PHILOSOPHERS - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 133
About This Presentation
Title:

PHILOSOPHERS

Description:

so clothes the grass of the field, which today is, and tomorrow is thrown into the ... Why only one great Designer? ... Hume's 'EVIL DESIGNER' RICHARD DAWKINS ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:170
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 134
Provided by: Cin959
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: PHILOSOPHERS


1
  • .

2
PHILOSOPHERS
3
WHO IS GOD?
4
.
  • What is God?
  • Have you ever wondered whether God exists? Most
    people have.
  • But have you wondered whether Gods existence can
    be proven?
  • Is there evidence, I mean real hard-core
    scientific evidence, that God exists?
  • Are there any good reasons to think that God does
    not exist?
  • How many of you here believe that God exists?
  • How many of you think that Gods existence can be
    proven?

5
(No Transcript)
6
(No Transcript)
7
.
  • The question, "Do we have any good reason to
    think that God does (or does not) exist?", is
    equally important in the Philosophy of Religion.
  • There are four main positions with regard to the
    existence of God that one might take
  • Theism - the belief that God exists.
  • Weak atheism - the lack of belief in any deity.
  • Strong atheism - the belief that no deity
    exists.
  • Agnosticism - the belief that the existence or
    non- .existence of God is not known or cannot
    be known.
  • Most of Philosophy of Religion involves
    determining which of these positions is most
    rational to take. However, this assumes that the
    existence of God can be debated and proved or
    disproved.

8
.
  • The existence of God is a metaphysical question
    central to a branch of philosophy called the
    Philosophy of Religion.
  • As the name implies, this area of philosophy
    applies philosophical methods to the study of a
    wide variety of religious issues, including the
    existence of God.
  • Philosophy of Religion should be distinguished
    from a type of theology called revealed theology.

9
(No Transcript)
10
.
  • Theos is the Greek word for God, so
    Theology literally means the study of God.
  • Revealed Theology is a type of theology that
    claims human knowledge of God comes through
    special revelations such as the Bible or Quran
    or through visions or other types of direct
    revelations from God.
  • St. Thomas Aquinas said that revealed theology
    provides saving knowledge that is, knowledge
    that will result in our salvation.

St. Thomas Aquinas
11
(No Transcript)
12
.
  • Another kind of theology, called Natural
    Theology, has to do with the knowledge of God
    that is possible based on the use of natural
    reason that is, reason unaided by special
    revelations.
  • St. Thomas says that this sort of theology can
    provide us with some knowledge of Gods nature
    and can demonstrate that God exists, but it
    cannot provide saving knowledge because, after
    all, even devils know that God exists.
  • Natural theology is sometimes called rational
    theology or philosophical theology. As this last
    name indicates, this kind of theology is more
    closely related to the Philosophy of Religion
    than is revealed theology.

13
.
  • Both natural theology and the Philosophy of
    Religion they solely on the use of human reason
    in their attempts to discover something about the
    divine.
  • They do not assume the truth of some special
    revelation they allow only what reason can
    prove.
  • Natural Theology has as its professed object to
    vindicate our belief in God, and to deal with the
    manifold objections, which from a wide variety of
    standpoints have been urged either against His
    existence or against His infinite perfections.
  • Sometimes Revealed and Natural Theology overlap
    on issues.

14
.
  • Thomas Aquinas said that if it an issue in which
    there is disagreement between the two, then faith
    (revealed theology) takes precedence over reason
    (natural theology).

15
.
  • One thing it's important to understand is that
    the Philosophy of Religion is far more subtle in
    its study of such arguments than some critics of
    religion suppose.
  • It recognizes that religious beliefs are a
    complex interaction of ideas and to suppose that
    a single argument could ground them all is not
    only unreasonable but contrary to the way in
    which we decide questions in everyday life.
  • Thus the modern justification of belief is
    cumulative and complaining that a particular
    argument fails to make the case for the entire
    network of beliefs is to miss the point.

16
.
  • Indeed, although there is general agreement that
    the five main arguments fail to prove the
    existence of God, some philosophers of religion
    claim that this is not what should be aimed at
    instead, their combination makes it more likely
    than not that God exists.
  • If we were to believe because of arguments, or
    even if we could show that the existence of God
    were certain or rationally justified, there would
    be no room left for faith.

17
.
  • Religious belief is to be taken not as something
    that can be proven or disproven but instead as a
    boundary condition or principle through which we
    interpret life and our experiences.
  • There must be some measure of considering the
    evidence and arguments for and against and
    deciding on the balance of probabilities.
  • It is also suggested that God would not make it
    unreasonable for us to believe in Him, so there
    must be some value in the proofs of His
    existence, whether or not we find them
    convincing.

18
.
  • Recall that Kierkegaard identified subjective
    truths as those things which I believe are true
    for ME.
  • William James noted that truth is what works
    for you.
  • Belief is not objective rationality (or we would
    not call it faith) but belief in the unseen
    (and yet important to us) things shape and give
    meaning to our lives.

19
Theistical Systems
  • The philosophical systems which assert the
    existence of God fall into three classes deism,
    pantheism, and theism.

