Title: Moral Theory
1 2QUESTION What exactly are moral judgements about?
- a. Permissibility, Optionality, and
Obligatoriness - Permissible (right, acceptable, justified)
- Optional Permissible to do and permissible not
to do - Obligatory Permissible to do but not
permissible not to do
3b. The Moral Point of View
- Morality is a normative viewpoint the concern of
which is to impartially protect and/or promote
the basic interests of all individuals. - A normative viewpoint is one that classifies
actions, etc. in terms of their permissibility or
in terms of their goodness. - Normative viewpoints are concerned with how
things should be, and not necessarily with how
things are.
4Morality vs. Rational Self-Interest
- These two points of view may conflict It may be
permissible from the viewpoint of self-interest
to break a promise, but it may not be permissible
from the moral point of view.
5Morality vs. the Law
- The moral point of view can also conflict with
the legal point of view. What is morally
permissible need not be legally permissible - (e.g., going through a red light when no one is
around). - And what is legally permissible need not be
morally permissible - (e.g., failing to pull a drowning baby out of the
water).
6Descriptive vs. Critical Morality
- The descriptive morality of a given individual or
society consists of the moral norms reflected in
the verbal and other behavior of that individual
or society. - It is an empirical matter and is part of what
social science studies. The descriptive morality
of a given individual or society (e.g., of Nazis)
may be deeply defective. - Critical morality is not a mere descriptive
matter. It concerns the correct moral norms, and
thus provides a basis for criticizing the
prevailing descriptive morality of a given
individual or society. We will be concerned with
critical morality.
7QUESTION
- Are there any valid moral judgments (or are such
judgments just matters of emotion with no room
for error)?
8Moral Nihilism
- Moral nihilism denies that there are any valid
moral judgments, and holds that there is no point
in discussing, or reflecting about, moral issues.
- Most of us, however, reject this view. Suppose,
for example, that a fellow student beats you up,
smashes your car, and steals your wallet.
According to moral nihilism there is no moral
issue, whereas most of us would say that he did
something wrong. We would criticize his behavior,
blame him for what he did, hold him responsible
for compensating you for the damages, and think
it appropriate that he be punished. According to
moral nihilism, this would all be a mistake,
since morality is an illusion. - (Moral nihilism is closely related to moral
relativism, which holds that there are no moral
judgments valid for all people, but we won't
worry about the distinction between the two
here.)
9Moral Realism
- Moral realism is the view that there are
objective (i.e., mind independent) laws of
morality that determine which actions are
permissible (the laws of morality are often
thought of as analogous to the laws of nature
that determine which actions are possible, or to
laws of mathematics). - According to moral realism there is an
objectively correct moral view.
10Moral Constructivism
- Moral constructivism is the view that the
validity of a moral judgment, for a given person
or group of persons, is based on whether it would
be endorsed after careful reflection (and not on
whether it conforms to any objective law of
morality).
11QUESTION What is the point of moral reflection
and discussion?
- If moral realism is true, then one should engage
in moral discussion to find out about the
objectively correct moral theory. Of course, even
if moral realism is true, there is no guarantee
that we will all agree, or even that all well
informed experts will agree. Morality, like
physics, may be very complicated, and we may not
understand it very well. But careful
investigation and discussion will at least
improve our understanding, and reduce (if not
eliminate) disagreement. - If, however, moral constructivism is trueand
many people think it iswhy should one engage in
moral discussion? Here are some reasons why Even
if there is no objectively correct moral theory,
we can still defend/criticize a person's moral
view on internal grounds. That is, instead of
criticizing a person's moral views on external
grounds (i.e., because they do not correspond to
objective reality), we can criticize them in some
of the following ways
12- (a) A person's moral view might be based on a
confused or ill understood notion. For example,
someone might believe that abortion is wrong
because the fetus is a "person". Or someone might
hold that homosexuality is wrong because it is
"unnatural". But what exactly is meant by
"person" or "unnatural"? Forcing the person to
clarify what they mean may lead them to change
his/her mind. - (b) A person's moral view might be based on a
false belief, or lack of any belief. For example,
a person's view that killing animals is
permissible might rest on the false belief that
they cannot feel pain, or on the lack of any
belief about the matter. Providing the relevant
information may lead the person to change his/her
mind. - (c) A person's moral view combined with certain
plausible assumptions might have unforeseen
implications that are incompatible with some of
that person's particular moral judgments. For
example, a person may hold that abortion is
permissible on the grounds that it is not
generally wrong to kill something that is unaware
of its own existence and the fetus is so unaware.
