
    judgments of everyones actions

37
Rational Principles of Morality
  • Philosophers have tried to base morality on a
    concept of perfection
  • The ontological concept is empty and presupposes
    the morality it is supposed to explain
  • The theological concept of perfection is that of
    a divine will
  • We have no understanding of divine properties
    except on the model of our own
  • If it is not derived from our concept of
    morality, it would be based on notions such as
    domination and vengeance, which are opposed to
    morality

38
Freedom
  • The will is a causality that living beings have
    insofar as they are rational
  • Freedom is a property of this causality, where
    the will acts independently of alien causes
  • This conception of freedom is negative
  • Positive freedom is autonomy the will dictates
    a law to itself, the moral law
  • So, a free will is one which is subject to moral
    law

39
Practical Reason
  • Practical reason is the will of a rational being
  • A will cannot be rational if it is directed by
    something other than itself, e.g., impulse
  • So, a rational will can be directed only by
    itself
  • So, a rational will must be considered to be free
    (in the positive sense)
  • This is so even though we cannot demonstrate the
    metaphysical reality of freedom

40
Our Interest in Morality
  • Why should I subject myself to the moral law?
  • It is not that so doing will serve my interests
  • The answer is that I would do so insofar as I am
    a rational being and am not hindered
  • But I am also a sensible being and am subject to
    inclinations, so I only ought to obey the moral
    law

41
A Circle?
  • We suppose that we are free of external causes so
    that we can understand how we are subject to
    moral laws
  • But we think of ourselves as being subject to
    moral laws only because we suppose that we are
    free, autonomous, wills
  • So it seems that freedom depends on morality and
    morality depends on freedom

42
Resolution
  • When we think of ourselves as free from external
    causes, these causes are in the order of
    appearances
  • When we think of the will as an autonomous cause,
    this cause is in the order of things in
    themselves
  • There is a faculty in human beings which is
    distinct from all external causes reason
  • Rational causality can be thought only as freedom

43
Duality
  • All my actions, viewed as appearances, can be
    explained in terms of desires and inclinations
  • If I were a purely intelligible being, all my
    actions would be explained by freedom
  • Since I am both sensible and intelligible, the
    laws of freedom express only what I ought to do
  • Even the meanest villain recognizes that he
    would conform to the moral law if he were not
    such a slave to his impulses

44
Compatibilism
  • There is no contradiction between freedom of the
    will and natural necessity
  • We think of the human being in different ways in
    each case
  • So, natural necessity, which we know a priori
    holds, is no threat to freedom
  • Inclinations and impulses are not all-controlling
  • But on the other hand, we cannot explain anything
    in the natural world through freedom, which is a
    mere idea

45
The Limit of Moral Inquiry
  • Moral feeling is not a criterion of morality
  • Our pure interest in the moral law (membership in
    the kingdom of ends) is the basis of moral
    feeling
  • Moral feeling, in turn, is what moves us to act
    in the world of appearances
  • But we cannot understand how something
    intelligible explains something sensible
  • We only have an idea of a reason that serves as a
    causality in and of itself
  • This is the limit of all moral inquiry
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com