Lesson Six - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 23
About This Presentation
Title:

Lesson Six

Description:

The dividing parts must be inferior, that is, less universal, than the whole being divided. ... is the division of an integral whole into its component parts. ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:18
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 24
Provided by: kathleen112
Category:
Tags: lesson | six | whole

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: Lesson Six


1
Lesson Six
  • Division
  • Part I, L. 6

2
Introduction
  • In general, division is the distribution of
    something into its parts. It helps us to know a
    thing, because when we divide a thing into its
    parts, we can know that thing better and more
    distinctly.
  • When we studied signs, we divided them into
    natural, conventional, and formal, enabling us to
    better understand what a sign is by knowing its
    parts in detail.

3
  • Making an outline is an example of dividing
    something in order to better understand it. If
    we can make a good outline, we can be fairly sure
    we understand the subject thoroughly. This is
    why outlining is a useful skill in studying,
    since it helps us see the logical order between
    the principal points as well as the relation
    between them and their relative importance.

4
  • The purpose of division in Logic is to enable us
    to define well. It is necessary to divide in
    order to define well, because by dividing a genus
    adequately into its species, we achieve clearer
    knowledge of the species. We seek to define a
    species, or nature, as we will see shortly.

5
The Rules of Division
  • Division, like nearly every other sort of
    activity, can be done well or badly. To achieve
    its goal in Logic, it must obviously be done
    correctly, as it seems extremely unlikely that we
    will arrive at knowledge by mistake. We can
    summarize the requirements for good division in
    the form of rules that can be used to evaluate
    whether any division is good or bad.

6
Rule 1
  • The dividing parts must be inferior, that is,
    less universal, than the whole being divided.
  • Obviously, if we are dividing something, each
    member of the division must be less universal
    than what is being divided. The thing divided
    should be a universal, since that is what Logic
    deals with, as opposed to a merely physical
    division such as cutting a cake into pieces.

7
  • Therefore, the members of a division must be less
    universal. They cannot be singulars, either,
    because we differentiate between singulars by
    counting them, not by division.
  • For example, we can divide tree into its species
    oak, mahogany, maple, apple, pine, cedar, etc.
    Both the thing divided (tree) and the members of
    the division are universals.

8
Rule 2
  • 2. The dividing parts must exhaust the species.
  • For a division to be a good one, it must
    adequately and completely divide the species.
    There must be nothing which belongs to the
    species as a whole which does not fall under one
    of the parts.

9
  • For example, when we divide Predicables into
    genus, species, specific difference, property,
    and accident, we have complied with this rule,
    since there are no other possible connections
    between a subject and a predicate other than
    these five. If we were to divide Predicable into
    genus and species, we would not have an
    exhaustive division, because something would have
    been left out.

10
  • As a consequence of this Rule, we realize that
    there must be at least two members of every
    division. Otherwise it will not be a division at
    all, as every whole must contain at least two
    parts.

11
Rule 3
  • The dividing parts must be formally opposed, such
    that one part excludes all others.
  • It must be impossible for anything belonging to
    the species to fall under two or more dividing
    parts, for then the division will not serve to
    distinguish them. We can assure this by ensuring
    that there is opposition of some kind between the
    parts.

12
  • We can divide using contradictory opposition, as
    when we divide Religions into Christian and
    non-Christian. This is the easiest and surest
    way to comply with Rule 3, as there can be no
    doubt that the parts exclude each other. It is
    also exhaustive, as there are only two members of
    the division. Yet this kind of division is often
    not very useful.

13
  • We can divide using privative opposition, as when
    we divide human beings into sighted and blind.
  • We can divide by contrary opposition, as when we
    divide numbers into odd and even. This differs
    from division using privative opposition, because
    each of the members has a positive existence in
    the same way, unlike privative opposition, where
    one has a positive existence and the other a
    negative existence (the lack of something that
    ought to be present.)

14
  • And we can divide using relative opposition
    between the parts in various ways, either by
    using parts which have a mutual reference to each
    other, as when we divide family into parents and
    children, or parts which differ merely formally
    within their genus, as when we divide flowers
    into roses, lilies, and daisies.

15
Rule 4
  • The same criterion of division must be maintained
    throughout the division.
  • The criterion of a division is the basis or
    viewpoint used to make the division. For
    example, we can divide human beings according to
    nationality into French, Swedish, German,
    Spanish, Egyptian, Russian, Japanese, etc. But
    we cannot suddenly begin to divide them as
    right-handed and left-handed halfway through,
    which would be to change the criterion of
    division from nationality to handedness.

16
  • This Rule does not prevent us from dividing
    something exhaustively using one criterion and
    then dividing the same thing using another. This
    is called co-division. Either way of dividing
    human beings is perfectly acceptable as long as
    we dont confuse them.

17
  • Another legitimate procedure is known as
    sub-division, which is dividing a whole according
    to one criterion, then dividing one or more of
    the parts according to another. This is a
    division made under another division, or a
    division subordinate to the original one. For
    example, we divided things into ten Categories,
    and proceeded to divide some of the Categories
    according to other criteria.

18
The Kinds of Division
  • The different kinds of division result from the
    different kinds of wholes and parts.
  • The first kind is the division of a universal
    whole into its subjective parts. In this type of
    division, the whole is predicable of each of its
    parts. This is the most basic type of logical
    division.

19
  • For example, we can divide animal into rational
    and non-rational. This is the division of a
    genus into its species using essential
    differences.

20
  • The second kind of division is the division of an
    integral whole into its component parts. In this
    kind of division we divide into parts which,
    taken together, constitute the whole. The parts
    do not share a common nature, but rather make up
    the whole.
  • For example, we can divide families into parents,
    children, aunts and uncles, grandparents, etc.
    It is not possible to predicate the whole of the
    parts (we cannot say that the parents are a
    family).

21
  • Finally, we can divide accidentally in at least
    three ways.
  • First, we can divide a subject according to its
    accidents, for example, as when we divide human
    beings into right-handed and left-handed, or into
    black, white, yellow, red, etc.

22
  • Second, we can divide an accident according to
    its subject, which is the reverse of the previous
    type. For example, we can divide the sense of
    sight according to whether it is found in human
    beings, dogs, cats, bulls, flies, etc.

23
  • Lastly, we can divide an accident according to
    its accidents. For example, the policeman
    divides the accident of velocity according to
    quantity, another accident, for the purpose of
    giving speeding tickets.
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com