When it is pointed out that on that view
infanticide is also generally permissible (since
infants are also unaware of their own existence),
the person may change his/her view.
13- So, even if moral constructivism is true,
discussing moral issues can be useful. - (1) We still care about what morality says. The
issue of the moral permissibility of abortion,
strong affirmative action, capital punishment,
etc., don't disappear if moral constructivism is
true. - (2) By being reflective one may come to change
one's view (e.g., to make one's view coherent in
light of a criticism of the above type). - (3) Even if one does not change one's moral
views, one will at least better understand one's
own moral views and those of others, and be
better able to defend one's own views (rather
than simply being dogmatic). - In general we must be on our guard against
blindly accepting the prevailing ideology. In the
past all sorts of weird views were generally
accepted, such as that earth is flat, that
monarchy is the only acceptable form of
government, that women are the property of their
husbands, that blacks aren't human, etc. Some of
our current views are surely just as mistaken.
14Ethics vs. Political Morality
- Moral theory is concerned with moral
permissibility. For simplicity we can think of it
as having two branches. - Ethical theory (or individual moral theory) is
concerned with the moral permissibility of the
actions (things done on a particular occasion)
and practices (things done repeatedly over time)
of individual agents. - Political moral theory is concerned with the
moral permissibility of legal social structures
(laws and systems of laws). - Although each of the following theories can be
formulated as a theory of political morality,
well only consider their formulations as ethical
theories.
15DIVINE COMMAND THEORY
- a. This is the oldest moral theory.
- The Divine Command Theory An action is
permissible if and only if (and solely because)
it violates none of God's commands. - A note on terminology "An action satisfies God's
commands" means that it does not violate any of
Gods commands. - Note that this theory does not make any specific
assumptions about what God's commands are (e.g.,
that they are as represented in Christian,
Jewish, or Muslim holy documents). It simply
appeals to God's commands as they truly are
(whatever they are).
16b. An assessment of the Divine Command Theory
- Attractive features (1) If God exists, then (at
least on a common conception) God is omnipotent,
omniscient and perfectly benevolent. If God gave
us commands, then it makes a lot of sense that we
should obey them. - Unattractive features
- (1) The theory presupposes that God exists. Many
people deny this. - (2) The theory presupposes that God gave us
commands. God might simply have created the world
and left it at that. (Deists hold this view.) - (3) Why think that Gods commands determine what
is morally permissible? That is, why think that
it is Gods commands that make things permissible
or impermissible? Would it be permissible to
torture babies if God gave us no commands? - Note that the rejection of the Divine Command
theory does not entail that God is not the source
of morality, it only entails that Gods commands
are not the source of morality. Cf. Natural Law
Theory.
17A. Gods Commands as Creating Morality (Divine
Command Theory)
18B. Gods Commands Instruct us about Morality
(Natural Law)
God lets us know that killing innocent humans is
wrong by telling us Dont kill innocent humans!
19UTILITARIANISM
- a. Utilitarianism is the most well known
goal-directed theory. - It arose primarily in Great Britain during the
1600s and 1700s during which time social thinkers
were beginning to challenge the traditional
social, economic, and political systems (e.g.,
monarchies) and their Divine Command
justifications. - The utilitarian emphasis was on designing and
justifying social structures in terms of
promoting human wellbeing. The most famous
proponents are Jeremy Bentham (1748-1832) and
John Stuart Mill (1806-1873). - There are many versions of utilitarianism (e.g.,
act utilitarianism, rule utilitarianism), but we
will consider only act utilitarianism, which is
the most common one. - (Act) utilitarianism An action (practice) is
permissible if and only if it maximizes social
wellbeing.
20UTILITARIANISM
- b. There are different versions of utilitarianism
that understand social wellbeing in different
ways. - The notion of individual wellbeing (welfare,
utility) can be interpreted in a number of
different ways - (1) net pleasure over pain,
- (2) happiness, or
- (3) preference satisfaction. For simplicity,
we'll usually understand well-being to be
happiness. - Social well-being can be understood either as the
total well-being for all members of society
(adding together everyone's individual
well-being), or as the average level of
well-being in society.
21UTILITARIANISM
- There are further variations depending on what
kinds of entity count as members of society. All
sentient beings (i.e., that can feel pleasure and
pain)? Only rational and self-conscious
beings? Only homo sapiens? Only members of one's
country? Only presently living beings, or also
beings that will potentially exist in the future?
- In general, we will not worry about these
differences, except where relevant.