20
.
Deism teaches that God created the world, but
that having created it, He leaves it to the
guidance of those laws which He established
at its creation, abstaining from further
interference.
  • He acts thus, it holds, both in regard to the
    physical and moral order.
  • There is no such thing as a personal providence
    nor does prayer avail to obtain His special
    assistance.
  • The externality, not to say the remoteness, of
    God in relation to the world is fundamental in
    this system.

21
.
  • Pantheism goes to the other extreme. It denies
    that there is any distinction between God and the
    universe.
  • Nothing exists, it contends, except God.
  • The universe is, in fact, simply the Divine Being
    evolving itself in various forms.
  • By this it means that they deserve a religious
    reverence.

22
.
  • Theism holds a middle position between these.
    Like deism, it maintains the doctrine of
    creation, affirming that finite things are
    fundamentally distinct from their Infinite Maker.
  • But it rejects the teaching which makes God
    remote from the world.
  • It asserts, on the contrary, that God is, and
    must be, ever present to every created thing,
    sustaining it in existence and conferring upon it
    whatever activity it possesses - that "in Him we
    live and move and have are being."
  • And further, Theism says that He exercises a
    special and detailed providence over the whole
    course of things, interfering as He sees fit, and
    guiding all things to their respective ends.

23
"Therefore I say to you, do not worry about your
life, what you will eat or what you will drink
nor about your body, what you will put on. Is not
life more than food and the body more than
clothing?...why do you worry about clothing?
Consider the lilies of the field, how they grow
they neither toil nor spin and yet I say to you
that even Solomon in all his glory was not
arrayed like one of these. Now if God so clothes
the grass of the field, which today is, and
tomorrow is thrown into the oven, will He not
much more clothe you, O you of little faith?
(Matt. 625-30)
24
.
  • Theistic philosophies and religion are not
    exclusively western. The Hindu Brahman is a
    god-figure of sorts, but certainly the ultimate
    reality.
  • NONTHEISTICAL SYSTEMS
  • Nontheistic philosophies, such as Buddhism and
    Taoism are not overtly concerned with the issue
    of Gods existence even though they have been
    concerned with the nature and existence of some
    ultimate reality.
  • Two other forms of nontheistical philosophies are
    agnosticism and atheism.

25
.
  • Agnosticism (from the Greek words, Anot and
    gnosisknowledge) admits to the middle ground of
    uncertainty between a belief in a God or some
    ultimate reality and a rejection of belief in a
    God or some ultimate reality.
  • An agnostics identification means that he
    literally does not know.

26
The ONE THING that an Agnostic DOES KNOW is that
he DOESNT KNOW
27
(No Transcript)
28
PURE AGNOSTICISM
29
LIGHT SUMMER READING FOR AN AGNOSTIC LIVING IN
COLUMBIA, SC DURING AUGUST
30
(No Transcript)
31
.
  • Atheistic philosophies, while claiming not to
    believe in the existence of God, nevertheless
    often spend a great deal of time devising
    rational proofs designed to prove that the
    theistic proofs for the existence of God are
    irrational or at least logically unsupportable.

32
.
Q Who died and made YOU God?
GOD DID !
33
Go to next slide
34
(No Transcript)
35
(No Transcript)
36
(No Transcript)
37
(No Transcript)
38
Agnosticism Atheism Compared
39
HOW CAN I KNOW GOD?
40
(No Transcript)
41
How Can we know God?
  • If He is ineffable or indescribable, then how is
    it that people have sought to give accounts of
    Him within religious texts throughout the years?
  • One answer is to say that we can take a negative
    approach and only say what God is not.
  • To some (like the Jews), God is even too holy to
    be named and perhaps He is beyond human language
    and its limits?
  • Others suggest that God could be known from His
    effects, hence talk of His being all-powerful,
    just, all knowing, as well as the converse of
    these.
  • More recent answers include regarding religious
    texts as a myths, perhaps giving timeless
    insights into the human condition but often
    through the interpretations and context of a
    particular age.
  • But, can we honestly know God and His nature?

42
THE IDEA OF GOD
  • Before the emergence of the belief that the whole
    world is under the sovereign control of a single
    being, people often believed in a plurality of
    divine beings or gods, a religious position
    called polytheism.
  • In ancient Greece and Rome, for example, the
    various gods had control over different aspects
    of life, so that one naturally worshipped several
    gods, a god of war, a goddess of love, and so
    forth.
  • Sometimes, however, one might believe that there
    are a number of gods but worship only one of
    them, the god of ones own tribe, a religious
    position called henotheism.

43
.
  • Monotheism, the belief in only one divine being,
    has passed through a profound change, a change he
    describes with the help of the expressions up
    there and out there.
  • The god up there is a being located in space
    above us, presumably at some definite distance
    from the earth, in a region known as the heavens.
    He is above all and outside of time, space,
    and the limitations of a finite existence.
  • He is a transcendent God, and he does not take
    time to bother with individual matters. He
    controls the world much like an unseen puppeteer
    controls a marionette on the stage.

