Title: Cognition and Strategy: A Deliberation Experiment
1Cognition and StrategyA Deliberation Experiment
- Eric Dickson (NYU),
- Catherine Hafer (NYU),
- and Dimitri Landa (NYU)
2Deliberative Considerations
- Different considerations may be seen as
relevant by different people. - At a given point in time, individuals may not
have in mind all considerations they would find
to be relevant - Considerations perceived as (potentially)
relevant induce policy preferences - Deliberation as argumentation
- provable messages
- non-common veridicality (considerations relevant
for some need not be for others) - Endogenous deliberation roles
- speaking to affect the considerations perceived
as relevant by others VS. - listening to receive arguments made by others or
to withhold arguments from others
3Persuasion vs Alienation
- Imagine collective choice between leftist
policy (induced under complete information by
considerations (A),(B)) and a centrist policy
(induced by (B),(C)) - Suppose you have active consideration (B), and
a left-winger makes an argument trying to
activate consideration (A) - If (A) is a latent consideration of yours, (A)
is brought to mind - You become more likely to favor the leftist
policy - If (A) is not a latent consideration of yours,
no new consideration is brought to mind - However, an introspective listener might use this
failure to persuade to update in favor of the
centrist policy - The dog that didnt bark in the night
- Sherlock Holmes realizes this implies the crime
was not a burglary - Dr. Watson didnt realize that the dogs silence
could be informative - Do people use such indirect information in
updating policy judgments? - And do they anticipate that others might do so?
4Model of Deliberation Information Structure
- Set of true numbers AB,BC,CD is commonly
known (e.g., 13,37,79) - Unconditional probabilities of each of the true
numbers is commonly known - Each individual knows a fragment of his or her
true number (e.g., 3 or 7 if true number is 37) - Set of fragments known to group members is common
knowledge - Pair of social alternatives x1, x2 is common
knowledge - Individuals known fragment a active fragment
- Individuals unknown fragment l latent fragment
5Model of Deliberation Deliberation Stage
- Individuals simultaneously choose a mode of
deliberative participation ? ? 0,1 - ? 0 speaking (to all members of the group
who are listening) - ? 1 listening (to all members of the group
who are speaking) - Communication from i to j takes place iff i
speaks and j listens - If this is true (?i 0 and ?i 1)
- The message received, mj ai if and only if ai ?
aj lj - Otherwise mj You have received a foreign
fragment. (that is, listener is told they have
received a fragment that is not part of their
true number) - Receiving your latent fragment hearing a
convincing argument of which you were not already
aware - Receiving your active fragment hearing a
convincing argument of which you were already
aware - Receiving a notice of a foreign fragment
hearing an unconvincing argument
6Model of Deliberation Voting Stage
- Once deliberation is complete, individuals vote
for one of x1, x2 - x is the winner by simple majority rule
- Payoffs are assigned ui(x, xi) c - xi - x
7Example 1 Foreign Fragments Can Be Informative
- Commonly known set of true numbers is 13,37,79
- Group members active fragments are 1,3,3
- An individual j with active fragment 3 may have
true number 13 or 37 - Suppose j chooses to listen, and receives notice
of a foreign fragment - This foreign fragment must have come from the
individual with active fragment 1 - 1 must not be part of js true number
- 37 must be js true number
8Example 1a Strategic Incentive to Speak
- Commonly known set of true numbers is 13,37,79
- Group members active fragments are 1,3,3
- Social alternatives in voting stage 13,37
- 37 has higher unconditional probability than 13.
- An individual j with active fragment 3 may have
true number 13 or 37 - This individual will vote for 37 in the absence
of further information - The individual i with active fragment 1 has a
weakly dominant strategy to speak - If those with active fragment 3 speak, decision
is of no consequence - If at least one of those with active fragment 3
listens, speaking may convince listener to vote
for 13 (if message of 1 is received) better
for the speaker. - Speaking can help but cannot hurt
9Example 1b Strategic Incentive not to Speak
- Commonly known set of true numbers is 13,37,79
- Group members active fragments are 1,3,3
- Social alternatives in voting stage 13,37
- 13 has higher unconditional probability than 37.