22UTILITARIANISM
- c. An example (a1 and a3, but not a2, are judged
permissible) - Action John Mary Sue Total
- a1 80 30 70 180
- a2 40 60 60 160
- a3 20 90 70 180
23- d. An assessment of utilitarianismAttractive
features
24- (1) It takes a tough-minded approach to morality
(worrying about the long-term consequences for
human well-being).
25- d. An assessment of utilitarianismUnattractive
features
26- (1) It is very demanding of the agent (very few
actions are judged permissible). For example,
normally it judges it wrong to watch television,
go to restaurants, etc.. - (2) It gives little protection from interference
from others (it can permit others to kill,
torture, lie to, and steal from us). For example,
it judges it permissible for the sheriff to
execute the innocent person if that avoids
horrible riots. - (3) It is relatively insensitive to distributive
considerations. It doesn't care how unequally
well-being is distributed. All it cares about is
the total (or average) well-being. - (4) It is insensitive to what the past was like
(what promises or agreements were made, who did
something wrong, who worked hard, who chose to
take a risk, etc.). - (5) It presupposes that well-being is cardinally
measurable and interpersonally comparable (i.e.,
that there is a natural scale for precisely
measuring everyone's well-being on the same
scale).
27- e. An example that illustrates utilitarianism's
insensitivity to distributive considerations - Action John Mary Sue Total
- a1 0 105 100 205
- a2 65 65 65 195
- Utilitarianism judges a1 (with its unequal
distribution) permissible, but not a2 (with its
more equal distribution). - f. Satisficing utilitarianism The maximizing
nature of utilitarianism makes it very demanding.
It could be modified by requiring only that the
social well-being be "satisfactory" (or adequate)
according to some specified criterion (e.g., 50
of the maximum possible, or an amount that would
be sufficient for a minimally decent life for
each person). - g. Libertarian-constrained utilitarianism This
holds that an action is permissible if and only
if (1) it violates none of the libertarian
constraints, and (2) it produces as much social
well-being as possible without violating the
libertarian constraints. Adding the constraints
provides greater protection from interference and
introduces sensitivity to the past (past
wrongdoings, past commitments).
28LIBERTARIANISM
- a. A well known constraint theory is
libertarianism. It arose primarily in Great
Britain during the 1600 and 1700s during which
time social thinkers were beginning to challenge
the traditional social, economic, and political
systems (e.g., monarchies) and their Divine
Command justifications. - The libertarian emphasis was on designing and
justifying social structures in terms of
protecting human rights of liberty. The most
famous proponents are John Locke (1632-1704
British) and more recently Robert Nozick
(1938-2002 American). Although most advocates of
libertarianism focus on political libertarians
(the permissibility of legal structures), for
simplicity well focus on ethical libertarianism.
- Libertarianism An action (practice) is
permissible if and only if it violates none of
the libertarian constraints.
29- b. The libertarian constraints consist of
- (1) personal body constraints against killing,
physically harming, physically annoying, or
moving an innocent person, without his/her
consent - (2) physical property (other than personal body)
constraints against destroying, damaging, or
moving an innocent person's physical property
without his/her consent - (3) spatial property constraints against moving
on, or causing physically annoying things to move
on, an innocent person's spatial property without
his/her consent - (4) communication constraints (a) against
breaking promises (and agreements) without an
innocent promisee's consent and (b) against
deception (e.g., lies, non-rational manipulation,
or misleading statements or practices) without an
innocent deceived party's consent and - (5) compensatory constraints against failing to
provide compensation to people that the agent has
previously wrongedwithout their consent.
30- c. Above, killing, harming, annoying, moving,
destroying, damaging, etc., are to be understood
solely in terms of the things that an agent
brings aboutas opposed to what he/she allows to
happen. An agent brings about X just in case X
occurs, but would not have occurred had that
agent "done nothing", i.e., not intervened in the
"normal course of events". - pushing a non-swimmer into a lake brings about
her death, whereas - watching as a non-swimmer who fell in the lake
drowns is merely allowing her to die. - Above property is understood to be moral property
(that which a person morally owns)not legal
property (that which a person legally owns). Cf.
Slavery. - The above constraints are to be understood so
that people who violate these constraints lose
some of their protection from the constraints. A
note on terminology "An action satisfies the
constraints" means that it does not violate the
constraints.