44
.
  • The fundamental change from the God up there to
    the God out there in the past 800 years is the
    change from thinking of God as located at some
    spatial distance from the earth to thinking of
    God as separate from and independent of the
    world.
  • According to this idea, God has no location in
    some spot or region of physical space.
  • He is a purely spiritual being, a supremely good,
    all-powerful, all-knowing, personal being who has
    created the world, but is not a part of it.
  • He is separate from the world, not subject to its
    laws, and yet he judges it, and guides it to its
    final purpose.
  • He is HERE with the world, but not of the
    world. He is an eminent God.

45
The TRANSCENDENT GOD
46
Transcendent God controls the world from up
there ?
Eminent God controls the world from out there
(here) ?
47
This rather majestic idea of an eminent God
was slowly developed over the centuries
by great western theologians such as
Augustine, Boethius, Bonaventure,
Avicenna, Anselm, Maimonides, and
Aquinas. It has been the dominant idea of
God in western civilization.
Two views of God controlling the world
48
THE ATTRIBUTES OF GOD
  • According to many major theologians, God is
    conceived of as a supremely good being, separate
    from and independent of the world, all-powerful,
    all-knowing, and the creator of the universe.
  • Two other features that were ascribed to God by
    the great theologians are self-existent and
    eternal.
  • The dominant idea of God in western civilization,
    then, is the idea of a supremely good being,
    creator of but separate from and independent of
    the world, all-powerful (omnipotent), all-knowing
    (omniscient), eternal, and self-existent.

49
.
  • What is it for a being to be omnipotent?
  • How are we to understand the idea of
    self-existence?
  • In what way is God thought to be separate from
    and independent of the world?
  • What is meant when it is said that God, and God
    alone, is eternal?
  • Only to the extent that we can answer these and
    similar questions do we comprehend the central
    idea of God to emerge within western
    civilization.
  • Before turning to a study of the question of the
    existence of God, therefore, it is important to
    enrich our grasp of this idea of God by trying to
    answer some of these basic questions.

50
OMNIPOTENCEParadox of the Stone
  • Does God have the power to create a stone so
    heavy that He cannot lift it?
  • Is it possible that he does or does not?

51
.
  • In his great work, the Summa Theologica, St.
    Thomas Aquinas undertakes to explain what it is
    for God to be omnipotent.
  • After pointing out that for God to be omnipotent
    is for God to be able to do all things that are
    possible, Aquinas carefully explains that there
    are two different kinds of possibility, relative
    possibility and absolute possibility, and
    inquires as to which kind of possibility is meant
    when it is said that Gods omnipotence is the
    ability to do all things that are possible.
    Something is a relative possibility when it lies
    within the power of some being or beings to do.
  • Flying by natural means, for example, is possible
    relative to birds but not relative to humans.
  • Something is an absolute possibility, however, if
    it is not a contradiction in terms.

52
.
  • Having explained the two different kinds of
    possibility, Aquinas points out that it must be
    absolute possibility which is meant when Gods
    omnipotence is explained as the ability to do all
    things that are possible. For if we meant
    relative possibility, our explanation would say
    no more than that God is omnipotent means that
    he can do all things that are in his power to do.
    And while it is certainly true that God can do
    all things that are in his power to do, it
    explains nothing. God is omnipotent, then,
    means that God can do whatever does not involve a
    contradiction in terms.
  • Does this mean that there are some things God
    cannot do?
  • In one sense it clearly does mean this. God
    cannot make one and the same thing both round and
    square at the same time.

53
(No Transcript)
54
.
  • The idea that Gods omnipotence does not include
    the power to do something inconsistent with any
    of his basic attributes can help us solve what
    has been called the paradox of the stone.
  • According to this paradox, either God has the
    power to create a stone so heavy that he cannot
    lift it, or God does not have that power.
  • If he does have the power to create such a stone,
    then there is something God cannot do lift the
    stone he can create.
  • On the other hand, if God cannot create such a
    stone, then there is also something he cannot do
    create a stone so heavy he cannot lift it.
  • In either case there is something God cannot do.
    Therefore, God is not omnipotent. But..

55
.
  • The solution to this puzzle is to see that
    creating a stone so heavy that God cannot lift it
    is doing something inconsistent with one of Gods
    essential attributesthe attribute of
    omnipotence.
  • For if there exists a stone so heavy that God
    lacks the power to lift it, then God is not
    omnipotent.
  • Therefore, if God has the power to create such a
    stone, he has the power to bring it about that he
    lacks an attribute (omnipotence) that is
    essential to him.
  • So, the proper solution to the puzzle is to say
    that God cannot create such a stone any more than
    he can do an evil deed.

56
GOODNESSThe Dilemma of Divine Command
  • In Platos Euthyphro, the issue concerning Gods
    goodness and his commands could be expressed in a
    two part question
  • Is something good because God commands it, or
    does God command it because it is good?

57
(No Transcript)
58
.
  • The idea that God (and his commands) must be
    perfectly good is connected to the view that God
    is a being who deserves unconditional gratitude,
    praise, and worship.
  • For if a being were to fall short of perfect
    goodness, it would not be worthy of unreserved
    praise and worship.
  • So, God is not just a good being, his goodness is
    unsurpassable.
  • Moreover, God doesnt simply happen to be
    perfectly good it is his nature to be that way.
  • God logically could not fail to be perfectly
    good. It was for this reason that God does not
    have the power to do evil.
  • To attribute such a power to God is to attribute
    to him the power to cease to be the being that he
    necessarily is.
  • Being God is part of the nature or essence of the
    being who is God. So, since the being who is God
    cannot cease to be God, that being cannot cease
    to be perfectly good.
    Or can he?