- An individual j with active fragment 3 may have
true number 13 or 37 - This individual will vote for 13 in the absence
of further information - The individual i with active fragment 1 has a
weakly dominant strategy to listen - If those with active fragment 3 speak, decision
is of no consequence - If at least one of those with active fragment 3
listens, speaking may convince listener to vote
for 37 (if message indicating foreign fragment is
received) worse for the speaker. - Speaking can hurt but cannot help
10Experimental Setup Different Deliberative
Situations
- Distributions of Active Fragments
- ABB (or CCD)
- ABC (or BCD)
- Different probability orderings
- Pr(BCB) gt Pr(ABB)
- Pr(BCB) lt Pr(ABB)
- Agents with A and C active fragments know ex ante
which social alternative they prefer - Agents with B active fragments do not
- A and C agents extremists (one issue-voters,
more extreme ex ante policy preference) B
agents moderates - Speaking Case A and C agents with an incentive
to speak - Listening Case A and C agents with an incentive
to listen
11Experimental Instantiation
- z-tree software at Center for Experimental Social
Science, New York University - Two experimental sessions of 18 subjects each,
web-based recruitment - Each session consisted of 30 periods (period 1
play of entire deliberation game) - Instructions were distributed to subjects and
also read aloud in an effort to induce common
knowledge - Subjects interacted anonymously through computers
and were randomly rematched into new groups each
period - Different values of fragments, probabilities each
period - Exposure to ABB vs ABC, Speaking Case vs
Listening Case, spread throughout experiment - Periods 1-12 inexperienced Periods 13-30
experienced - Sessions lasted 90 minutes, average pay to
subjects US26.56
12Experimental Results I Aggregate Level
Deliberation Data
- Conclusion 1 Extremists Speak More, Moderates
Listen More - Conclusion 2 Extremists Speak More in Speaking
Case than in Listening Case, but barely. In
particular there is far too much over-speaking
in Listening Case. - Conclusion 3 Strategically Irrelevant
Distinctions Dont Matter Between ABB and ABC
Between A and C role in ABC Specific Values of
Fragments or Probabilities
13Experimental Results II Aggregate Level Voting
Data
- Conclusion 4 Subjects Almost Always Use Dominant
Voting Strategies When Receiving their Latent
Fragment or Receiving No Signal - Conclusion 5 But Often Fail to Learn from
Informative Foreign Fragments that Indicate They
Should Vote Against their Prior Belief (Listening
Case-ABB) - Violation of Negative Introspection (Failure to
learn from what does not happen or from what one
does not know)
14Disaggregating by Behavioral Types
- Watsonian
- Violates Negative Introspection. For purposes of
deliberation, imagines that others are also
Watsonians. - Deliberative Prediction Speaks as Extremist in
Listening Case and Speaking Case - Voting Prediction Votes incorrectly as moderate
in Listening Case (ABB) upon receiving foreign
fragment. - Unreflective Bayesian
- Does Not Violate Negative Introspection. But
fails to account for possibility that others may
be negatively introspective. - Deliberative Prediction Speaks as Extremist in
Listening Case and Speaking Case - Voting Prediction Votes correctly as moderate in
Listening Case (ABB) upon receiving foreign
fragment.
15Experimental Results IIIIndividual-Level Data
- Conclusion 6 The bulk of subjects can be
classified as Watsonian/Unreflective Bayesian. - Conclusion 7 At the individual level,
classification in the deliberation stage is
correlated with extent of negative introspection
in the voting stage. - Deliberators classified as Bayesian vote
correctly upon receiving a foreign fragment in
Listening Case (ABB) 100 of time (4/4) - Deliberators classified as Watsonian/Unreflective
Bayesian vote correctly in this situation 57.9
of the time (11/19) - Deliberators classified as Deviant vote
correctly in this situation 28.6 of the time
(2/7)
16Experimental Results IVWatsonians and
Unreflective Bayesians
- Conclusion 8 There is a significant presence of
both Watsonian and Unreflective Bayesian Types - Subjects classified as Watsonian/Unreflective
Bayesian based on deliberative choices vote
correctly 57.9 of the time (11/19) in Listening
Case (ABB) - If they were all Watsonians would be 0
- If they were all UB would be 100.
- Post-experiment questionnaire responses are
broadly consistent with these conclusions - How did you decide when to send vs receive?
- Did your choice of sending vs. receiving vary
depending on circumstances? If so, how? - Did communication often help you decide how to
vote - and if so, how? - Pattern of responses is Bayesian for a small
of subjects is Watsonian for a large of
subjects and is Bayesian with respect to
voting but not deliberative choices for some (UB).
17Alternative Hypothesis
- Everyone is Bayesian, but believes others are a
deviant type that will vote randomly unless they
know both fragments of their true number (in
which case they will vote correctly). - But
- Quiz Questions people understand probability
structure of game - Voting Behavior people vote correctly when
they receive no message - Questionnaire Questions people thought that the
game was easy and believed that others also
found it easy