31d. An assessment of libertarianism
- Attractive features
- (1) It leaves lots of liberty to the agent (it's
permissible to watch television). - (2) It gives lots of protection from interference
from others (it's always judged wrong to kill or
torture). - (3) It holds people responsible for their actions
(sensitivity to the past). - Unattractive features
- (1) It demands very little of the agent (i.e.,
leaves the agent too much liberty). For example,
it judges it permissible to allow the baby in the
puddle to drown, or to refuse to give a starving
person some food. - (2) It is totally insensitive to the long-term
impact on society (it's too rigid). For example,
it's wrong to kill one innocent person, even if
that saves millions of lives. - (3) It is totally insensitive to distributive
considerations.
32OPPORTUNITY EGALITARIANISM
- a. Opportunity egalitarianism, like
utilitarianism, is a goal-directed theory. - Unlike utilitarianism, its goal is a kind of
equality of opportunity for well-being rather
than total well-being. - Although it has antecedents that go back at least
to the 1600s, its most famous proponent is John
Rawls, who published his extremely influential A
Theory of Justice in 1971. (His theory is much
more complex than the simple version that we are
considering.) - Opportunity Egalitarianism An action (practice)
is permissible if and only if it maximizes
equality of initial effective opportunity for
well-being.
33- Initial effective opportunity for well-being
This is the effective opportunity for a good life
that individuals face at the beginning of their
responsible life. It reflects the real
opportunities that individuals then have to lead
fulfilling lives. - There are many versions of egalitarianism. Each
has a different conception of what is to be
equalized. For simplicity we are focusing on
equality of effective opportunity for well-being.
Unlike outcome egalitarianism, opportunity
egalitarianism denies that morality requires
outcomes (e.g., well-being) to be equal. - Any plausible version of egalitarianism will
require the promotion of equality by benefiting
someone (e.g., improving someones opportunity
for well-being). It will not, for example,
require the promotion of equality when no
benefits and some are harmed. - For example, it will not require choosing giving
everyone 2 (perfect equality) rather than giving
some 3 and some 4 (less equal, but better for
everyone). For simplicity, I have left this
qualification implicit.
34c. An assessment of opportunity egalitarianism
- Attractive features
- (1) It takes a tough-minded approach to morality
(worrying about the long-term consequences for
human well-being). - (2) It is sensitive to distributive
considerations. - (3) It is sensitive to what the past was like
(who worked hard, who chose to take a risk,
etc.). - Unattractive features
- (1) It is very demanding of the agent (very few
actions are judged permissible). For example,
normally it judges it wrong to watch television,
go to restaurants, etc.. - (2) Although the concern for equality gives more
protection from interference from others to
disadvantaged individuals than act utilitarianism
does, it doesnt provide very much protection for
advantaged individuals. Execution example. - (3) It presupposes that there is a natural scale
for precisely measuring everyone's well-being on
the same scale.
35- d. Satisficing opportunity egalitarianism The
maximizing nature of egalitarianism makes it very
demanding. It could be modified by requiring only
that the degree of equality of opportunity for
well-being be "satisfactory" (or adequate)
according to some specified criterion (e.g., 50
of the maximum possible). - e. Libertarian-constrained opportunity
egalitarianism This holds that an action is
permissible if and only if - (1) it violates none of the libertarian
constraints, and - (2) it produces as much equality of opportunity
for well-being as possible without violating the
libertarian constraints. - Adding the constraints provides greater
protection from interference and introduces
greater sensitivity to the past (past
wrongdoings, past commitments).
36SATISFICING LIBERTARIAN-CONSTRAINED OPPORTUNITY
EGALITARIANISM
- This is the theory that I believe (roughly
speaking) to be the most plausible. There will be
no test questions on this. This is included
solely for your reference. - Satisficing Libertarian-Constrained Opportunity
Egalitarianism An action (practice) is
permissible if and only if - (1) it violates none of the libertarian
constraints, and - (2) of those actions satisfying the libertarian
constraints that benefit at least one person, it
produces a satisfactory (relative to the
circumstances) degree of equality of opportunity
for well-being.
37- Attractive features
- (1) It takes a tough-minded approach to morality
(worrying about the long-term consequences for
human well-being). - (2) It is moderately demanding.
- (3) It provides strong protection from
interference. - (4) It is sensitive to the equality of effective
opportunity for well-being. - (5) It is sensitive to the past and holds
individuals accountable for their past choices. - Unattractive features
- (1) It provides too much protection from
interference (e.g., wrong to forcibly remove the
kidney of a privileged person when it would save
thousands of lives). - (2) It recognizes no duty to help the needy when
their neediness is their own fault. - (3) It presupposes that well-being is cardinally
measurable and interpersonally comparable (i.e.,
that there is a natural scale for precisely
measuring everyone's well-being on the same
scale).