59
(No Transcript)
60
.
  • Platos writings were in the form of dialogues,
    usually between Socrates and one or more
    interlocutors.
  • In one of these dialogues, the Euthyphro, there
    is a discussion concerning whether right can be
    defined as that which the gods command.
  • Socrates is skeptical and asks Is conduct right
    because the gods command it, or do the gods
    command it because it is right?
  • It is one of the most famous questions in the
    history of philosophy. The British philosopher
    Antony Flew suggests that one good test of a
    persons aptitude for philosophy is to discover
    whether he can grasp its force and point.

61
.
  • The point is this. If we accept the theological
    conception of right and wrong, we are caught in a
    dilemma. Socrates question asks us to clarify
    what we mean. There are two things we might mean,
    and both lead to trouble.
  • 1. First, we might mean that conduct is right
    because God commands it. For example, in Exodus
    2016, we read that God commands us to be
    truthful. On this option, the reason we should be
    truthful is simply that God requires it. Apart
    from the divine command, truth telling is neither
    good nor bad. It is Gods command that makes
    truthfulness right. But this leads to trouble,
    for it represents Gods commands as arbitrary. It
    means that God could have given different
    commands just as easily.

62
(No Transcript)
63
.
  • He could have commanded us to be liars, and then
    lying, and not truthfulness, would be right. (You
    may be tempted to reply But God would never
    command us to lie! But why not? If he did
    endorse lying, God would not be commanding us to
    do wrong, because his command would make lying
    right.) Remember that on this view, honesty was
    not right before God commanded it.
  • Therefore, he could have had no more reason to
    command it than its opposite and so, from a
    moral point of view, his command is perfectly
    arbitrary.
  • Moreover, on this view, the doctrine of the
    goodness of God is reduced to nonsense.

64
.
  • It is important to religious believers that God
    is not only all-powerful and all-knowing, but
    that he is also good yet if we accept the idea
    that good and bad are defined by reference to
    Gods will, this notion is deprived of any
    meaning. What could it mean to say that Gods
    commands are good? If X is good means X is
    commanded by God, then Gods commands are good
    would mean only Gods commands are commanded by
    God, an empty truism. In his Discourse on
    Metaphysics (1686) Leibniz put the point clearly
  • So in saying that things are not good by any rule
    of goodness, but sheerly by the will of God, it
    seems to me that one destroys, without realizing
    it, all the love of God and all his glory. For
    why praise him for what he has done if he would
    be equally praiseworthy in doing exactly the
    contrary?

65
.
  • If Gods commands could be arbitrary,
  • how can we say that He is GOOD ?

66
.
  • Thus if we choose the first of Socrates two
    options, we are stuck with consequences that even
    the most religious people must find unacceptable.
  • 2. There is a way to avoid these troublesome
    consequences. We can take the second of Socrates
    options. We need not say that right conduct is
    right because God commands it. Instead, we may
    say that God commands right conduct because it is
    right. God, who is infinitely wise, realizes that
    truthfulness is far better than deceitfulness,
    and so he commands us to be truthful he sees
    that killing is wrong, and so he commands us not
    to kill and so on for all the commandments.

67
.
  • If we take this option, we avoid the troublesome
    consequences that plagued the first alternative.
    Gods commands turn out to be not at all
    arbitrary they are the result of his wisdom in
    knowing what is best. And the doctrine of the
    goodness of God is preserved To say that his
    commands are good means that he commands only
    what, in perfect wisdom, he sees to be the best.
    But this option leads to a different problem,
    which is equally troublesome for the theological
    conception of right and wrong In taking this
    option, we have virtually abandoned the
    theological conception of right and wrong.

68
,
  • If God knows some things are good
  • (and also knows some things are evil),
  • we cannot say that He knows the Good
  • because He is Good unless we are
  • also willing to say that He knows the Evil
  • because He is Evil.
  • So the standard of good evil
  • must exist outside of God.

69
(No Transcript)
70
.
  • If we say that God commands us to be truthful
    because truthfulness is right, then we are
    admitting that there is some standard of right
    and wrong that is independent of Gods will. We
    are saying that God sees or recognizes that
    truthfulness is right, and that is very different
    from his making it right. The rightness exists
    prior to and independent of Gods command, and it
    is the reason for the command. Thus if we want to
    know why we should be truthful, the reply
    Because God commands it will not take us very
    far. We may still ask But why does God command
    it? and the answer to that question will provide
    the underlying reasons why truthfulness is a good
    thing.
  • All this may be summarized in the following
    argument

71
(No Transcript)
72
(No Transcript)
73
.
  • Many religious people believe that they must
    accept a theological conception of right and
    wrong because it would be impious not to do so.
    They feel, somehow, that if they believe in God,
    they should think that right and wrong are to be
    defined ultimately in terms of his will. But this
    argument suggests otherwise.
  • It suggests that, on the contrary, the Divine
    Command Theory of right and wrong itself leads to
    impious results, so that a pious person should
    not accept it. And in fact, some of the greatest
    theologians, such as St. Thomas Aquinas (ca.
    12251274), rejected the theory for just this
    reason.

74
.
  • But even if we cannot
  • say that Gods commands
  • are good, can we
  • still say that
  • God is good?

75
WHAT IS THE ARGUMENT?
  • Theologians and philosophers have developed
    arguments for the existence of God, arguments
    which, they have claimed, prove beyond reasonable
    doubt that there is a God.
  • Arguments for the existence of God are commonly
    divided into a posteriori arguments and a priori
    arguments.
  • An a posteriori argument depends on a principle
    or premise that can be known only by means of our
    experience of the world.

76
.
  • An a priori argument, on the other hand, purports
    to rest on principles all of which can be known
    independently of our experience of the world, by
    just reflecting on and understanding them.
  • Of the three major arguments for the existence of
    Godthe Cosmological, the Design, and the
    Ontologicalonly the last of these is entirely a
    priori.
  • In the Cosmological Argument one starts from some
    simple fact about the world, such as that it
    contains things which are caused to exist by
    other things. In the Design Argument a somewhat
    more complicated fact about the world serves as a
    starting point, the fact that the world exhibits
    order and design. In the Ontological Argument,
    however, one begins simply with aconcept of God.

77
Ontological Argument
  • This argument was first propounded by St. Anselm,
    Archbishop of Canterbury in his Proslogion of
    1077-78.
  • Iin the Proslogion Anselm sets out to convince
    "the fool," that is, the person who "has said in
    his heart, There is no God " (Psalm 141 531).

78
.
  • Anselms argument is considered by some that he
    intended it for those who were already theists,
    not necessarily for convincing atheists. This
    distinction is important because his goals for
    the argument tell us how it was supposed to
    function if it was meant for theists, to provide
    a rational basis for already-existing faith and
    hence work as a cumulative argument (as discussed
    above), then we might judge it differently than
    if it was supposed to prove definitively the
    existence of God.
  • Anselm himself wrote
  • I have written the following treatise as ...
    one who seeks to understand what he believes...
  • Given this context, we can now look at the
    argument itself.

79
.
  • In basic form, it states that the definition of
    God entails His existence. For example
  • P1 God is the greatest possible being, one whom
    nothing greater than can be conceived of
  • P2 If God is just a concept and does not exist
    in reality then a greater being can be conceived,
    one that exists both as a concept and in reality
  • C1 This being would be greater than God,
    contradicting P1
  • C2 Therefore, God is not just a concept and must
    exist in reality.

80
.
  • Thus the fact that we define God to be the
    greatest possible being means that He must exist,
    or else He would no longer be the greatest.
  • Another way to understand the argument is to
    distinguish between a necessary being (that is,
    one that necessarily must exist) and a contingent
    one (that is, one that may or may not exist,
    depending on the circumstances).
  • According to the ontological argument, then, it
    would be greater for God to exist as a necessary
    being than as a contingent one.
  • Notice that this argument depends only on the
    definition, not any facts about the world. It is
    perhaps for this reason that many people find it
    unsatisfactory at first glance.
  • Does the notion of a "greatest possible being"
    make sense?

81
(No Transcript)
82
Lets do the argument again
  • In presenting Anselms argument again, I shall
    use the term God in place of the longer phrase
    the being than which none greater is
    possiblewherever the term God appears we are to
    think of it as simply an abbreviation of the
    longer phrase.
  • God exists in the understanding.As weve noted,
    anyone who hears of the being than which none
    greater is possible is, in Anselms view,
    committed to premise 1.
  • God might have existed in reality (God is a
    possible being).Anselm, I think, assumes the
    truth of premise 2 without making it explicit in
    his reasoning.
  • If something exists only in the understanding and
    might have existed in reality, then it might have
    been greater than it is.Statement 3 is the key
    idea in Anselms Ontological Argument. It is
    intended as a general principle true of anything.
    Steps 13 constitute the basic premises of
    Anselms Ontological Argument.

83
.
  • From these three items it follows, so Anselm
    believes, that God exists in reality.
  • But how does Anselm propose to convince us that
    if we accept 13 we are committed by the rules of
    logic to accept his conclusion that God exists in
    reality?
  • Anselms procedure is to offer what is called a
    reductio ad absurdum proof of his conclusion.
    Instead of showing directly that the existence of
    God follows from13, Anselm invites us to suppose
    that God does not exist (that is, that the
    conclusion he wants to establish is false).
  • Then he shows how this supposition when conjoined
    with 13 leads to an absurd result, a result that
    couldnt possibly be true because it is
    contradictory.

84
,
  • In short, with the help of 13 Anselm shows that
    the supposition that God does not exist reduces
    to an absurdity.
  • Since the supposition that God does not exist
    leads to an absurdity, that supposition must be
    rejected in favor of the conclusion that God does
    exist.
  • Does Anselm succeed in reducing the fools belief
    that God does not exist to an absurdity?
  • The best way to answer this question is to follow
    the steps of his argument.

85
(No Transcript)
86
.
  • 4. Suppose God exists only in the
    understanding.This supposition, as we saw
    earlier, is Anselms way of expressing the fools
    belief that God does not exist.
  • 5. God might have been greater than he is. (2, 4,
    and 3)6Step 5 follows from steps 2, 4, and 3.
    Since 3, if true, is true of anything, it will be
    true of God. Step 3, therefore, implies that if
    God exists only in the understanding and might
    have existed in reality, then God might have been
    greater than he is. If so, then given 2 and 4, 5
    must be true. For what 3 says when applied to God
    is that given 2 and 4 it follows that 5.
  • 6. God is a being than which a greater is
    possible. (5)Surely if God is such that he
    logically might have been greater, then he is
    such than which a greater is possible.

87
.
  • Were now in a position to appreciate Anselms
    reductio argument. He has shown us that if we
    accept 14 we must accept 6. But 6 is
    unacceptable it is the absurdity Anselm was
    after. For replacing God in step 6 with the
    longer phrase it abbreviates, we see that 6
    amounts to the absurd assertion
  • 7. The being than which none greater is possible
    is a being than which a greater is possible.Now
    since 14 have led us to an obviously false
    conclusion, if we accept Anselms basic premises
    13 as true, 4, the supposition that God exists
    only in the understanding, must be rejected as
    false. Thus we have shown that
  • 8. It is false that God exists only in the
    understanding.But since premise 1 tells us that
    God does exist in the understanding, and 8 tells
    us that God does not exist only there, we may
    infer that
  • 9. God exists in reality as well as in the
    understanding. (1, 8)

88
(No Transcript)
89
.
  • Defending critics of Anselms argument
  • Try to think, for example, of a hockey player
    than which none greater is possible.
  • How fast would he have to skate?
  • How many goals would such a player have to score
    in a game?
  • How fast would he have to shoot the puck?
  • Could this player ever fall down, be checked, or
    receive a penalty?

90
.
  • Although the phrase The hockey player than which
    none greater is possible seems meaningful, as
    soon as we try to get a clear idea of what such a
    being would be like, we discover that we cant
    form a coherent idea of it at all. For we are
    being invited to think of some limited, finite
    thinga hockey player or an islandand then to
    think of it as exhibiting unlimited, infinite
    perfections.
  • Perhaps, then, since Anselms reasoning applies
    only to possible things, Anselm can reject its
    application to his critics hockey player on the
    grounds that the hockey player and than which
    none greater is possible is, like the round
    square, an impossible thing.

91
Cosmological Argument
  • According to Plato in his dialogue the Timaeus,
    ...everything that comes to be or changes must
    do so owing to some cause for nothing can come
    to be without a cause.
  • Historically, the cosmological argument can be
    traced to the writings of the Greek philosophers,
    Plato and Aristotle, but the major developments
    in the argument took place in the thirteenth and
    in the eighteenth centuries.
  • In the thirteenth century St. Thomas Aquinas put
    forth five distinct arguments for the existence
    of God, and of these, the first three are
    versions of the Cosmological Argument.

92
.
  • The Cosmological Argument has two parts.
  • In the first part the effort is to prove the
    existence of a special sort of being, for
    example, a being that could not have failed to
    exist, or a being that causes change in other
    things but is itself unchanging.
  • In the second part of the argument the effort is
    to prove that the special sort of being whose
    existence has been established in the first part
    has, and must have, the featuresperfect
    goodness, omnipotence, omniscience, and so
    onwhich go together to make up the theistic idea
    of God.
  • What this means, then, is that Aquinas first
    three arguments (of five) are different versions
    of only the first part of the Cosmological
    Argument.

93
St. Thomas Aquinas' FIVE WAYS
  • Background
  • St. Thomas Aquinas (1224-1274) was a Dominican
    priest, theologian, and philosopher. Called the
    Doctor Angelicus (the Angelic Doctor,) Aquinas is
    considered one the greatest Christian
    philosophers to have ever lived. Two of his most
    famous works, the Summa Theologiae and the Summa
    Contra Gentiles, are the finest examples of his
    work on Christian philosophy.

94
(No Transcript)
95
First Way (Cosmological)Argument From Motion
  • St. Thomas Aquinas, studying the works of the
    Greek philosopher Aristotle, concluded from
    common observation that an object that is in
    motion (e.g. the planets, a rolling stone) is put
    in motion by some other object or force.
  • From this, Aquinas believes that ultimately there
    must have been an UNMOVED MOVER (GOD) who first
    put things in motion.

96
.
  • Follow the argument this way
  • P1 Everything that moves is moved by something
    else
  • P2 An infinite regress (that is, going back
    through a chain of movers forever) is impossible
  • C Therefore, there must exist a first mover
    (i.e. God).

97
Second Way (Cosmological)Causation Of Existence
  • This way deals with the issue of existence.
    Aquinas concluded that common sense observation
    tells us that no object creates itself. In other
    words, some previous object had to create it.
    Aquinas believed that ultimately there must have
    been an UNCAUSED FIRST CAUSE (GOD) who began the
    chain of existence for all things.
  • The second cosmological argument proceeds
    similarly.

98
.
  • Follow the argument this way
  • 1) There exists things that are caused (created)
    by other things.
  • 2) Nothing can be the cause of itself (nothing
    can create itself.)
  • 3) There can not be an endless string of objects
    causing other objects to exist.
  • 4) Therefore, there must be an uncaused first
    cause called God.

99
(No Transcript)
100
.
  • The first two cosmological arguments seem much
    the same but the slight distinction is that the
    first focuses on the fact that things are moved
    by agents acting in the world while the second
    discusses the actors causing these things to
    happen.
  • Several criticisms have been made of Aquinas'
    assumptions. Philosophers have challenged the
    idea that events are linked in a "chain" from one
    to the next, each resting, as it were, on those
    below. Another telling objection is to ask why
    there could not be more than one first
    cause/mover? Why could the chain not lead back to
    several ultimate causes, each somehow outside the
    universe? Not only that, but these two arguments
    could just as easily lead to two different Gods.
  • Aquinas offers a third argument.

101
Third Way (Cosmological) Contingent and
Necessary Objects
  • This way defines two types of objects in the
    universe contingent beings and necessary beings.
  • A contingent being is an object that cannot exist
    without a necessary being causing its existence.
  • Aquinas believed that the existence of contingent
    beings would ultimately necessitate a being which
    must exist for all of the contingent beings to
    exist.
  • This being, called a necessary being, is what we
    call God.

102
.
  • Follow the argument this way
  • 1) Contingent beings are caused.
  • 2) Not every being can be contingent.
  • 3) If a contingent being exists, then there must
    exist a being which is necessary to cause
    contingent beings.
  • 4) This necessary being is God.

103
.
  • The idea here is that if everything in the
    universe was contingent then there must have been
    some time when there were no contingent beings at
    all. In that case, how could the universe have
    come into being, since contingent beings would
    require a cause? This means that there must be
    some necessary being, which we take to be God.
  • The problem again is that Aquinas third argument
    might be taken to imply another God, different
    from the other two. Others object that matter or
    energy are not contingent (although still others
    question this assumption), or that the
    contingency could run backwards in time as far as
    we like and "end" in the future.

104
(No Transcript)
105
.
  • Final Comment on the Cosmological Argument
  • As with the ontological argument, the
    cosmological argument does not appear to be
    intended to convince non-theists that they should
    become theists but instead suggests the existence
    of God as a possibility, or an explanation of the
    brute fact of the existence of the universe.
  • How convincing it is depends, apart from the
    opinions we might hold of the content of the
    argument, on whether we feel this fact is in need
    of explanation or not.

106
Fourth Way The Argument From Degrees And
Perfection
  • St. Thomas Aquinas formulated this Way from a
    very interesting observation about the qualities
    of things. For example one may say that of two
    marble sculptures one is more beautiful than the
    other. So for these two objects, one has a
    greater degree of beauty than the next. This is
    referred to as degrees or gradation of a quality.
  • From this fact Aquinas concluded that for any
    given quality (e.g. goodness, beauty, knowledge)
    there must be a perfect standard by which all
    such qualities are measured. These perfections
    are contained in God.

107
Fifth Way (Teleological) Argument From
Intelligent Design
  • The final Way that St. Thomas Aquinas speaks of
    has to do with the observable universe and the
    order of nature.
  • Aquinas states that common sense tells us that
    the universe works in such a way, that one can
    conclude that is was designed by an intelligent
    designer, God.
  • In other words, all physical laws and the order
    of nature and life were designed and ordered by
    God, the intelligent designer.

108
.
  • The Teleological Argument points to the existence
    of purpose and order in the universe and supposes
    that if we see signs of design then there must
    have been a designer.
  • Indeed, the word "teleology" comes from the Greek
    telos, meaning "purpose", "goal", or "end."
  • Sometimes it is called the argument from design,
    or more properly the argument for design.
  • A more complete explanation of St. Thomas' Fifth
    Way about God as Intelligent Designer can be
    understood by examining William Paley's
    Teleological Argument.

109
(No Transcript)
110
.
  • The basic premise, of all teleological arguments
    for the existence of God, is that the world
    exhibits an intelligent purpose based on
    experience from nature such as its order, unity,
    coherency, design, and complexity.
  • Hence, there must be an intelligent designer to
    account for the observed intelligent purpose and
    order that we can observe.

111
.
2. Paley's teleological argument is based on an
analogy. Watchmaker is to watch as God is to
universe. Just as a watch, with its
intelligent design and complex function must
have been created by an intelligent maker.
  • A watchmaker, the universe, with all its
    complexity and greatness, must have been created
    by an intelligent and powerful creator.
  • Therefore a watchmaker is to watch as God is to
    universe.

112
.
WILLIAM PALEY AND HIS WATCH.
  • If you tripped over a watch you would assume
    (after examining it) that it had been put
    together by a clever watchmaker. 
  • Is it not reasonable to assume the same about the
    world?
  • You could say the same about an eye.
  • Except its maker is a lot cleverer  than the
    watchmaker.

113
.
  • Paley's Teleological Argument
  • 1) Human artifacts are products of intelligent
    design.
  • 2) The universe resembles human artifacts.
  • 3) Therefore the universe is a product of
    intelligent design.
  • 4) But the universe is complex and gigantic, in
    comparison to human artifacts.
  • 5) Therefore, there probably is a powerful and
    vastly intelligent designer who created the
    universe.

114
Design Argument we may disagree about WHO is in
charge, but somebody must be!
115
CRITICISMS
  • HUME - It depends what you look at in the world.
    What if you focus on suffering and disease. Does
    this suggest a designer? An incompetent designer
    or an evil designer?
  • Why only one great Designer? Hume suggests there
    could be several so not God, in the usual sense
    of God.
  • J S MILL - Nature is guilty of many serious
    crimes. If people committed crimes like these
    (earthquakes etc) they would be punished. Mill
    suggests that it is wrong to think of the world
    as being ordered or designed.

116
Humes EVIL DESIGNER
117
.
  • RICHARD DAWKINS - Modern Darwinian biologist. In
    his famous book The Selfish Gene (1989), he
    suggests that human beings and other animals
    exists as gene carriers (and not because theyre
    important in themselves). The human body is a
    gene survival suit. There is no order or design
    there is no God.
  • CHARLES DARWIN - Darwin was famous for
    formulating the theory of evolution. Darwin
    said that, what looks like order, has come about
    as a result of a random process. Animals just
    keep adapting to the things that happen
    (accidentally) in their environments. What looks
    like order is just adaptation.

118
(No Transcript)
119
.
  • Hume
  • An incompetent designer
  • Mill
  • An unordered world
  • Dawkins
  • Gene survival No God
  • Darwin
  • Adaptation No God

120
(No Transcript)
121
After years of trying to create life in the
laboratory, the scientists finally concede that
God did a better job than they every could.
122
.
  • The success of evolutionary theory has also
    provided an alternative explanation as to where
    the order we see has come from, with the caveat
    that there is apparently no need to invoke
    purposive behavior to account for it. This is not
    necessarily an objection against design, however,
    since many theists now suggest that evolution is
    the means used by God to achieve His goals.
  • With developments in science continually
    suggesting new angles to view the argument from,
    as well as refinements that point to the amount
    of beauty in the universe as opposed to just
    design, the teleological argument rumbles on and
    it perhaps once again depends on the perspective
    from which it is viewed.

123
The Religious Experience Argument
  • Perhaps the most interesting argument for the
    existence of God comes from the fact that very
    many people have experiences they characterize as
    religious.
  • These tend to have different forms, but there is
    enough common ground to list a few of them that
    have been distilled as a result of work by people
    like William James and David Hay.

124
.
  • Some common descriptions include
  • - The experience is hard (if not impossible) to
    describe.
  • - It is a feeling of oneness with God.
  • - It can also be a sense of being dependent on
    God.
  • - It may sometimes call attention to a painful
    separation from God.
  • - It can be experienced anywhere, in everyday
    situations.
  • - It can provide insight into otherwise
    inaccessible truths.
  • - The experience tends to be transient.
  • There are other descriptions, of course, and the
    experience itself seems to be largely personal.

125
.
  • The issue, then, is to explain these religious
    experiences in a satisfactory way. The religious
    experience argument, again, does not seek to
    prove that God exists but instead that it is
    reasonable to believe that He does because of the
    direct experience of Him.
  • Moreover, the argument gives a motive for
    non-believers to also believe unless they can
    explain the experiences (which they may have for
    themselves) in another way. Indeed, we could say
    the argument is an inference to the best
    explanation
  • P1 People have religious experiencesP2 The
    existence of God explains these experiencesC
    Therefore, God exists.

126
.
  • In summary, the argument from religious
    experience does not prove existence definitively
    and depends in good measure on what our prior
    opinions of such experiences are.
  • Nevertheless, it provides an explanation for a
    widespread phenomenon.

127
Other Types of Argument
  • There are other types of arguments used to prove
    the existence of God.
  • One commonly occurring one (used by Kant as well
    as others) is the Moral Argument.
  • In its simplest form, it says that without God,
    there would be no morality. Since human beings
    have some internal sense of morality, there must
    be a God who not only created the world but also
    instilled within human beings a sense of right
    and wrong.

128
.
  • Another common argument is the Free Will
    Argument, which is designed to fly in the face of
    the notion of an uncreated universe that still
    (for some reason) has laws (such as cause and
    effect).

129
.
  • P1 Every event is derived from a cause
    determined by universal laws.
  • P2. Human actions are undetermined.
  • P3 Undetermined actions do no follow universal
    laws and thus must be the result of free will.
  • P4 But if every event has a cause, then even
    undetermined events (resulting from free will)
    must have a cause.
  • P4 The cause of free will must also (by analogy)
    be the cause of the universal laws.
  • C Therefore God, the cause of the universal
    laws, must exist as the cause of free will.
  • Personally, I dont think it is a very convincing
    argument.

130
God smites those who do not obey Him, because
they use their free will badly.
On the other hand (or maybe with the same hand),
the Bible says that the Lord disciplines those
He loves (Hebrews 126).
131
.
  • For thought and discussion
  • If there is only one God whose existence is being
    proven in all these arguments, why is it that
    there is a plurality of religions?
  • If people can agree that God exists, then are all
    religions equally good in their approaches to
    God?
  • Well discuss that after we read the handout.

132
(No Transcript)
133
(No Transcript)
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com